Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Heidegger's Theory of Truth and its Importance for the Quality of Qualitative Research.Rauno Huttunen & Leena Kakkori - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (3):600-616.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education When reliability and validity were introduced as validation criteria for empirical research in the human sciences, quantitative research methods prevailed, and theory of science relied on neopositivism (Vienna Circle) or postpositivism (scientific realism). Within this worldview, notions of reliability and validity as criteria of scientific goodness were introduced. Reliability and validity were associated with the correspondence theory of truth, which is mostly ill-suited to the needs of qualitative research. For that reason, qualitative research must look (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger and the genesis of social ontology: Mitwelt, Mitsein, and the problem of other people.Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (3):723-739.
    This article traces the development of how the early Heidegger tried to integrate the structures of social life into phenomenological ontology. Firstly, I argue that Heidegger's analysis of the three elements of the lifeworld—the with-world (Mitwelt), the environing world (Umwelt), and the self-world (Selbstwelt)—is ambiguous, because it shifts between defining sociality as a domain of entities and a mode of appearance. This is untenable because the social as a mode of appearance constantly overflows the definition as a domain by implicating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Platonism in Lotze and Frege Between Psyschologism and Hypostasis.Nicholas Stang - 2018 - In Sandra Lapointe (ed.), Logic from Kant to Russell. New York: Routledge. pp. 138–159.
    In the section “Validity and Existence in Logik, Book III,” I explain Lotze’s famous distinction between existence and validity in Book III of Logik. In the following section, “Lotze’s Platonism,” I put this famous distinction in the context of Lotze’s attempt to distinguish his own position from hypostatic Platonism and consider one way of drawing the distinction: the hypostatic Platonist accepts that there are propositions, whereas Lotze rejects this. In the section “Two Perspectives on Frege’s Platonism,” I argue that this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl on Communication and Knowledge Sharing in the Logical Investigations and a 1931 Manuscript.Michele Averchi - 2018 - Husserl Studies 34 (3):209-228.
    In the Logical Investigations, Husserl argues that “sign” is an ambiguous word because it refers to two essentially different signitive functions: indication and expression. Indications work in an evidential way, providing information through a direct association of the sign and the presence of an object or state of affairs. Expressions work in a non-evidential way, pointing to possible experiences and displaying that the speaker or someone else has had such experience. In this paper I show that Husserl went back to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Affectivity in Heidegger II: Temporality, Boredom, and Beyond.Lauren Freeman & Andreas Elpidorou - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (10):672-684.
    In ‘Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time’, we explicated the crucial role that Martin Heidegger assigns to our capacity to affectively find ourselves in the world. There, our discussion was restricted to Division I of Being and Time. Specifically, we discussed how Befindlichkeit as a basic existential and moods as the ontic counterparts of Befindlichkeit make circumspective engagement with the world possible. Indeed, according to Heidegger, it is primarily through moods that the world is ‘opened (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time.Andreas Elpidorou & Lauren Freeman - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (10):661-671.
    This essay provides an analysis of the role of affectivity in Martin Heidegger's writings from the mid to late 1920s. We begin by situating his account of mood within the context of his project of fundamental ontology in Being and Time. We then discuss the role of Befindlichkeit and Stimmung in his account of human existence, explicate the relationship between the former and the latter, and consider the ways in which the former discloses the world. To give a more vivid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Continental Philosophy of Science.Babette Babich - 2007 - In Constantin V. Boundas (ed.), The Edinburgh Companion to the Twentieth Century Philosophies. Edinburgh. University of Edinburgh Press. pp. 545--558.
    Continental philosophies of science tend to exemplify holistic themes connecting order and contingency, questions and answers, writers and readers, speakers and hearers. Such philosophies of science also tend to feature a fundamental emphasis on the historical and cultural situatedness of discourse as significant; relevance of mutual attunement of speaker and hearer; necessity of pre-linguistic cognition based in human engagement with a common socio-cultural historical world; role of narrative and metaphor as explanatory; sustained emphasis on understanding questioning; truth seen as horizonal, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger’s Relative Essentialism.Timothy J. Nulty - 2022 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 53 (1):40-60.
    There is relatively little comprehensive treatment of Heidegger’s theory of essences despite his ubiquitous use of essences. It is commonplace in contemporary analytic philosophy to view essences as the ground for true de re modal claims. I argue that Heidegger offers an account of essences that can best be understood as a type of relative essentialism. Relative essentialism is the view that more than one being can occupy the same space at the same time and those beings have distinct sets (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heidegger and the contradiction of Being: a dialetheic interpretation of the late Heidegger.Filippo Casati - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (5):1002-1024.
    ABSTRACTIt is well known that, from the beginning to the end of his philosophical trajectory, Martin Heidegger tries to develop a fundamental ontology which aims at answering the so-called question...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Why Tugendhat's critique of Heidegger's concept of truth remains a critical problem.William H. Smith - 2007 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (2):156 – 179.
    With what right and with what meaning does Heidegger use the term 'truth' to characterize Dasein's disclosedness? This is the question at the focal point of Ernst Tugendhat's long-standing critique of Heidegger's understanding of truth, one to which he finds no answer in Heidegger's treatment of truth in §44 of Being and Time or his later work. To put the question differently: insofar as unconcealment or disclosedness is normally understood as the condition for the possibility of propositional truth rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Thinking, meaning, and truth: Arendt on Heidegger and the possibility of critique.Jennifer Gaffney - 2024 - Constellations 31 (1):3-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Re‐thinking Truth: Assessing Heidegger's critique of Aquinas in light of Vallicella's critique of Heidegger.Jonathan Lyonhart - 2020 - New Blackfriars 103 (1105):326-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a Resolute Reading of Being and Time: Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and the Dilemma between Inconsistency and Ineffability.Gilad Nir - 2021 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):572-605.
    Both Heidegger and Wittgenstein consider the possibility of a philosophical inquiry of an absolutely universal scope—an inquiry into the being of all beings, in Heidegger’s case, and into the logical form of everything that can be meaningfully said, in Wittgenstein’s. Moreover, they both raise the worry that the theoretical language by means of which we speak of particular beings and assert particular facts is not suited to this task. And yet their own philosophical work seems to include many assertions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Editorial introduction.Damian Veal - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (1):1 – 31.
    The project behind this and the following1 special issue of Angelaki first assumed concrete form in the shape of a three-day international conference, “Continental Philosophy and the Sciences,” hel...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pippin's The Culmination, ‘logic as metaphysics’, and the unintelligibility of Dasein.Denis McManus - forthcoming - European Journal of Philosophy.
    April 15, 2024: This article published in Early View in error. The article will republish shortly.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pippin's The Culmination, Heidegger's Question, and Hegel's Revenge.Denis McManus - forthcoming - Hegel Bulletin:1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dasein and World: Heidegger’s Reconceiving of the Transcendental After Husserl.Niall Keane - 2020 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (3):265-287.
    The following examines Heidegger’s analysis of world and Dasein from a transcendental perspective. It is argued that Heidegger’s reflections on the interconnected themes of world and Dasein reveal the tensions that exist between the transcendental claims before and after Being and Time and the analysis of worldliness. It begins by looking at Heidegger’s early analysis of Husserl’s critique of psychologism and naturalism, assessing what this tells us about Heidegger’s analysis of world and nature. It subsequently addresses Heidegger’s transformation of Husserlian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The recent engagement between analytic philosophy and Heideggerian thought: Logic and language.Filippo Casati - 2020 - Philosophy Compass 15 (2):e12651.
    Martin Heidegger's philosophy is famous for being unusually rich. It ranges over technology, poetry, theology, history, and many other subjects. In this paper, I focus my attention on two topics which are particularly close to the hearts of analytic philosophers: logic and language. I show that Heidegger faces two different kinds of paradoxes: an ontic paradox and an ontological paradox. Moreover, for each one of these paradoxes, I give an overview of how both Heidegger and the philosophers who engage with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tugendhat's Idea of Truth.Christian Skirke - 2016 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (4):831-854.
    This paper argues that Tugendhat's critique of Heidegger's existential conception of truth as disclosedness is usually misunderstood. The main claim of this paper is that Tugendhat insists against Heidegger on certain conventional features of truth such as conformity of the law of non-contradiction, not because he adheres to an ideal of truth as correctness; rather, he proposes an alternative existential conception of truth in terms of an active, critical or self-critical, engagement with untruth. Various recent objections to Tugendhat's critique of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reading Logos as Speech: Heidegger, Aristotle and Rhetorical Politics.Stuart Elden - 2005 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 38 (4):281-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The state of the question in early Heidegger studies.William Blattner - forthcoming - Southern Journal of Philosophy.
    This article surveys the state of the literature in English‐language scholarship on Heidegger's early work (1919–29). The survey falls into roughly two halves. The first is devoted to scholarship on Heidegger's intellectual development during the 1920s, focusing on four themes: Heidegger's relationship to Husserl; Heidegger's early phenomenology of religious life; Heidegger's appropriation of Aristotle; and Heidegger's retrieval of Kant's First Critique. The second half focuses on work on the early Heidegger that has arisen out of the reception of his early (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negentropy for the anthropocene; Stiegler, Maori and exosomatic memory.Ruth Irwin & Te Haumoana White - 2022 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 54 (5):532-544.
    Exosomatic memory is a crucial phase in the evolution of humanity because it enables learning to take place across groups and generations rather than exclusively through lived experience or one on one transmission. Exosomatic memory is the attribution of knowledge to objects, such as art or writing, which allows epistemology to be transmitted beyond the individual to subsequent generations of people. Exosomatic memory is the key to the transmission of culture and knowledge, beyond the individual who learns exclusively from personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a Critical Philosophy of Science: Continental Beginnings and Bugbears, Whigs, and Waterbears.Babette Babich - 2010 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 24 (4):343-391.
    Continental philosophy of science has developed alongside mainstream analytic philosophy of science. But where continental approaches are inclusive, analytic philosophies of science are not–excluding not merely Nietzsche’s philosophy of science but Gödel’s philosophy of physics. As a radicalization of Kant, Nietzsche’s critical philosophy of science puts science in question and Nietzsche’s critique of the methodological foundations of classical philology bears on science, particularly evolution as well as style (in art and science). In addition to the critical (in Mach, Nietzsche, Heidegger (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Being-in-the-World Reconsidered: Thinking Beyond Absorbed Coping and Detached Rationality.Karl Leidlmair - 2020 - Human Studies 43 (1):23-36.
    Recently, a revival of phenomenological approaches has been gaining ground in the literature of cognition and human understanding. Heidegger’s Being-in-the-World plays a decisive role here. Instead of viewing the mind as an independent entity separated from the “outer” world, these approaches assert an immediate understanding of a meaningful environment. Such an immediate understanding is seen in the light of embodied practices, when humans are engaged in skillful absorbed coping. An analysis of Heidegger’s concept of truth provides a more sophisticated view. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger on Being Self-Concealing.Leslie Macavoy - forthcoming - Mind:fzad022.
    Often we frame our learning about or discovery of things and indeed the very existence of those things in terms of unconcealment, as when we say that something.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger’s Concept of Truth Reconsidered in Light of Tugendhat’s Critique.Gracie Holliday Beck - 2018 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 49 (2):91-108.
    Ernst Tugendhat’s critique of Martin Heidegger’s conception of truth is an ongoing topic in Heideggerian scholarship. In this paper, I contribute to the ongoing exchange between defenders of Heidegger and those who are in agreement with Tugendhat. Specifically, I contend that Tugendhat’s criticisms fail to situate Heidegger’s account of truth within his broader phenomenological–hermeneutic project. In the end, Tugendhat’s critique is grounded upon philosophical assumptions that Heidegger is bringing under question by rethinking the concept of truth. I suggest that thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reading.Stuart Elden - 2005 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 38 (4):281-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Heidegger and the Aesthetics of Rhetoric.Joshua Reeves & Ethan Stoneman - 2014 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 47 (2):137-157.
    But that which remains the poets have founded.In contemporary rhetorical theory, the relationship between rhetoric and art tends to be articulated in terms of aesthetics. This increasingly popular discourse on “aesthetic rhetoric,” however, is characterized by a remarkable diversity. The rhetoric of fiction, poetry, and other literary genres, for example, has been explored in these terms (e.g., Booth 1983), as has the rhetoric of film (Haskins 2003), photography (Hariman and Lucaites 2007), and even natural landscapes (Clark 2004). From a different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Indicación formal y juicio reflexionante. El discurso filosófico y sus desafíos.Bernardo Ainbinder - 2011 - Natureza Humana 13 (1):25-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark