Switch to: References

Citations of:

Semantic analysis

Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press (1960)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Futher reflections on semantic minimalism: Reply to Wedgwood.Alessandro Capone - 2013 - In Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Springer. pp. 437-474..
    semantic minimalism and moderte contextualism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Value and the right kind of reason.Mark Schroeder - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 5:25-55.
    Fitting Attitudes accounts of value analogize or equate being good with being desirable, on the premise that ‘desirable’ means not, ‘able to be desired’, as Mill has been accused of mistakenly assuming, but ‘ought to be desired’, or something similar. The appeal of this idea is visible in the critical reaction to Mill, which generally goes along with his equation of ‘good’ with ‘desirable’ and only balks at the second step, and it crosses broad boundaries in terms of philosophers’ other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Philosophy of language for metaethics.Mark Schroeder - 2012 - In Gillian Russell & Delia Graff Fara (eds.), The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Routledge.
    Metaethics is the study of metaphysics, epistemology, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language, insofar as they relate to the subject matter of moral or, more broadly, normative discourse – the subject matter of what is good, bad, right or wrong, just, reasonable, rational, what we must or ought to do, or otherwise. But out of these four ‘core’ areas of philosophy, it is plausibly the philosophy of language that is most central to metaethics – and not simply (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wishful thinking.Daniel C. Dennett - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner on the verbal behavior of verbal behaviorists.Arthur C. Danto - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Geach and Ascriptivism: Beside the Point.Luís Duarte D'Almeida - 2016 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 4 (6).
    This paper discusses the first incarnation of what came to be known as the “Frege-Geach” point. The point was made by Peter Geach in his 1960 essay “Ascriptivism”, and developed in “Assertion”, a 1965 piece. Geach’s articles launch a wholesale attack on theories of non-descriptive performances advanced by “some Oxford philosophers” whom he accuses of ignoring “the distinction between calling a thing ‘P’ and predicating ‘P’ of a thing”. One view that Geach specifically targets is H. L. A. Hart’s claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Marcus, Kripke, and names.John P. Burgess - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 84 (1):1 - 47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Waiting for the world to make me talk and tell me what I meant.Richard P. Brinker & Julian Jaynes - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modified occam's razor: Parsimony, pragmatics, and the acquisition of word meaning.Thomas D. Bontly - 2005 - Mind and Language 20 (3):288–312.
    Advocates of linguistic pragmatics often appeal to a principle which Paul Grice called Modified Occam's Razor: 'Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity'. Superficially, Grice's principle seems a routine application of the principle of parsimony ('Entities are not to be multiplied beyond necessity'). But parsimony arguments, though common in science, are notoriously problematic, and their use by Griceans faces numerous objections. This paper argues that Modified Occam's Razor makes considerably more sense in light of certain assumptions about the processes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Stimulus-response meaning theory.Jonathan Bennett - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Varieties of Goodness at Work: The Relationship between Business and Morality.Claus Beisbart - 2012 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 55 (4):405-430.
    Abstract What do we mean to say when we call some person a good business manager? And where do the criteria flow from by which we judge people good business managers? I answer these questions by drawing on von Wright's distinction between several varieties of goodness. We can then discriminate between instrumental, technical and moral senses of the expression ?to be a good business manager?. The first two senses presume that business managers have a characteristic task or that they engage (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Admiration and Motivation.Alfred Archer - 2019 - Emotion Review 11 (2):140-150.
    What is the motivational profile of admiration? In this article, I will investigate what form of connection between admiration and motivation there may be good reason to accept. A number of philosophers have advocated a connection between admiration and motivation to emulate. I will start by examining this view and will then present objections to it. I will then suggest an expanded account of the connection between admiration and motivation, according to which, admiration involves motivation to promote the value that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On Goodness, by David Conan Wolfsdorf. [REVIEW]Mahrad Almotahari - 2022 - Mind 131 (521):326-337.
    On Goodness, by WolfsdorfDavid Conan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019. Pp. xxii + 314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is anything just plain good?Mahrad Almotahari & Adam Hosein - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (6):1485-1508.
    Geach and Thomson have argued that nothing is just plain good, because ‘good’ is, logically, an attributive adjective. The upshot, according to Geach and Thomson, is that consequentialism is unacceptable, since its very formulation requires a predicative use of ‘good’. Reactions to the argument have, for the most part, been uniform. Authors have converged on two challenging objections . First, although the logical tests that Geach and Thomson invoke clearly illustrate that ‘good’, as commonly used, is an attributive, they don’t (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Too Much Morality.Stephen Finlay - 2008 - In Paul Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This paper addresses the nature and relationship of morality and self-interest, arguing that what we morally ought to do almost always conflicts with what we self-interestedly ought to do. The concept of morality is analyzed as being essentially and radically other-regarding, and the category of the supererogatory is explained as consisting in what we morally ought to do but are not socially expected to do. I express skepticism about whether there is a coherent question, ‘Which ought I all things considered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Against compositionality: The case of adjectives.Ran Lahav - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 57 (3):261 - 279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Conceptual Analysis in Metaethics.N. G. Laskowski & Stephen Finlay - 2017 - In Tristram Colin McPherson & David Plunkett (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics. New York: Routledge. pp. 536-551.
    A critical survey of various positions on the nature, use, possession, and analysis of normative concepts. We frame our treatment around G.E. Moore’s Open Question Argument, and the ways metaethicists have responded by departing from a Classical Theory of concepts. In addition to the Classical Theory, we discuss synthetic naturalism, noncognitivism (expressivist and inferentialist), prototype theory, network theory, and empirical linguistic approaches. Although written for a general philosophical audience, we attempt to provide a new perspective and highlight some underappreciated problems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Defense of Russellian Descriptivism.Brandt H. van der Gaast - unknown
    In this dissertation, I defend a Russellian form of descriptivism. The main supporting argument invokes a relation between meaning and thought. I argue that the meanings of sentences are the thoughts people use them to express. This is part of a Gricean outlook on meaning according to which psychological intentionality is prior to, and determinative of, linguistic intentionality. The right approach to thought, I argue in Chapter 1, is a type of functionalism on which thoughts have narrow contents. On this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contextualism in Ethics.Gunnar Björnsson - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    There are various ways in which context matters in ethics. Most clearly, the context in which an action is performed might determine whether the action is morally right: though it is often wrong not to keep a promise, it might be permissible in certain contexts. More radically, proponents of moral particularism (see particularism) have argued that a reason for an action in one context is not guaranteed to be a reason in a different context: whether it is a reason against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Radical behaviorism and theoretical entities.G. E. Zuriff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • On the operational definition of a toothache.Colin Wright - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):571.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic kinds.John Woods - 1973 - Philosophia 3 (2-3):117-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extant Social Contracts and the Question of Business Ethics.Ben Wempe - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 88 (S4):741 - 750.
    ISCT arguably forms the most promising impetus to a contractarian theory of business ethics presently available. In this article, I want to pay tribute to the lasting significance of Dunfee's contribution to the field of business ethics by analyzing the vital role of the idea of extant social contracts (ESCs) in the conceptual set up of the ISCT project. The construct of ESCs can be shown to shape the problem statement from which the ISCT project proceeds – indeed it helps (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The legacy of principia.Judith Jarvis Thomson - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):62-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A behavioral theory of mind?H. S. Terrace - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Proper names as connoting expressions.John David Stone - 1982 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):233-239.
    Close attention to the meanings of certain sentences--Counterfactual-Identity sentences--Reveals that no theory in which proper names are simple designators can be a complete and correct semantics of english. An account of connotation is outlined according to which connotation varies with the linguistic environment and with the context of utterance: this accounts for the fact that no proper name is synonymous with a cluster of descriptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • B. F. Skinner's theorizing.Douglas Stalker & Paul Ziff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Orthodox Liturgy and Ethics: a Case Study.Stanley S. Harakas - 2002 - Studies in Christian Ethics 15 (1):11-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The operational analysis of psychological terms.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The operational analysis of psychological terms.B. F. Skinner - 1945 - Psychological Review 52 (4):270-78.
    The major contributions of operationism have been negative, largely because operationists failed to distinguish logical theories of reference from empirical accounts of language. Behaviorism never finished an adequate formulation of verbal reports and therefore could not convincingly embrace subjective terms. But verbal responses to private stimuli can arise as social products through the contingencies of reinforcement arranged by verbal communities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Coming to terms with private events.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • For Goodness' Sake.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):83-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What Organisms Once Were and Might Yet Be.Christopher Shields - 2017 - Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 9 (7).
    Organisms receded from view in much of twentieth-century biology, only to undergo a sort of renaissance at the start of the twenty-first. The story of why this should be so is complicated and fascinating, but belongs primarily to the history of biology. On the other hand, to the extent that it is so, a question naturally arises: what, after all, are organisms? This question has a long and complicated history of its own, both within and without of biology; an investigation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The dialectic of life.Christopher Shields - 2012 - Synthese 185 (1):103-124.
    In the dialectic of debates about the extension of life, one witnesses a predictably repeating pattern: one side appeals to a motley of variegated criteria for something’s qualifying as a living system, only to find an opposite side taking issue with the individual necessity or collective sufficiency of the proposed criteria. Some of these criteria tend to cluster with one another, while others do not: metabolism, growth and reproduction; self-organization and homeostasis; an ability to decrease internal entropy by the appropriation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ordinary Constraints on the Semantics of Living Kinds: A Commonsense Alternative to Recent Treatments of Natural-Object Terms.Scott Atran - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (1):27-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The unity of the normative. [REVIEW]T. M. Scanlon - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 154 (3):443-450.
    From the issue entitled "With Book Symposium on Judith Thomson's Normativity".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reasons as the Unity Among the Varieties of Goodness.Richard Rowland - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (2):200-227.
    Our concepts of good simpliciter, good for, and good as a particular kind of thing must share some common element. I argue that all three types of goodness can be analysed in terms of the reasons that there are for a certain sets of agents to have pro-attitudes. To this end I provide new and compelling accounts of good for and goodness of a kind in terms of reasons for pro-attitudes that are more explanatorily illuminating than competing accounts and that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • In defence of good simpliciter.Richard Rowland - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (5):1371-1391.
    Many including Judith Jarvis Thomson, Philippa Foot, Peter Geach, Richard Kraut, and Paul Ziff have argued for good simpliciter skepticism. According to good simpliciter skepticism, we should hold that there is no concept of being good simpliciter or that there is no property of being good simpliciter. I first show that prima facie we should not accept either form of good simpliciter skepticism. I then show that all of the arguments that good simpliciter skeptics have proposed for their view fail (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • There is more than one way to access an image.Lynn C. Robertson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • B. F. Skinner's operationism.Jon D. Ringen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental, yes. Private, no.Howard Rachlin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Development of Externalist Semantics.Hilary Putnam - 2013 - Theoria 79 (3):192-203.
    In this lecture I describe the path by which I was led to the “semantic externalism” for which I was honoured with the Rolf Schock Prize. Although my interest in linguistics goes back as far as my undergraduate days, it was conversations with Jerrold Katz and Jerry Fodor at MIT (where all three of us taught at the time) in the 1960s that first led to an effort by all three of us to develop semantic theories. My own direction was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • General-purpose content.Carolyn Price - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (2):123-133.
    In this paper, I consider the objection, raised by Radu Bogdan, that a teleological theory of content is unable to ascribe content to a general-purpose, doxastic system. I begin by giving some attention to the notion of general-purpose representation, and suggest that this notion can best be understood as what I term "interest-independent" representation. I then outline Bogdan's objection in what I take to be its simplest form. I attempt to counter the objection by explaining how a teleologist might ascribe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic, reference, and mentalism.Ullin T. Place - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modified Occam’s Razor.Ben Phillips - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2):371-382.
    According to the principle Grice calls 'Modified Occam's Razor' (MOR), 'Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity'. More carefully, MOR says that if there are distinct ways in which an expression is regularly used, then, all other things being equal, we should favour the view that the expression is unambiguous and that certain uses of it can be explained in pragmatic terms. In this paper I argue that MOR cannot have the central role that is typically assigned to it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on language and artificial intelligence: The Chinese-room thought experiment revisited.Klaus K. Obermeier - 1983 - Synthese 56 (September):339-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The non-uniqueness of semantic solutions: Polysemy. [REVIEW]Geoffrey Nunberg - 1979 - Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (2):143 - 184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • On skinner's radical operationism.J. Moore - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Radical behaviorism and mental events: Four methodological queries.Paul E. Meehl - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding proper names.Michael McKinsey - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (4):325-354.
    There is a fairly general consensus that names are Millian (or Russellian) genuine terms, that is, are singular terms whose sole semantic function is to introduce a referent into the propositions expressed by sentences containing the term. This answers the question as to what sort of proposition is expressed by use of sentences containing names. But there is a second serious semantic problem about proper names, that of how the referents of proper names are determined. This is the question that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations