Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Grundlagen der Arithmetik: Studienausgabe mit dem Text der Centenarausgabe.Gottlob Frege - 1988 - Meiner, F.
    Die Grundlagen gehören zu den klassischen Texten der Sprachphilosophie, Logik und Mathematik. Frege stützt sein Programm einer Begründung von Arithmetik und Analysis auf reine Logik, indem er die natürlichen Zahlen als bestimmte Begriffsumfänge definiert. Die philosophische Fundierung des Fregeschen Ansatzes bilden erkenntnistheoretische und sprachphilosophische Analysen und Begriffserklärungen. Studienausgabe aufgrund der textkritisch herausgegebenen Jubiläumsausgabe (Centenarausgabe). Mit Einleitung, Anmerkungen, Literaturverzeichnis und Namenregister.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   255 citations  
  • Core systems of number.Stanislas Dehaene, Elizabeth Spelke & Lisa Feigenson - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (7):307-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   296 citations  
  • Category theory as an autonomous foundation.Øystein Linnebo & Richard Pettigrew - 2011 - Philosophia Mathematica 19 (3):227-254.
    Does category theory provide a foundation for mathematics that is autonomous with respect to the orthodox foundation in a set theory such as ZFC? We distinguish three types of autonomy: logical, conceptual, and justificatory. Focusing on a categorical theory of sets, we argue that a strong case can be made for its logical and conceptual autonomy. Its justificatory autonomy turns on whether the objects of a foundation for mathematics should be specified only up to isomorphism, as is customary in other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics: structure and ontology.Stewart Shapiro - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Do numbers, sets, and so forth, exist? What do mathematical statements mean? Are they literally true or false, or do they lack truth values altogether? Addressing questions that have attracted lively debate in recent years, Stewart Shapiro contends that standard realist and antirealist accounts of mathematics are both problematic. As Benacerraf first noted, we are confronted with the following powerful dilemma. The desired continuity between mathematical and, say, scientific language suggests realism, but realism in this context suggests seemingly intractable epistemic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • Criteria of identity and structuralist ontology.Hannes Leitgib & James Ladyman - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):388-396.
    In discussions about whether the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles is compatible with structuralist ontologies of mathematics, it is usually assumed that individual objects are subject to criteria of identity which somehow account for the identity of the individuals. Much of this debate concerns structures that admit of non-trivial automorphisms. We consider cases from graph theory that violate even weak formulations of PII. We argue that (i) the identity or difference of places in a structure is not to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Physics and Leibniz's principles.Simon Saunders - 2002 - In Katherine Brading & Elena Castellani (eds.), Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 289--307.
    It is shown that the Hilbert-Bernays-Quine principle of identity of indiscernibles applies uniformly to all the contentious cases of symmetries in physics, including permutation symmetry in classical and quantum mechanics. It follows that there is no special problem with the notion of objecthood in physics. Leibniz's principle of sufficient reason is considered as well; this too applies uniformly. But given the new principle of identity, it no longer implies that space, or atoms, are unreal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.Bertrand Russell - 1919 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 89:465-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   488 citations  
  • Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics. [REVIEW]Charles Parsons - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):540.
    This work is the long awaited sequel to the author’s classic Frege: Philosophy of Language. But it is not exactly what the author originally planned. He tells us that when he resumed work on the book in the summer of 1989, after a long interruption, he decided to start afresh. The resulting work followed a different plan from the original drafts. The reader does not know what was lost by their abandonment, but clearly much was gained: The present work may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • An “I” for an I: Singular terms, uniqueness, and reference.Stewart Shapiro - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (3):380-415.
    There is an interesting logical/semantic issue with some mathematical languages and theories. In the language of (pure) complex analysis, the two square roots of i’ manage to pick out a unique object? This is perhaps the most prominent example of the phenomenon, but there are some others. The issue is related to matters concerning the use of definite descriptions and singular pronouns, such as donkey anaphora and the problem of indistinguishable participants. Taking a cue from some work in linguistics and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Cardinality, Counting, and Equinumerosity.Richard G. Heck - 2000 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 41 (3):187-209.
    Frege, famously, held that there is a close connection between our concept of cardinal number and the notion of one-one correspondence, a connection enshrined in Hume's Principle. Husserl, and later Parsons, objected that there is no such close connection, that our most primitive conception of cardinality arises from our grasp of the practice of counting. Some empirical work on children's development of a concept of number has sometimes been thought to point in the same direction. I argue, however, that Frege (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Structure and identity.Stewart Shapiro - 2006 - In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and modality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 34--69.
    According to ante rem structuralism a branch of mathematics, such as arithmetic, is about a structure, or structures, that exist independent of the mathematician, and independent of any systems that exemplify the structure. A structure is a universal of sorts: structure is to exemplified system as property is to object. So ante rem structuralist is a form of ante rem realism concerning universals. Since the appearance of my Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology, a number of criticisms of the idea (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Identity, indiscernibility, and Ante Rem structuralism: The tale of I and –I.Stewart Shapiro - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):285-309.
    Some authors have claimed that ante rem structuralism has problems with structures that have indiscernible places. In response, I argue that there is no requirement that mathematical objects be individuated in a non-trivial way. Metaphysical principles and intuitions to the contrary do not stand up to ordinary mathematical practice, which presupposes an identity relation that, in a sense, cannot be defined. In complex analysis, the two square roots of –1 are indiscernible: anything true of one of them is true of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Realistic structuralism's identity crisis: A hybrid solution.Tim Button - 2006 - Analysis 66 (3):216–222.
    Keränen (2001) raises an argument against realistic (ante rem) structuralism: where a mathematical structure has a non-trivial automorphism, distinct indiscernible positions within the structure cannot be shown to be non-identical using only the properties and relations of that structure. Ladyman (2005) responds by allowing our identity criterion to include 'irreflexive two-place relations'. I note that this does not solve the problem for structures with indistinguishable positions, i.e. positions that have all the same properties as each other and exactly the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine Logisch Mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl.Gottlob Frege & Christian Thiel - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):993-999.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Structuralism.Geoffrey Hellman - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
    With developments in the 19th and early 20th centuries, structuralist ideas concerning the subject matter of mathematics have become commonplace. Yet fundamental questions concerning structures and relations themselves as well as the scope of structuralist analyses remain to be answered. The distinction between axioms as defining conditions and axioms as assertions is highlighted as is the problem of the indefinite extendability of any putatively all-embracing realm of structures. This chapter systematically compares four main versions: set-theoretic structuralism, a version taking structures (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Identity Problem for Realist Structuralism.J. Keranen - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (3):308--330.
    According to realist structuralism, mathematical objects are places in abstract structures. We argue that in spite of its many attractions, realist structuralism must be rejected. For, first, mathematical structures typically contain intra-structurally indiscernible places. Second, any account of place-identity available to the realist structuralist entails that intra-structurally indiscernible places are identical. Since for her mathematical singular terms denote places in structures, she would have to say, for example, that 1 = − 1 in the group (Z, +). We call this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • The individuation of the natural numbers.Øystein Linnebo - 2009 - In Ø. Linnebo O. Bueno (ed.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics. Palgrave-Macmillan.
    It is sometimes suggested that criteria of identity should play a central role in an account of our most fundamental ways of referring to objects. The view is nicely illustrated by an example due to (Quine, 1950). Suppose you are standing at the bank of a river, watching the water that floats by. What is required for you to refer to the river, as opposed to a particular segment of it, or the totality of its water, or the current temporal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Structuralism.Geoffrey Hellman - manuscript
    With the rise of multiple geometries in the nineteenth century, and in the last century the rise of abstract algebra, of the axiomatic method, the set-theoretic foundations of mathematics, and the influential work of the Bourbaki, certain views called “structuralist” have become commonplace. Mathematics is seen as the investigation, by more or less rigorous deductive means, of “abstract structures”, systems of objects fulfilling certain structural relations among themselves and in relation to other systems, without regard to the particular nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Benacerraf's dilemma revisited.Bob Hale & Crispin Wright - 2002 - European Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):101–129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Benacerraf's Dilemma Revisited.Crispin Wright Bob Hale - 2002 - European Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):101-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Frege's theorem and the peano postulates.George Boolos - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):317-326.
    Two thoughts about the concept of number are incompatible: that any zero or more things have a number, and that any zero or more things have a number only if they are the members of some one set. It is Russell's paradox that shows the thoughts incompatible: the sets that are not members of themselves cannot be the members of any one set. The thought that any things have a number is Frege's; the thought that things have a number only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Learning the Natural Numbers as a Child.Stefan Buijsman - 2017 - Noûs 53 (1):3-22.
    How do we get out knowledge of the natural numbers? Various philosophical accounts exist, but there has been comparatively little attention to psychological data on how the learning process actually takes place. I work through the psychological literature on number acquisition with the aim of characterising the acquisition stages in formal terms. In doing so, I argue that we need a combination of current neologicist accounts and accounts such as that of Parsons. In particular, I argue that we learn the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Principles of Mathematics.Bertrand Russell - 1903 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 11 (4):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   754 citations  
  • Singular terms and arithmetical logicism.Ian Rumfitt - 2003 - Philosophical Books 44 (3):193--219.
    This article is a critical notice of Bob Hale and Crispin Wright's *The Reason's Proper Study* (OUP). It focuses particularly on their attempts (crucial to their neo-logicist project) to say what a singular term is. I identify problems for their account but include some constructive suggestions about how it might be improved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology.Stewart Shapiro - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):467-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • What constitutes the numerical diversity of mathematical objects?F. MacBride - 2006 - Analysis 66 (1):63-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl.Gottlob Frege - 1884 - Wittgenstein-Studien 3 (2):993-999.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • All Things Indefinitely Extensible.Stewart Shapiro & Crispin Wright - 2006 - In Stewart Shapiro & Crispin Wright (eds.), All Things Indefinitely Extensible. pp. 255--304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Is Hume's principle analytic?G. Boolos - 1998 - Logic, Logic, and Logic:301--314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Are quantum particles objects?Simon Saunders - 2006 - Analysis 66 (1):52-63.
    Particle indistinguishability has always been considered a purely quantum mechanical concept. In parallel, indistinguishable particles have been thought to be entities that are not properly speaking objects at all. I argue, to the contrary, that the concept can equally be applied to classical particles, and that in either case particles may (with certain exceptions) be counted as objects even though they are indistinguishable. The exceptions are elementary bosons (for example photons).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology.Stewart Shapiro - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198):120-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   256 citations  
  • Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size.Michael Hallett - 1984 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    This volume presents the philosophical and heuristic framework Cantor developed and explores its lasting effect on modern mathematics. "Establishes a new plateau for historical comprehension of Cantor's monumental contribution to mathematics." --The American Mathematical Monthly.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Increasing magnitude counts more: Asymmetrical processing of ordinality in 4-month-old infants.Viola Macchi Cassia, Marta Picozzi, Luisa Girelli & Maria Dolores de Hevia - 2012 - Cognition 124 (2):183-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hume's principle and the number of all objects.Ian Rumfitt - 2001 - Noûs 35 (4):515–541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics.Michael DUMMETT - 1991 - Philosophy 68 (265):405-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • Frege's Theorem and the Peano Postulates.George Boolos - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):317-326.
    Two thoughts about the concept of number are incompatible: that any zero or more things have a (cardinal) number, and that any zero or more things have a number (if and) only if they are the members of some one set. It is Russell's paradox that shows the thoughts incompatible: the sets that are not members of themselves cannot be the members of any one set. The thought that any (zero or more) things have a number is Frege's; the thought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Frege. [REVIEW]Michael D. Resnik - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):961-963.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations