Switch to: Citations

References in:

Platonism in metaphysics

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The nature of mathematical knowledge.Philip Kitcher - 1983 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues against the view that mathematical knowledge is a priori,contending that mathematics is an empirical science and develops historically,just as ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   275 citations  
  • Structured propositions and complex predicates.Jeffrey C. King - 1995 - Noûs 29 (4):516-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Language and Other Abstract Objects.Jerrold J. Katz - 1980 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    To find more information about Rowman and Littlefield titles, please visit www.rowmanlittlefield.com.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Quantifying in.David Kaplan - 1968 - Synthese 19 (1-2):178-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   379 citations  
  • Creativity, Freedom, and Authority: A New Perspective On the Metaphysics of Mathematics.Julian C. Cole - 2009 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (4):589-608.
    I discuss a puzzle that shows there is a need to develop a new metaphysical interpretation of mathematical theories, because all well-known interpretations conflict with important aspects of mathematical activities. The new interpretation, I argue, must authenticate the ontological commitments of mathematical theories without curtailing mathematicians' freedom and authority to creatively introduce mathematical ontology during mathematical problem-solving. Further, I argue that these two constraints are best met by a metaphysical interpretation of mathematics that takes mathematical entities to be constitutively constructed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Why I am not a nominalist.John P. Burgess - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (1):93-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Philosophie der Arithmetik.E. S. Husserl - 1892 - Philosophical Review 1 (3):327-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • On the nature and norms of theoretical commitment.Paul Horwich - 1991 - Philosophy of Science 58 (1):1-14.
    It is not uncommon for philosophers to maintain that one is obliged to believe nothing beyond the observable consequences of a successful scientific theory. This doctrine is variously known as instrumentalism, fictionalism, constructive empiricism, theoretical skepticism and the philosophy of "as if". The purpose of the present paper is to subject such forms of scientific antirealism to a two-pronged critique. In the first place it is argued that there is no genuine difference between believing a theory and being disposed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Number determiners, numbers, and arithmetic.Thomas Hofweber - 2005 - Philosophical Review 114 (2):179-225.
    In his groundbreaking Grundlagen, Frege (1884) pointed out that number words like ‘four’ occur in ordinary language in two quite different ways and that this gives rise to a philosophical puzzle. On the one hand ‘four’ occurs as an adjective, which is to say that it occurs grammatically in sentences in a position that is commonly occupied by adjectives. Frege’s example was (1) Jupiter has four moons, where the occurrence of ‘four’ seems to be just like that of ‘green’ in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Kitcher, ideal agents, and fictionalism.Sarah Hoffman - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):3-17.
    Kitcher urges us to think of mathematics as an idealized science of human operations, rather than a theory describing abstract mathematical objects. I argue that Kitcher's invocation of idealization cannot save mathematical truth and avoid platonism. Nevertheless, what is left of Kitcher's view is worth holding onto. I propose that Kitcher's account should be fictionalized, making use of Walton's and Currie's make-believe theory of fiction, and argue that the resulting ideal-agent fictionalism has advantages over mathematical-object fictionalism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Intuitionism.A. Heyting - 1956 - Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism.Gideon Rosen - 2001 - Noûs 35 (s15):69 - 91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • The thought: A logical inquiry.Gottlob Frege - 1956 - Mind 65 (259):289-311.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl.Gottlob Frege - 1884 - Wittgenstein-Studien 3 (2):993-999.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   278 citations  
  • Indexicals and intensionality: A Fregean perspective.Graeme Forbes - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (1):3-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1987 - MIT Press. Edited by Margaret A. Boden.
    Preface 1 Introduction: The Persistence of the Attitudes 2 Individualism and Supervenience 3 Meaning Holism 4 Meaning and the World Order Epilogue Creation Myth Appendix Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought Notes References Author Index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1512 citations  
  • Realism, Mathematics and Modality.Hartry Field - 1988 - Philosophical Topics 16 (1):57-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Understanding Demonstratives.Gareth Evans - 1981 - In Herman Parret & Jacques Bouveresse (eds.), Meaning and understanding. New York: W. de Gruyter. pp. 280-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Language.Franklin Edgerton & Leonard Bloomfield - 1933 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 53 (3):295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   747 citations  
  • Realism in Mathematics. Penelope Maddy. [REVIEW]Jill Dieterle & Stewart Shapiro - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (4):659-660.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Truth and Meaning.Donald Davidson - 2005-01-01 - In José Medina & David Wood (eds.), Truth. Blackwell. pp. 69–79.
    This chapter contains section titled: Notes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Mathematical explanation and indispensability arguments.Chris Daly & Simon Langford - 2009 - Philosophical Quarterly 59 (237):641-658.
    We defend Joseph Melia's thesis that the role of mathematics in scientific theory is to 'index' quantities, and that even if mathematics is indispensable to scientific explanations of concrete phenomena, it does not explain any of those phenomena. This thesis is defended against objections by Mark Colyvan and Alan Baker.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Fictionalism and the attitudes.Chris John Daly - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (3):423 - 440.
    This paper distinguishes revolutionary fictionalism from other forms of fictionalism and also from other philosophical views. The paper takes fictionalism about mathematical objects and fictionalism about scientific unobservables as illustrations. The paper evaluates arguments that purport to show that this form of fictionalism is incoherent on the grounds that there is no tenable distinction between believing a sentence and taking the fictionalist's distinctive attitude to that sentence. The argument that fictionalism about mathematics is ‘comically immodest’ is also evaluated. In place (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Outlines of a formalist philosophy of mathematics.Haskell Brooks Curry - 1951 - Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Prince and the Phone Booth: Reporting Puzzling Beliefs.Mark Crimmins & John Perry - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (12):685.
    Beliefs are concrete particulars containing ideas of properties and notions of things, which also are concrete. The claim made in a belief report is that the agent has a belief (i) whose content is a specific singular proposition, and (ii) which involves certain of the agent's notions and ideas in a certain way. No words in the report stand for the notions and ideas, so they are unarticulated constituents of the report's content (like the relevant place in "it's raining"). The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   195 citations  
  • Hesperus and Phosphorus.Mark Crimmins - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):1-47.
    In “On Sense and Reference,” surrounding his discussion of how we describe what people say and think, identity is Frege’s first stop and his last. We will follow Frege’s plan here, but we will stop also in the land of make-believe.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The Indispensability of Mathematics.Mark Colyvan - 2001 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    This book not only outlines the indispensability argument in considerable detail but also defends it against various challenges.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • Mathematics and aesthetic considerations in science.Mark Colyvan - 2002 - Mind 111 (441):69-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • On Carnap's Analysis of Statements of Assertion and Belief.A. Church - 1949 - Analysis 10 (5):97-99.
    The intent of the article is to point out an objection against analyses that attempt to eliminate propositions and replace them with sentences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Intensional Isomorphism and Identity of Belief.Alonzo Church - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):294-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Aspects of the Theory of Syntax.Noam Chomsky - 1965 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    Chomsky proposes a reformulation of the theory of transformational generative grammar that takes recent developments in the descriptive analysis of particular ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1505 citations  
  • Person and Object.Roderick Chisholm - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39 (2):281-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   241 citations  
  • Constructibility and mathematical existence.Charles S. Chihara - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book is concerned with `the problem of existence in mathematics'. It develops a mathematical system in which there are no existence assertions but only assertions of the constructibility of certain sorts of things. It explores the philosophical implications of such an approach through an examination of the writings of Field, Burgess, Maddy, Kitcher, and others.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • On realism in set theory.Emily Carson - 1996 - Philosophia Mathematica 4 (1):3-17.
    In her recent book, Realism in mathematics, Penelope Maddy attempts to reconcile a naturalistic epistemology with realism about set theory. The key to this reconciliation is an analogy between mathematics and the physical sciences based on the claim that we perceive the objects of set theory. In this paper I try to show that neither this claim nor the analogy can be sustained. But even if the claim that we perceive some sets is granted, I argue that Maddy's account fails (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Abstract particulars.Keith Campbell - 1990 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Philosophy of logic.Hilary Putnam - 1971 - London,: Allen & Unwin. Edited by Stephen Laurence & Cynthia Macdonald.
    First published in 1971, Professor Putnam's essay concerns itself with the ontological problem in the philosophy of logic and mathematics - that is, the issue of whether the abstract entities spoken of in logic and mathematics really exist. He also deals with the question of whether or not reference to these abstract entities is really indispensible in logic and whether it is necessary in physical science in general.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Mathematics and bleak house.John P. Burgess - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):18-36.
    The form of nominalism known as 'mathematical fictionalism' is examined and found wanting, mainly on grounds that go back to an early antinominalist work of Rudolf Carnap that has unfortunately not been paid sufficient attention by more recent writers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Is it possible to nominalize quantum mechanics?Otávio Bueno - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1424-1436.
    Hartry Field (1980) has developed an interesting nominalization strategy for Newtonian gravitation theory—a strategy that reformulates the theory without quantification over abstract entities. According to David Malament (1982), Field's strategy cannot be extended to quantum mechanics (QM), and so it only has a limited scope. In a recent work, Mark Balaguer has responded to Malament's challenge by indicating how QM can be nominalized, and by “doing much of the work needed to provide the nominalization” (Balaguer 1998, 114). In this paper, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Dirac and the dispensability of mathematics.Otavio Bueno - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36 (3):465-490.
    In this paper, 1 examine the role of the delta function in Dirac’s formulation of quantum mechanics (QM), and I discuss, more generally, the role of mathematics in theory construction. It has been argued that mathematical theories play an indispensable role in physics, particularly in QM [Colyvan, M. (2001). The inrlispensability of mathematics. Oxford University Press: Oxford]. As I argue here, at least in the case of the delta function, Dirac was very clear about its rlispensability. I first discuss the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Fictionalism about fictional characters.Stuart Brock - 2002 - Noûs 36 (1):1–21.
    Despite protestations to the contrary, philosophers have always been renowned for espousing theories that do violence to common-sense opinion. In the last twenty years or so there has been a growing number of philosophers keen to follow in this tradition. According to these philosophers, if a story of pure fic-tion tells us that an individual exists, then there really is such an individual. According to these realists about fictional characters, ‘Scarlett O’Hara,’ ‘Char-lie Brown,’ ‘Batman,’ ‘Superman,’ ‘Tweedledum’ and ‘Tweedledee’ are not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Understanding belief reports.David Braun - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (4):555-595.
    In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory is Russellianism, sometimes also called `neo-Russellianism', `Millianism', `the direct reference theory', `the "Fido"-Fido theory', or `the naive theory'. The objection concernssubstitution of co-referring names in belief sentences. Russellianism implies that any two belief sentences, that differ only in containing distinct co-referring names, express the same proposition (in any given context). Since `Hesperus' and `Phosphorus' both refer to the planet Venus, this view implies that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • Saving Frege from contradiction.George Boolos - 1987 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87:137--151.
    George Boolos; IX*—Saving Frege from Contradiction, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 137–152, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Mathematical truth.Paul Benacerraf - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (19):661-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   688 citations  
  • Inference to the best explanation and mathematical realism.Sorin Ioan Bangu - 2008 - Synthese 160 (1):13-20.
    Arguing for mathematical realism on the basis of Field’s explanationist version of the Quine–Putnam Indispensability argument, Alan Baker has recently claimed to have found an instance of a genuine mathematical explanation of a physical phenomenon. While I agree that Baker presents a very interesting example in which mathematics plays an essential explanatory role, I show that this example, and the argument built upon it, begs the question against the mathematical nominalist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Platonism and Anti-Platonism in Mathematics.Mark Balaguer - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (4):516-518.
    This book does three main things. First, it defends mathematical platonism against the main objections to that view (most notably, the epistemological objection and the multiple-reductions objection). Second, it defends anti-platonism (in particular, fictionalism) against the main objections to that view (most notably, the Quine-Putnam indispensability objection and the objection from objectivity). Third, it argues that there is no fact of the matter whether abstract mathematical objects exist and, hence, no fact of the matter whether platonism or anti-platonism is true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • Fictionalism, theft, and the story of mathematics.Mark Balaguer - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (2):131-162.
    This paper develops a novel version of mathematical fictionalism and defends it against three objections or worries, viz., (i) an objection based on the fact that there are obvious disanalogies between mathematics and fiction; (ii) a worry about whether fictionalism is consistent with the fact that certain mathematical sentences are objectively correct whereas others are incorrect; and (iii) a recent objection due to John Burgess concerning “hermeneuticism” and “revolutionism”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Attitudes without propositions.Mark Balaguer - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):805-26.
    This paper develops a novel version of anti-platonism, called semantic fictionalism. The view is a response to the platonist argument that we need to countenance propositions to account for the truth of sentences containing `that'-clause singular terms, e.g., sentences of the form `x believes that p' and `σ means that p'. Briefly, the view is that (a) platonists are right that `that'-clauses purport to refer to propositions, but (b) there are no such things as propositions, and hence, (c) `that'-clause-containing sentences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A platonist epistemology.Mark Balaguer - 1995 - Synthese 103 (3):303 - 325.
    A response is given here to Benacerraf's 1973 argument that mathematical platonism is incompatible with a naturalistic epistemology. Unlike almost all previous platonist responses to Benacerraf, the response given here is positive rather than negative; that is, rather than trying to find a problem with Benacerraf's argument, I accept his challenge and meet it head on by constructing an epistemology of abstract (i.e., aspatial and atemporal) mathematical objects. Thus, I show that spatio-temporal creatures like ourselves can attain knowledge about mathematical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Mathematical Explanation in Science.Alan Baker - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3):611-633.
    Does mathematics ever play an explanatory role in science? If so then this opens the way for scientific realists to argue for the existence of mathematical entities using inference to the best explanation. Elsewhere I have argued, using a case study involving the prime-numbered life cycles of periodical cicadas, that there are examples of indispensable mathematical explanations of purely physical phenomena. In this paper I respond to objections to this claim that have been made by various philosophers, and I discuss (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations