Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Impossible Worlds: A Modest Approach.Daniel Nolan - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4):535-572.
    Reasoning about situations we take to be impossible is useful for a variety of theoretical purposes. Furthermore, using a device of impossible worlds when reasoning about the impossible is useful in the same sorts of ways that the device of possible worlds is useful when reasoning about the possible. This paper discusses some of the uses of impossible worlds and argues that commitment to them can and should be had without great metaphysical or logical cost. The paper then provides an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • On what there is.W. V. Quine - 1953 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 1-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   259 citations  
  • From a Logical Point of View.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1953 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   868 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2590 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine, Patricia Smith Churchland & Dagfinn Føllesdal - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    Willard Van Orman Quine begins this influential work by declaring, "Language is asocial art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • I_– _Stephen Yablo.Stephen Yablo - 1998 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1):229-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • I_– _Stephen Yablo.Stephen Yablo - 1998 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1):229-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Abstract Objects: A Case Study.Stephen Yablo - 2002 - Philosophical Issues 12 (1):220-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Indicative versus subjunctive conditionals, congruential versus non-hyperintensional contexts.Timothy Williamson - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):310–333.
    §0. A familiar if obscure idea: an indicative conditional presents its consequent as holding in the actual world on the supposition that its antecedent so holds, whereas a subjunctive conditional merely presents its consequent as holding in a world, typically counterfactual, in which its antecedent holds. Consider this pair.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Eligibility and inscrutability.J. Robert G. Williams - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (3):361-399.
    Inscrutability arguments threaten to reduce interpretationist metasemantic theories to absurdity. Can we find some way to block the arguments? A highly influential proposal in this regard is David Lewis’ ‘ eligibility ’ response: some theories are better than others, not because they fit the data better, but because they are framed in terms of more natural properties. The purposes of this paper are to outline the nature of the eligibility proposal, making the case that it is not ad hoc, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Abstract Objects: A Case Study.Stephen Yablo - 2002 - Noûs 36 (s1):220 - 240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Remnants of Meaning.James E. Tomberlin - 1992 - Noûs 26 (1):85-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Remnants of Meaning.Stephen R. Schiffer - 1987 - MIT Press.
    In this foundational work on the theory of linguistic and mental representation, Stephen Schiffer surveys all the leading theories of meaning and content in the philosophy of language and finds them lacking. He concludes that there can be no correct, positive philosophical theory or linguistic or mental representation and, accordingly advocates the deflationary "no-theory theory of meaning and content." Along the way he takes up functionalism, the nature of propositions and their suitability as contents, the language of thought and other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • Ontological commitment.Agustín Rayo - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (3):428–444.
    I propose a way of thinking aboout content, and a related way of thinking about ontological commitment. (This is part of a series of four closely related papers. The other three are ‘On Specifying Truth-Conditions’, ‘An Actualist’s Guide to Quantifying In’ and ‘An Account of Possibility’.).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Ontological Commitment1.Agustín Rayo - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (3):428-444.
    I propose a way of thinking about content, and a related way of thinking about ontological commitment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Ontological relativity.W. V. O. Quine - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (7):185-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   342 citations  
  • Ontological relativity: The Dewey lectures 1969.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (7):185-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Models and reality.Hilary Putnam - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):464-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   283 citations  
  • Extensional theories of ontological commitment.Terence Parsons - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (14):446-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Putnam’s paradox.David Lewis - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):221 – 236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   408 citations  
  • New work for a theory of universals.David K. Lewis - 1983 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4):343-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1502 citations  
  • Counterfactuals and comparative possibility.David Lewis - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (4):418-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David K. Lewis - 1973 - Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
    Counterfactuals is David Lewis' forceful presentation of and sustained argument for a particular view about propositions which express contrary to fact conditionals, including his famous defense of realism about possible worlds and his theory of laws of nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1278 citations  
  • Counterfactuals and the analysis of necessity.Boris Kment - 2006 - Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1):237–302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Propositional Logic of Supposition and Assertion.John T. Kearns - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (3):325-349.
    This presentation of a system of propositional logic is a foundational paper for systems of illocutionary logic. The language contains the illocutionary force operators '' for assertion and ' ' for supposition. Sentences occurring in proofs of the deductive system must be prefixed with one of these operators, and rules of take account of the forces of the sentences. Two kinds of semantic conditions are investigated; familiar truth conditions and commitment conditions. Accepting a statement A or rejecting A commits a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Only in the context of a sentence do words have any meaning.John Wallace - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):144-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A puzzle about ontology.Thomas Hofweber - 2005 - Noûs 39 (2):256–283.
    Ontology is the philosophical discipline that tries to find out what there is: what entities make up reality, what is the stuff the world is made from? Thus, ontology is part of metaphysics, and in fact it seems to be about half of all of metaphysics. It tries to establish what (kinds of) things there are, the other half tries to find out what the (general) properties of these things are and what (general) relations they have to each other. Settling (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Symposium: On What there is.P. T. Geach, A. J. Ayer & W. V. Quine - 1948 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25 (1):125-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   303 citations  
  • The Ontological Significance of Inscrutability.Matti Eklund - 2007 - Philosophical Topics 35 (1-2):115-134.
    I shall here discuss some matters related to the so-called radical indeterminacy or inscrutability arguments due to, e.g., Willard v. O. Quine, Hilary Putnam, John Wallace and Donald Davidson.1 These are arguments that, on the face of it, demonstrate that there is radical indeterminacy in what the expressions in a theory refer to and in what the ontology of the theory is. I will use “inscrutability argument” as a general label for these arguments. My main topic – after I have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Neo-Fregean ontology.Matti Eklund - 2006 - Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1):95-121.
    Neo-Fregeanism in the philosophy of mathematics consists of two main parts: the logicist thesis, that mathematics (or at least branches thereof, like arithmetic) all but reduce to logic, and the platonist thesis, that there are abstract, mathematical objects. I will here focus on the ontological thesis, platonism. Neo-Fregeanism has been widely discussed in recent years. Mostly the discussion has focused on issues specific to mathematics. I will here single out for special attention the view on ontology which underlies the neo-Fregeans’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Inscrutability of Reference.Donald Davidson - 1979 - Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 10 (2):7-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • The Waterfall Illusion.Tim Crane - 1988 - Analysis 48 (June):142-47.
    If you stare for a period of time at a scene which contains movement in one direction, and then turn your attention to an object in a scene which contains no movement, this object will appear to move in the opposite direction to that of the original movement. The effect can be easily achieved by attaching a piece of paper with a spiral drawn on it to the spinning turntable of a record player, and then turning the turntable off while (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • The ontological commitments of inconsistent theories.Mark Colyvan - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 141 (1):115 - 123.
    In this paper I present an argument for belief in inconsistent objects. The argument relies on a particular, plausible version of scientific realism, and the fact that often our best scientific theories are inconsistent. It is not clear what to make of this argument. Is it a reductio of the version of scientific realism under consideration? If it is, what are the alternatives? Should we just accept the conclusion? I will argue (rather tentatively and suitably qualified) for a positive answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Ontology and the Theory of Meaning.Richard L. Cartwright - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Ontology and the theory of meaning.Richard L. Cartwright - 1954 - Philosophy of Science 21 (4):316-325.
    In a number of essays published over the last decade or so, W. V. Quine has made some interesting suggestions concerning the ontology of theories. If I understand him correctly, one of his principal objects has been to formulate a criterion by means of which one can correctly decide what are the ontological commitments of any given theory. My aim in this paper is to reveal what I think are inadequacies in Quine's criterion and to indicate the direction in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Wide or narrow scope?John Broome - 2007 - Mind 116 (462):359-370.
    This paper is a response to ‘Why Be Rational?’ by Niko Kolodny. Kolodny argues that we have no reason to satisfy the requirements of rationality. His argument assumes that these requirements have a logically narrow scope. To see what the question of scope turns on, this comment provides a semantics for ‘requirement’. It shows that requirements of rationality have a wide scope, at least under one sense of ‘requirement’. Consequently Kolodny's conclusion cannot be derived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • Number Words and Ontological Commitment.Berit Brogaard - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226):1–20.
    With the aid of some results from current linguistic theory I examine a recent anti-Fregean line with respect to hybrid talk of numbers and ordinary things, such as ‘the number of moons of Jupiter is four’. I conclude that the anti-Fregean line with respect to these sentences is indefensible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Counterfactuals and context.Berit Brogaard & Joe Salerno - 2008 - Analysis 68 (1):39–46.
    It is widely agreed that contraposition, strengthening the antecedent and hypothetical syllogism fail for subjunctive conditionals. The following putative counter-examples are frequently cited, respectively.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism.Jody Azzouni - 2004 - Oxford, England: Oup Usa.
    If we must take mathematical statements to be true, must we also believe in the existence of abstract eternal invisible mathematical objects accessible only by the power of pure thought? Jody Azzouni says no, and he claims that the way to escape such commitments is to accept true statements which are about objects that don't exist in any sense at all. Azzouni illustrates what the metaphysical landscape looks like once we avoid a militant Realism which forces our commitment to anything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Cartwright Richard L.. Ontology and the theory of meaning. Philosophy of science, vol. 21 , pp. 316–325.Alan Ross Anderson - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism.Jody Azzouni - 2004 - New York, US: OUP Usa.
    What in our theoretical pronouncements commits us to objects? The Quinean standard for ontological commitment involves (nearly enough) commitments when we utter “there is” or “there are” statements without hope of eliminating these by paraphrase. Coupled with the indispensability of the truth of applied mathematical doctrine, the result is that the ontologically hard-nosed scientist is a Platonist—haplessly commited to abstracta. In this book Azzouni offers a way around the Quinean straitjacket: ontological commitment turns on how theories are (nearly enough) nailed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Quine: a guide for the perplexed.Gary Kemp - 2006 - New York, NY: Continuum.
    Willard Van Orman Quine is one of the most influential analytic philosophers of the latter half of the twentieth century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Truth and truthmakers.D. M. Armstrong - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Truths are determined not by what we believe, but by the way the world is. Or so realists about truth believe. Philosophers call such theories correspondence theories of truth. Truthmaking theory, which now has many adherents among contemporary philosophers, is the most recent development of a realist theory of truth, and in this book D. M. Armstrong offers the first full-length study of this theory. He examines its applications to different sorts of truth, including contingent truths, modal truths, truths about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   384 citations  
  • Counterpossibles and Similarity.David Vander Laan - 2004 - In Frank Jackson & Graham Priest (eds.), Lewisian Themes: The Philosophy of David K. Lewis. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. pp. 258-275.
    Several themes of David Lewis's theory of counterfactuals, especially their sensitivity to context, pave the way for a viable theory of non-trivial counterpossibles. If Lewis was successful in defending his account against the early objections, a semantics of counterpossibles can be defended from similar objections in the same way. The resulting theory will be extended to address 'might' counterfactuals and questions about the relative "nearness" of impossible worlds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • On quantifying into predicate position: Steps towards a new (tralist) perspective.Crispin Wright - 2007 - In Mary Leng, Alexander Paseau & Michael Potter (eds.), Mathematical Knowledge. Oxford University Press. pp. 150--74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • New Work For a Theory of Universals.David Lewis - 1983 - In D. H. Mellor & Alex Oliver (eds.), Properties. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1009 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 36 (3):602-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1276 citations  
  • Quine on Reference and Ontology.Peter Hylton - 2006 - In Gibson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Quine. Cambridge University Press. pp. 115--50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aspects of Quine's naturalized epistemology.Robert J. Fogelin - 2004 - In Roger F. Gibson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Quine. Cambridge University Press. pp. 19--46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?Stephen Yablo - 1998 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1):229 - 283.
    [Stephen Yablo] The usual charge against Carnap's internal/external distinction is one of 'guilt by association with analytic/synthetic'. But it can be freed of this association, to become the distinction between statements made within make-believe games and those made outside them-or, rather, a special case of it with some claim to be called the metaphorical/literal distinction. Not even Quine considers figurative speech committal, so this turns the tables somewhat. To determine our ontological commitments, we have to ferret out all traces of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations