Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Making it Explicit.Isaac Levi & Robert B. Brandom - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   945 citations  
  • The Runabout Inference-Ticket.A. N. Prior - 1960 - Analysis 21 (2):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Spreading the Word. [REVIEW]Kent Bach - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (1):120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading.Alvin I. Goldman - 2006 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    People are minded creatures; we have thoughts, feelings and emotions. More intriguingly, we grasp our own mental states, and conduct the business of ascribing them to ourselves and others without instruction in formal psychology. How do we do this? And what are the dimensions of our grasp of the mental realm? In this book, Alvin I. Goldman explores these questions with the tools of philosophy, developmental psychology, social psychology and cognitive neuroscience. He refines an approach called simulation theory, which starts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   318 citations  
  • Unity and Autonomy in Expressivist Logic.John Cantwell - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (3):443-457.
    It is argued that expressivists can solve their problems in accounting for the unity and autonomy of logic – logic is topic independent and does not derive from a general ‘logic’ of mental states – by adopting an analysis of the logical connectives that takes logically complex sentences to express complex combinations of simple attitudes like belief and disapproval and dispositions to form such simple attitudes upon performing suppositional acts, and taking acceptance and rejection of sentences to be the common (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Investigations into Logical Deduction.Gerhard Gentzen - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (4):288 - 306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • What Harmony Could and Could Not Be.Florian Steinberger - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (4):617 - 639.
    The notion of harmony has played a pivotal role in a number of debates in the philosophy of logic. Yet there is little agreement as to how the requirement of harmony should be spelled out in detail or even what purpose it is to serve. Most, if not all, conceptions of harmony can already be found in Michael Dummett's seminal discussion of the matter in The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Hence, if we wish to gain a better understanding of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Tonk, Plonk and Plink.Nuel Belnap - 1962 - Analysis 22 (6):130-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  • Multiple-Conclusion Logic.Ronald Harrop - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (1):161-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Clarendon Press.
    Provides a comprehensive introduction to the major philosophical theories attempting to explain the workings of language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   551 citations  
  • The runabout inference ticket.Arthur Prior - 1967 - In P. F. Strawson (ed.), Philosophical logic. London,: Oxford University Press. pp. 38-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Philosophy and logical syntax.Rudolf Carnap - 1935 - New York: AMS Press.
    'My endeavour in these pages is to explain the main features of the method of philosophizing which we, the Vienna Circle, use, and by using try to develop further. It is the method of the logical analysis of science, or more precisely, of the syntactical analysis of scientific language.... The purpose of the book -- as of the lectures -- is to give a first impression of our method and of the direction of our questions and investigations to those who (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Being for: evaluating the semantic program of expressivism.Mark Andrew Schroeder - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Mark Schroeder.
    Expressivism - the sophisticated contemporary incarnation of the noncognitivist research program of Ayer, Stevenson, and Hare - is no longer the province of metaethicists alone. Its comprehensive view about the nature of both normative language and normative thought has also recently been applied to many topics elsewhere in philosophy - including logic, probability, mental and linguistic content, knowledge, epistemic modals, belief, the a priori, and even quantifiers. Yet the semantic commitments of expressivism are still poorly understood and have not been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • The logical basis of metaphysics.Michael Dummett - 1991 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Such a conception, says Dummett, will form "a base camp for an assault on the metaphysical peaks: I have no greater ambition in this book than to set up a base ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   577 citations  
  • Rejection.Timothy Smiley - 1996 - Analysis 56 (1):1–9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Expression for expressivists.Mark Schroeder - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1):86–116.
    Expressivism’s central idea is that normative sentences bear the same relation to non-cognitive attitudes that ordinary descriptive sentences bear to beliefs: the expression relation. Allan Gibbard teIls us that “that words express judgments will be accepted by almost everyone” - the distinctive contribution of expressivism, his claim goes, is only a view about what kind of judgments words express. But not every account of the expression relation is equally suitable for the expressivist’s purposes. In fact, what I argue in this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • What is logic?Ian Hacking - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (6):285-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Attitudes and contents.Simon Blackburn - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):501-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Robert Brandom - 1994 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    What would something unlike us--a chimpanzee, say, or a computer--have to be able to do to qualify as a possible knower, like us? To answer this question at the very heart of our sense of ourselves, philosophers have long focused on intentionality and have looked to language as a key to this condition. Making It Explicit is an investigation into the nature of language--the social practices that distinguish us as rational, logical creatures--that revises the very terms of this inquiry. Where (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   992 citations  
  • Being for: Evaluating the semantic program of expressivism * by mark Schroeder * clarendon press, 2008. XVI + 198 pp. 27.50: Summary. [REVIEW]Mark Schroeder - 2010 - Analysis 70 (1):101-104.
    My project in Being For is both constructive and negative. The main aim of the book is to take the core ideas of meta-ethical expressivism as far as they can go, and to try to develop a version of expressivism that solves many of the more straightforward open problems that have faced the view without being squarely confronted. In doing so, I develop an expressivist framework that I call biforcated attitude semantics, which I claim has the minimal structural features required (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading.Alvin I. Goldman - 2006 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    People are minded creatures; we have thoughts, feelings and emotions. More intriguingly, we grasp our own mental states, and conduct the business of ascribing them to ourselves and others without instruction in formal psychology. How do we do this? And what are the dimensions of our grasp of the mental realm? In this book, Alvin I. Goldman explores these questions with the tools of philosophy, developmental psychology, social psychology and cognitive neuroscience. He refines an approach called simulation theory, which starts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Why ‘Not’?Huw Price - 1990 - Mind 99 (394):221-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Multiple Conclusion Logic.D. J. Shoesmith & Timothy Smiley - 1978 - Cambridge, England / New York London Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Edited by T. J. Smiley.
    Multiple -conclusion logic extends formal logic by allowing arguments to have a set of conclusions instead of a single one, the truth lying somewhere among the conclusions if all the premises are true. The extension opens up interesting possibilities based on the symmetry between premises and conclusions, and can also be used to throw fresh light on the conventional logic and its limitations. This is a sustained study of the subject and is certain to stimulate further research. Part I reworks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Natural deduction: a proof-theoretical study.Dag Prawitz - 1965 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    This volume examines the notion of an analytic proof as a natural deduction, suggesting that the proof's value may be understood as its normal form--a concept with significant implications to proof-theoretic semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   348 citations  
  • The co-ordination principles: A problem for bilateralism.Fernando Ferreira - 2008 - Mind 117 (468):1051-1057.
    In "'Yes" and "No'" (2000), Ian Rumfitt proposed bilateralism--a use-based account of the logical words, according to which the sense of a sentence is determined by the conditions under which it is asserted and denied. One of Rumfitt's key claims is that bilateralism can provide a justification of classical logic. This paper raises a techical problem for Rumfitt's proposal, one that seems to undermine the bilateralist programme.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Expressivism, Inferentialism, and Saving the Debate.Matthew Chrisman - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2):334-358.
    This paper addresses the “creeping minimalism” challenge to quasi-realist forms of expressivism by arguing that the solution suggested by Dreier doesn’t work and proposing an alternative solution based on the different inferential roles of ethical and descriptive judgments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Yes and no.I. Rumfitt - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):781-823.
    In what does the sense of a sentential connective consist? Like many others, I hold that its sense lies in rules that govern deductions. In the present paper, however, I argue that a classical logician should take the relevant deductions to be arguments involving affirmative or negative answers to yes-or-no questions that contain the connective. An intuitionistic logician will differ in concentrating exclusively upon affirmative answers. I conclude by arguing that a well known intuitionistic criticism of classical logic fails if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Logic, Mathematics, and the A Priori, Part II: Core Logic as Analytic, and as the Basis for Natural Logicism.Neil Tennant - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (3):321-344.
    We examine the sense in which logic is a priori, and explain how mathematical theories can be dichotomized non-trivially into analytic and synthetic portions. We argue that Core Logic contains exactly the a-priori-because-analytically-valid deductive principles. We introduce the reader to Core Logic by explaining its relationship to other logical systems, and stating its rules of inference. Important metatheorems about Core Logic are reported, and its important features noted. Core Logic can serve as the basis for a foundational program that could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophy and Logical Syntax. [REVIEW]E. N. & Rudolf Carnap - 1935 - Journal of Philosophy 32 (13):357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Classical logic without bivalence.Tor Sandqvist - 2009 - Analysis 69 (2):211-218.
    Semantic justifications of the classical rules of logical inference typically make use of a notion of bivalent truth, understood as a property guaranteed to attach to a sentence or its negation regardless of the prospects for speakers to determine it as so doing. For want of a convincing alternative account of classical logic, some philosophers suspicious of such recognition-transcending bivalence have seen no choice but to declare classical deduction unwarranted and settle for a weaker system; intuitionistic logic in particular, buttressed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Sense, assertion, Dummett and denial.Huw Price - 1983 - Mind 92 (366):161-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • For the Sake of the Argument: Ramsey Test Conditionals, Inductive Inference and Nonmonotonic Reasoning.Isaac Levi - 1996 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This book by one of the world's foremost philosophers in the fields of epistemology and logic offers an account of suppositional reasoning relevant to practical deliberation, explanation, prediction and hypothesis testing. Suppositions made 'for the sake of argument' sometimes conflict with our beliefs, and when they do, some beliefs are rejected and others retained. Thanks to such belief contravention, adding content to a supposition can undermine conclusions reached without it. Subversion can also arise because suppositional reasoning is ampliative. These two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Mind 94 (374):310-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   331 citations  
  • Negation for Expressivists: A Collection of Problems with a Suggestion for their Solution.James Dreier - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1:217-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Can there be a Logic of Attitudes?Bob Hale - 1993 - In John Haldane & Crispin Wright (eds.), Reality, representation, and projection. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 337--63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Gnosis.Marcus Kracht - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (3):397 - 420.
    The transition from form to meaning is not neatly layered: there is no point where form ends and content sets in. Rather, there is an almost continuous process that converts form into meaning. That process cannot always take a straight line. Very often we hit barriers in our mind, due to the inability to understand the exact content of the sentence just heard. The standard division between formula and interpretation (or value) should therefore be given up when talking about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Co-ordination principles: A reply.Ian Rumfitt - 2008 - Mind 117 (468):1059-1063.
    I explain why Fernando Ferreira's interesting formal result does not threaten the bilateralist account of the sense of the connectives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Formalisation of Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1945 - Philosophy 20 (75):84-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Negation for expressivists: a collection of problems with a suggestion for their solution.James Dreier - 2006 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 1. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading.Amy Coplan - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):94-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   268 citations  
  • Negation as a sign of negative judgment.Kent Bendall - 1979 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (1):68-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • First Order Expressivist Logic.John Cantwell - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (6):1381-1403.
    This paper provides finitary jointly necessary and sufficient acceptance and rejection conditions for the logical constants of a first order quantificational language. By introducing the notion of making an assignment as a distinct object level practice—something you do with a sentence—(as opposed to a meta-level semantic notion) and combining this with the practice of (hypothetical and categorical) acceptance and rejection and the practice of making suppositions one gains a structure that is sufficiently rich to fully characterize the class of classical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations