Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Algebraic semantics for modal logics II.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):191-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Algebraic semantics for modal logics I.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):46-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • What does a conditional knowledge base entail?Daniel Lehmann & Menachem Magidor - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 55 (1):1-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Functional Semantics of Algebraic Theories.F. William Lawvere - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):340-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Lies and deception: an unhappy divorce.Jennifer Lackey - 2013 - Analysis 73 (2):236-248.
    The traditional view of lying holds that this phenomenon involves two central components: stating what one does not believe oneself and doing so with the intention to deceive. This view remained the generally accepted view of the nature of lying until very recently, with the intention-to-deceive requirement now coming under repeated attack. In this article, I argue that the tides have turned too quickly in the literature on lying. For while it is indeed true that there can be lies where (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Weakly o-minimal structures and some of their properties.B. Sh Kulpeshov - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1511-1528.
    The main result of this paper is Theorem 3.1 which is a criterion for weak o-minimality of a linearly ordered structure in terms of realizations of 1-types. Here we also prove some other properties of weakly o-minimal structures. In particular, we characterize all weakly o-minimal linear orderings in the signature $\{ . Moreover, we present a criterion for density of isolated types of a weakly o-minimal theory. Lastly, at the end of the paper we present some remarks on the Exchange (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Outline of a theory of truth.Saul Kripke - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (19):690-716.
    A formal theory of truth, alternative to tarski's 'orthodox' theory, based on truth-value gaps, is presented. the theory is proposed as a fairly plausible model for natural language and as one which allows rigorous definitions to be given for various intuitive concepts, such as those of 'grounded' and 'paradoxical' sentences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   879 citations  
  • Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models and cumulative logics.Sarit Kraus, Daniel Lehmann & Menachem Magidor - 1990 - Artificial Intelligence 44 (1-2):167-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   365 citations  
  • Logical Pluralism from a Pragmatic Perspective.Teresa Kouri Kissel - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):578-591.
    This paper presents a new view of logical pluralism. This pluralism takes into account how the logical connectives shift, depending on the context in which they occur. Using the Question-Under-Discussion Framework as formulated by Craige Roberts, I identify the contextual factor that is responsible for this shift. I then provide an account of the meanings of the logical connectives which can accommodate this factor. Finally, I suggest that this new pluralism has a certain Carnapian flavour. Questions about the meanings of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Normative Pragmatism and the Language Game of Music.Vojtěch Kolman - 2014 - Contemporary Pragmatism 11 (2):147-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotions and Understanding in Music.Vojtěch Kolman - 2014 - Idealistic Studies 44 (1):83-100.
    The aim of this paper is to sketch a theory of musical experience which takes the empirical research seriously without abandoning or neglecting music’s transcendental features. The tension between the recent empirical approach, as represented particularly by Huron’s ITPRA theory, and the transcendental fact that music as an instance of art is something one can understand and, moreover, can understand oneself through, should be overcome by elaborating on the concept of emotion and the role it can play in musical understanding. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On notation for ordinal numbers.S. C. Kleene - 1938 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):150-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • On Notation for Ordinal Numbers.S. C. Kleene - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):93-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Law and logic.Stig Kanger - 1972 - Theoria 38 (3):105-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • The Paradox of the heap.Hans Kamp - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3):225-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • The Paradox of the Heap.Hans Kamp & Uwe Monnich - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3):991-993.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • A test for the equality of truth-tables.Jan Kalicki - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):161-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Test for the Equality of Truth-Tables.Jan Kalicki - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):268-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Illocutionary Logical Explanation of the Surprise Execution.John Kearns - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):195-213.
    This paper further develops the system of illocutionary logic presented in ?Propositional logic of supposition and assertion? (Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1997, 38, 325-349) to accommodate an ?I believe that? operator and resolve Moore's Paradox. This resolution is accomplished by providing both a truth-conditional and a commitment-based semantics. An important feature of the logical system is that the correctness of some arguments depends on who it is that makes the argument. The paper then shows that the logical system (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logical consistency in simultaneous statistical test procedures.Rafael Izbicki & Luís Gustavo Esteves - 2015 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 23 (5):732-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):281-294.
    We present a basis for the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic. Thereby a conjecture by de Jongh and Visser is proved. We also present a proof system for the admissible rules, and give semantic criteria for admissibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Sorites paradox.Dominic Hyde - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The sorites paradox is the name given to a class of paradoxical arguments, also known as little by little arguments, which arise as a result of the indeterminacy surrounding limits of application of the predicates involved. For example, the concept of a heap appears to lack sharp boundaries and, as a consequence of the subsequent indeterminacy surrounding the extension of the predicate ‘is a heap’, no one grain of wheat can be identified as making the difference between being a heap (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aristotle on Non-Contradiction: Philosophers vs. Non-Philosophers.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2013 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 7 (2):51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Modality and Predicative Necessity.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2013 - International Philosophical Quarterly 53 (1):5-21.
    Many logicians have tried to formalize a modal logic from the Prior Analytics, but the general view is that Aristotle has failed to offer a consistent modal logic there. This paper explains that Aristotle is not interested in modal logic as such. Modalities for him pertain to the relations of predication, without challenging the assertoric system of deductions simpliciter. Thus, demonstrations or dialectical deductions have modal predicates and yet are still deductions simpliciter. It is a matter of distinguishing inferential necessity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on Meaning.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (3):253-280.
    This paper shows that Aristotle's De Interpretatione does not separate syntax from semantics. Linguistic sentences are not syntactic entities, and non-linguistic meanings are not semantic propositions expressed by linguistic sentences. In fact, Aristotle resorts to a mental conception of meaning, distinguishing linguistic meanings in a given language from non-linguistic mental contents in relation to actual things: while the former are not the same for all, the latter are shared by everyone. Aristotle is not a modern logician, like Boole, Frege, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Anti-exceptionalism about logic.Ole Thomassen Hjortland - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (3):631-658.
    Logic isn’t special. Its theories are continuous with science; its method continuous with scientific method. Logic isn’t a priori, nor are its truths analytic truths. Logical theories are revisable, and if they are revised, they are revised on the same grounds as scientific theories. These are the tenets of anti-exceptionalism about logic. The position is most famously defended by Quine, but has more recent advocates in Maddy, Priest, Russell, and Williamson. Although these authors agree on many methodological issues about logic, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Degree spectra and computable dimensions in algebraic structures.Denis R. Hirschfeldt, Bakhadyr Khoussainov, Richard A. Shore & Arkadii M. Slinko - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 115 (1-3):71-113.
    Whenever a structure with a particularly interesting computability-theoretic property is found, it is natural to ask whether similar examples can be found within well-known classes of algebraic structures, such as groups, rings, lattices, and so forth. One way to give positive answers to this question is to adapt the original proof to the new setting. However, this can be an unnecessary duplication of effort, and lacks generality. Another method is to code the original structure into a structure in the given (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The fallacies of the new theory of reference.Jaakko Hintikka & Gabriel Sandu - 1995 - Synthese 104 (2):245 - 283.
    The so-called New Theory of Reference (Marcus, Kripke etc.) is inspired by the insight that in modal and intensional contexts quantifiers presuppose nondescriptive unanalyzable identity criteria which do not reduce to any descriptive conditions. From this valid insight the New Theorists fallaciously move to the idea that free singular terms can exhibit a built-in direct reference and that there is even a special class of singular terms (proper names) necessarily exhibiting direct reference. This fallacious move has been encouraged by a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Kant on Existence, Predication, and the Ontological Argument.Jaakko Hintikka - 1981 - Dialectica 35 (1):127-146.
    The ontological argument fails because of an operator order switch between (1) “necessarily there is an perfect being” and (2) “there is a being which necessarily is perfect”. Here (1) is trivially true logically but (2) problematic. Since Kant's criticisms were directed at the notion of existence, not at the step from (1) to (2), they are misplaced. They are also wrong, because existence can be a predicate. Moreover, Kant did not anticipate Frege's claim that “is” is ambiguous between existence, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Understandings of Logic Sublated by the Dialectic.Paul M. Healey - 2014 - Philosophy Study 4 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Squaring the Dialectic of Inference and Chance.Paul Healey - 2015 - Philosophy Study 5 (5).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Paradoxes of Deontic Logic: Alive and Kicking.Jörg Hansen - 2006 - Theoria 72 (3):221-232.
    In a recent paper, Sven Danielsson argued that the ‘original paradoxes' of deontic logic, in particular Ross's paradox and Prior's paradox of derived obligation, can be solved by restricting the modal inheritance rule. I argue that this does not solve the paradoxes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What Scientific Theories Could Not Be.Hans Halvorson - 2012 - Philosophy of Science 79 (2):183-206.
    According to the semantic view of scientific theories, theories are classes of models. I show that this view -- if taken seriously as a formal explication -- leads to absurdities. In particular, this view equates theories that are truly distinct, and it distinguishes theories that are truly equivalent. Furthermore, the semantic view lacks the resources to explicate interesting theoretical relations, such as embeddability of one theory into another. The untenability of the semantic view -- as currently formulated -- threatens to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation.Ulrike Hahn & Jos Hornikx - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1833-1873.
    In this paper, it is argued that the most fruitful approach to developing normative models of argument quality is one that combines the argumentation scheme approach with Bayesian argumentation. Three sample argumentation schemes from the literature are discussed: the argument from sign, the argument from expert opinion, and the appeal to popular opinion. Limitations of the scheme-based treatment of these argument forms are identified and it is shown how a Bayesian perspective may help to overcome these. At the same time, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • A Normative Theory of Argument Strength.Ulrike Hahn & Mike Oaksford - 2006 - Informal Logic 26 (1):1-24.
    In this article, we argue for the general importance of normative theories of argument strength. We also provide some evidence based on our recent work on the fallacies as to why Bayesian probability might, in fact, be able to supply such an account. In the remainder of the article we discuss the general characteristics that make a specifically Bayesian approach desirable, and critically evaluate putative flaws of Bayesian probability that have been raised in the argumentation literature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the Modal Logic of Jeffrey Conditionalization.Zalán Gyenis - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (3-4):351-374.
    We continue the investigations initiated in the recent papers where Bayes logics have been introduced to study the general laws of Bayesian belief revision. In Bayesian belief revision a Bayesian agent revises his prior belief by conditionalizing the prior on some evidence using the Bayes rule. In this paper we take the more general Jeffrey formula as a conditioning device and study the corresponding modal logics that we call Jeffrey logics, focusing mainly on the countable case. The containment relations among (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Standard bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable.Zalán Gyenis - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):326-337.
    In the article [2] a hierarchy of modal logics has been defined to capture the logical features of Bayesian belief revision. Elements in that hierarchy were distinguished by the cardinality of the set of elementary propositions. By linking the modal logics in the hierarchy to the modal logics of Medvedev frames it has been shown that the modal logic of Bayesian belief revision determined by probabilities on a finite set of elementary propositions is not finitely axiomatizable. However, the infinite case (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Shifting Sands.Delia Graff - 2000 - Philosophical Topics 28 (1):45-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Experts: Which ones should you trust?Alvin I. Goldman - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1):85-110.
    Mainstream epistemology is a highly theoretical and abstract enterprise. Traditional epistemologists rarely present their deliberations as critical to the practical problems of life, unless one supposes—as Hume, for example, did not—that skeptical worries should trouble us in our everyday affairs. But some issues in epistemology are both theoretically interesting and practically quite pressing. That holds of the problem to be discussed here: how laypersons should evaluate the testimony of experts and decide which of two or more rival experts is most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • Denying antecedents and affirming consequents: The state of the art.David Godden & Frank Zenker - 2015 - Informal Logic 35 (1):88-134.
    Recent work on conditional reasoning argues that denying the antecedent [DA] and affirming the consequent [AC] are defeasible but cogent patterns of argument, either because they are effective, rational, albeit heuristic applications of Bayesian probability, or because they are licensed by the principle of total evidence. Against this, we show that on any prevailing interpretation of indicative conditionals the premises of DA and AC arguments do not license their conclusions without additional assumptions. The cogency of DA and AC inferences rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A probabilistic analysis of argument cogency.David Godden & Frank Zenker - 2018 - Synthese 195 (4):1715-1740.
    This paper offers a probabilistic treatment of the conditions for argument cogency as endorsed in informal logic: acceptability, relevance, and sufficiency. Treating a natural language argument as a reason-claim-complex, our analysis identifies content features of defeasible argument on which the RSA conditions depend, namely: change in the commitment to the reason, the reason’s sensitivity and selectivity to the claim, one’s prior commitment to the claim, and the contextually determined thresholds of acceptability for reasons and for claims. Results contrast with, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Substructural Fuzzy Logics.George Metcalfe & Franco Montagna - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3):834 - 864.
    Substructural fuzzy logics are substructural logics that are complete with respect to algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval [0.1]. In this paper, we introduce Uninorm logic UL as Multiplicative additive intuitionistic linear logic MAILL extended with the prelinearity axiom ((A → B) ∧ t) ∨ ((B → A) ∧ t). Axiomatic extensions of UL include known fuzzy logics such as Monoidal t-norm logic MTL and Gödel logic G, and new weakening-free logics. Algebraic semantics for these logics are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Investigations into Logical Deduction.Gerhard Gentzen, M. E. Szabo & Paul Bernays - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Zur Miete bei Frege – Rudolf Hirzel und die Rezeption der stoischen Logik und Semantik in Jena.Gottfried Gabriel, Karlheinz Hülser & Sven Schlotter - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (4):369-388.
    It has been noted before in the history of logic that some of Frege's logical and semantic views were anticipated in Stoicism. In particular, there seems to be a parallel between Frege's Gedanke (thought) and Stoic lekton; and the distinction between complete and incomplete lekta has an equivalent in Frege's logic. However, nobody has so far claimed that Frege was actually influenced by Stoic logic; and there has until now been no indication of such a causal connection. In this essay, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The thought: A logical inquiry.Gottlob Frege - 1956 - Mind 65 (259):289-311.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations  
  • The method of levels of abstraction.Luciano Floridi - 2008 - Minds and Machines 18 (3):303–329.
    The use of “levels of abstraction” in philosophical analysis (levelism) has recently come under attack. In this paper, I argue that a refined version of epistemological levelism should be retained as a fundamental method, called the method of levels of abstraction. After a brief introduction, in section “Some Definitions and Preliminary Examples” the nature and applicability of the epistemological method of levels of abstraction is clarified. In section “A Classic Application of the Method ofion”, the philosophical fruitfulness of the new (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • A plea for non-naturalism as constructionism.Luciano Floridi - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (2):269-285.
    Contemporary science seems to be caught in a strange predicament. On the one hand, it holds a firm and reasonable commitment to a healthy naturalistic methodology, according to which explanations of natural phenomena should never overstep the limits of the natural itself. On the other hand, contemporary science is also inextricably and now inevitably dependent on ever more complex technologies, especially Information and Communication Technologies, which it exploits as well as fosters. Yet such technologies are increasingly “artificialising” or “denaturalising” the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Tarski on truth and logical consequence.John Etchemendy - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):51-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • The modalized Heyting calculus: a conservative modal extension of the Intuitionistic Logic ★.Leo Esakia - 2006 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 16 (3-4):349-366.
    In this paper we define an augmentation mHC of the Heyting propositional calculus HC by a modal operator ?. This modalized Heyting calculus mHC is a weakening of the Proof-Intuitionistic Logic KM of Kuznetsov and Muravitsky. In Section 2 we present a short selection of attractive (algebraic, relational, topological and categorical) features of mHC. In Section 3 we establish some close connections between mHC and certain normal extension K4.Grz of the modal system K4. We define a translation of mHC into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Relatedness and implication.Richard L. Epstein - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (2):137 - 173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations