Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Reforming Philosophy: A Victorian Debate on Science and Society.Laura J. Snyder - 2006 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    The Victorian period in Britain was an “age of reform.” It is therefore not surprising that two of the era’s most eminent intellects described themselves as reformers. Both William Whewell and John Stuart Mill believed that by reforming philosophy—including the philosophy of science—they could effect social and political change. But their divergent visions of this societal transformation led to a sustained and spirited controversy that covered morality, politics, science, and economics. Situating their debate within the larger context of Victorian society (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Science and Hypothesis: Historical Essays on Scientific Methodology.Larry Laudan & R. Laudan - 1981 - Springer.
    This book consists of a collection of essays written between 1965 and 1981. Some have been published elsewhere; others appear here for the first time. Although dealing with different figures and different periods, they have a common theme: all are concerned with examining how the method of hy pothesis came to be the ruling orthodoxy in the philosophy of science and the quasi-official methodology of the scientific community. It might have been otherwise. Barely three centuries ago, hypothetico deduction was in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • A forerunner?—Perhaps, but not to the context distinction. William Whewell's Germano-cantabrigian history of the fundamental ideas.Jutta Schickore - 2006 - In Jutta Schickore & Friedrich Steinle (eds.), Revisiting Discovery and Justification: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives on the Context Distinction. Springer. pp. 57--77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Newton's training in the Aristotelian textbook tradition: from effects to causes and back.Steffen Ducheyne - 2005 - History of Science 43 (3):217-237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • General scholium.Isaac Newton - 1999 - In The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. University of California Press. pp. 939-944.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • A preliminary discourse on the study of natural philosophy.John F. W. Herschel - 1830 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Originally published in 1830, this book can be called the first modern work in the philosophy of science, covering an extraordinary range of philosophical, methodological, and scientific subjects. "Herschel's book . . . brilliantly analyzes both the history and nature of science."—Keith Stewart Thomson, American Scientist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Galileo’s Interventionist Notion of “Cause‘.Steffen Ducheyne - 2006 - Journal of the History of Ideas 67 (3):443-464.
    In this essay, I shall argue that Galileo introduced a new scientifically useful notion of causality. This new notion of causality was an interventionist notion, according to which causal relations can be discovered by actively exploring and manipulating natural processes. The presence of this conception can be seen from Galileo's explanation of floating bodies and his theory of the tides. I shall point to the similarity between Galileo's notion of "cause" and recent interventionist accounts of causation in the philosophy of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Whewell and the Scientists: Science and Philosophy of Science in 19th Century Britain.Laura Snyder - 2002 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 9:81-94.
    What is the relation between science and philosophy of science? Specifically, does it matter whether a philosopher of science knows much about science or is actually engaged in scientific research? William Whewell is an obvious person to consider in relation to this question. Whewell was actively engaged in science in several important ways, some of which have not been previously noted. He conducted research in a number of scientific fields, he devised new terminology for the new discoveries made by other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Whewell's Critics: Have They Prevented Him from Doing Good?John Wettersten - 2005 - Rodopi.
    William Whewell's views on the philosophy of science were dismissed as incoherent and eclectic when he introduced them in the middle of the 19th century, though some leading contemporaries engaged and even incorporated them. When his ideas were resurrected a century later, they were dismissed as poor induction rather than original thinking. Wettersten (philosophy of science, Mannheim U., Germany) explores why Whewell's impact continues to be felt, and why almost all theorists have had to come to terms with his ideas. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain.Richard Yeo - 1979 - Annals of Science 36 (5):493-516.
    (1979). William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain. Annals of Science: Vol. 36, No. 5, pp. 493-516.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Whewell, Necessity and The Inductive Sciences: A Philosophical-Systematic Survey.Steffen Ducheyne - 2009 - South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):333-358.
    In this paper Whewell’s concept of necessity is scrutinized and its historical development is outlined (ca. 1833-1860). Particular attention will be paid to how Whewell interpreted the laws of the inductive sciences as being necessary since the laws of nature are concretizations of the Fundamental Ideas which can be partially described by Axioms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • William Whewell: A Composite Portrait.Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.) - 1991 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    William Whewell was a giant of Victorian intellectual culture. His influence, whether recognized or forgotten, is palpable in areas as diverse as moral philosophy, mineralogy, architecture, the politics of education, physics, engineering, and theology. Recent studies of the place of the sciences in nineteenth-century Britain have repeatedly indicated the significance of Whewell's sweeping and critical proposals for a reformed account of scientific knowledge and moral values. However, until now there has been no detailed study of the context and impact of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science.Robert E. Butts - 1965 - American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (3):161 - 181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Newton’s notion and practice of unification.Steffen Ducheyne - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1):61-78.
    n this paper I deal with a neglected topic with respect to unification in Newton’s Principia. I will clarify Newton’s notion and practice of unification . In order to do so, I will use the recent theories on unification as tools of analysis . I will argue, after showing that neither Kitcher’s nor Schurz’s account aptly capture Newton’s notion and practice of unification, that Salmon’s later work is a good starting point for analysing this notion and its practice in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Whewell on the ultimate problem of philosophy.Margaret Morrison - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (3):417-437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • William Stanley Jevons and the Making of Modern Economics.Harro Maas - 2005 - Cambridge University Press.
    The Victorian polymath William Stanley Jevons is generally and rightly venerated as one of the great innovators of economic theory and method in what came to be known as the 'marginalist revolution'. This book is an investigation into the cultural and intellectual resources that Jevons drew upon to revolutionize research methods in economics. Jevons's uniform approach to the sciences was based on a firm belief in the mechanical constitution of the universe and a firm conviction that all scientific knowledge was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Dialogue concerning the Two Chief World Systems.Galileo Galilei & Stillman Drake - 1954 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5 (19):253-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • William Whewell: Omniscientist.Michael Ruse - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. New York: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Necessary and contingent truth in William Whewell's antithetical theory of knowledge.Menachem Fisch - 1984 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (4):275-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reforming philosophy: a Victorian debate on science and society.Laura J. Snyder - 2006 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    A philosophically and historically sensitive account of the engagement of the major protagonists of Victorian British philosophy, Reforming Philosophy considers the controversies between William Whewell and John Stuart Mill on the topics of science, morality, politics, and economics. By situating their debate within the larger context of Victorian society and its concerns, Laura Snyder shows how two very different men—Whewell, an educator, Anglican priest, and critic of science; and Mill, a philosopher, political economist, and parliamentarian—reacted to the challenges of their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Rethinking Whewell.John Wettersten - 1993 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (4):481-515.
    The nineteenth-century appraisal of Whewell's philosophy as confused, eclectic, and metaphysical is still dominant today. Yet he keeps reappearing on the agenda of the historians and philosophers of science. Why? Whewell continues to be a puzzle. Historians evade the puzzle by deeming him to have had no serious philosophy but some interesting ideas and/or to have been socially important. Menachim Fisch's recent study offers promise of a new appraisal. But Fisch's account leads back to the puzzle. Fisch poses the question (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Galilean reflections on Milton friedman’s "methodology of positive economics," with thoughts on Vernon smith’s "economics in the laboratory".Eric Schliesser - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (1):50-74.
    In this article, the author offers a discussion of the evidential role of the Galilean constant in the history of physics. The author argues that measurable constants help theories constrain data. Theories are engines for research, and this helps explain why the Duhem-Quine thesis does not undermine scientific practice. The author connects his argument to discussion of two famous papers in the history of economic methodology, Milton Friedman's 'Methodology of Positive Economics', which appealed to example of Galilean Law of Fall (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Discoverers' induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):580-604.
    In this paper I demonstrate that, contrary to the standard interpretations, William Whewell's view of scientific method is neither that of the hypothetico-deductivist nor that of the retroductivist. Rather, he offers a unique inductive methodology, which he calls "discoverers' induction." After explicating this methodology, I show that Kepler's discovery of his first law of planetary motion conforms to it, as Whewell claims it does. In explaining Whewell's famous phrase about "happy guesses" in science, I suggest that Whewell intended a distinction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Whewell's Consilience of Inductions–An Evaluation.Menachem Fisch - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):239-255.
    The paper attempts to elucidate and evaluate William Whewell's notion of a "consilience of inductions." In section I Whewellian consilience is defined and shown to differ considerably from what latter-day writers talk about when they use the term. In section II a primary analysis of consilience is shown to yield two types of consilient processes, one in which one of the lower-level laws undergoes a conceptual change (the case aptly discussed in Butts [1977]), and one in which the explanatory theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Mill-Whewell Debate: Much Ado about Induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (2):159-198.
    This article examines the nineteenth-century debate about scientific method between John Stuart Mill and William Whewell. Contrary to standard interpretations (given, for example, by Achinstein, Buchdahl, Butts, and Laudan), I argue that their debate was not over whether to endorse an inductive methodology but rather over the nature of inductive reasoning in science and the types of conclusions yielded by it. Whewell endorses, while Mill rejects, a type of inductive reasoning in which inference is employed to find a property or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • It's all necessarily so: William Whewell on scientific truth.Laura J. Snyder - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):785-807.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • William Whewell and John Stuart Mill on the Methodology of Political Economy.Samuel Hollander - 1983 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 14 (2):127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Observing Science in Early Victorian England: Recent Scholarship on William Whewell.Joan L. Richards - 1996 - Perspectives on Science 4 (2):231-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviewing Herschel's discourse.Richard Yeo - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (4):541-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Re-examining Galileos Theory of Tides.Paolo Palmieri - 1998 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 53 (3 - 4):223-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Defining Science. William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in Early Victorian Britain.R. Yeo & G. Cantor - 1995 - Annals of Science 52 (1):88-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • William Whewell Philosopher of Sciences.Menachem Fisch & Robert C. Richardson - 1994 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 16 (1):155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Scientific Methodology of William Whewell.Michael Ruse - 1976 - Centaurus 20 (3):227-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Galileo’s Tidal Theory.Ron Naylor - 2007 - Isis 98 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Galileo’s Tidal Theory.Ron Naylor - 2007 - Isis 98:1-22.
    The aim of Galileo’s tidal theory was to show that the tides were produced entirely by the earth’s motion and thereby to demonstrate the physical truth of Copernicanism. However, in the Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems Galileo did not explain some of the most significant aspects of the theory completely. As a consequence, the way the theory works has long been disputed. Though there exist a number of interpretations in the literature, the most widely accepted are based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A “Large and Graceful Sinuosity”.Thomas L. Hankins - 2006 - Isis 97 (4):605-633.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A “large And Graceful Sinuosity”.Thomas Hankins - 2006 - Isis 97:605-633.
    In 1833 John Herschel published a graphical method for determining the orbits of double stars. He argued that his method, which depended on human judgment rather than mathematical analysis, gave better results than computation, given the uncertainty in the data. Herschel found that astronomy and terrestrial physics were especially suitable for graphical treatment, and he expected that graphs would soon become important in all areas of science. He argued with William Whewell and James D. Forbes over the process of induction, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Galilean reflections on Milton friedman’ S “ methodology of positive economics, ” with thoughts on Vernon smith’ S “ economics in the laboratory&rdquo””.Schliesser Eric - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (1):50-74.
    In this article, the author offers a discussion of the evidential role of the Galilean constant in the history of physics. The author argues that measurable constants help theories constrain data. Theories are engines for research, and this helps explain why the Duhem-Quine thesis does not undermine scientific practice. The author connects his argument to discussion of two famous papers in the history of economic methodology, Milton Friedman’s “Methodology of Positive Economics,” which appealed to example of Galilean Law of Fall (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Spirited Horse, the Engineer, and the Mathematician: Water Waves in Nineteenth-Century Hydrodynamics.Olivier Darrigol - 2003 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 58 (1):21-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A philosopher's coming of age: A study in erotetic intellectual history.Menachem Fisch - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. New York: Clarendon Press. pp. 31--66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations