Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant on the Content of Cognition.Clinton Tolley - 2014 - European Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):200-228.
    I present an argument for an interpretation ofKant's views on the nature of the ‘content [Inhalt]’ of ‘cognition [Erkenntnis]’. In contrast to one of the longest standing interpretations ofKant's views on cognitive content, which ascribes toKant a straightforwardly psychologistic understanding of content, and in contrast as well to the more recently influential reading ofKant put forward byMcDowell and others, according to whichKant embraces a version ofRussellianism, I argue thatKant's views on this topic are of a much moreFregean bent than has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise.[author unknown] - 1993 - Ethics 103 (3):540-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • A Progress of Sentiments. Reflections on Hume's Treatise.[author unknown] - 1993 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 55 (2):369-369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Leaving Nature Behind.Robert Pippin - 2002 - In Nicholas Hugh Smith (ed.), Reading McDowell: On Mind and World. New York: Routledge. pp. 58--75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Immanuel Kant - 1781 - Mineola, New York: Macmillan Company. Edited by J. M. D. Meiklejohn.
    Immanuel Kant was one of the leading lights of 18th-century philosophy; his work provided the foundations for later revolutionary thinkers such as Hegel and Marx. This work contains the keystone of his critical philosophy - the basis of human knowledge and truth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   272 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-40).David Hume - 1969 - Mineola, N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Edited by Ernest Campbell Mossner.
    A key to modern studies of 18th century Western philosophy, the Treatise considers numerous classic philosophical issues, including causation, existence, freedom and necessity and morality. This abridged edition has an introduction which explain's Hume's thought and places it in the context of its times.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   477 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1969 - Harmondsworth,: Penguin Books. Edited by Ernest Campbell Mossner.
    One of Hume's most well-known works and a masterpiece of philosophy, A Treatise of Human Nature is indubitably worth taking the time to read.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   943 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Günter Zöller - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):113.
    This new translation of the first Critique forms part of a fifteen-volume English-language edition of the works of Immanuel Kant under the general editorship of this volume’s editor-translators, Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. The edition, which is almost complete by now, comprises all of Kant’s published works along with extensive selections from his literary remains, his correspondence, and student transcripts of his lecture courses in metaphysics, ethics, logic, and anthropology. The Cambridge edition aims at a consistent English rendition of Kant’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Kant on the Content of Cognition.Clinton Tolley - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):200-228.
    I present an argument for an interpretation of Kant's views on the nature of the ‘content [Inhalt]’ of ‘cognition [Erkenntnis]’. In contrast to one of the longest standing interpretations of Kant's views on cognitive content, which ascribes to Kant a straightforwardly psychologistic understanding of content, and in contrast as well to the more recently influential reading of Kant put forward by McDowell and others, according to which Kant embraces a version of Russellianism, I argue that Kant's views on this topic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • ...this I or He or It (The thing) which thinks..Wilfrid Sellars - 1970 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 44:5 - 31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Kant on the Spontaneity of Mind.Robert B. Pippin - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):449 - 475.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant refers often and with no apparent hesitation or sense of ambiguity to the mind. He does so not only in his justly famous destruction of rationalist proofs of immaterialism, but throughout his own, positive, ‘transcendental’ account in the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental Analytic. In the first edition of the Critique, he even proposed what he adventurously called a ‘transcendental psychology’ and, although this strange discipline seemed to disappear in the second edition, he left (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Kant's Thinker. [REVIEW]Colin Marshall - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (6):1226-1229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant on Freedom of Empirical Thought.Markus Kohl - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (2):301-26.
    It is standardly assumed that, in Kant, “free agency” is identical to moral agency and requires the will or practical reason. Likewise, it is often held that the concept of “spontaneity” that Kant uses in his theoretical philosophy is very different from, and much thinner than, his idea of practical spontaneity. In this paper I argue for the contrary view: Kant has a rich theory of doxastic free agency, and the spontaneity in empirical thought (which culminates in judgments of experience) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kant on self-identity.Patricia Kitcher - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (1):41-72.
    Despite Kemp Smith's claims to the contrary, I show that there is good reason to believe that Kant was aware of Hume's attack on personal identity. My interpretive claim is that we can make sense of many of Kant's puzzling remarks in the subjective deduction by assuming that he was trying to reply to Hume's challenge. My substantive claim is that Kant succeeds in defending a notion of the self as a continuing sequence of informationally interdependent states.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant on self-consciousness.Patricia Kitcher - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (3):345-386.
    The highest principle of Kant’s theoretical philosophy is that all cognition must “be combined in one single self-consciousness”. Elsewhere I have tried to explain why he believed that all cognition must belong to a single self ; here I try to clarify the other half of the doctrine. What led him to the claim that all cognition involved self-consciousness? This question is pressing, because the thesis strikes many as obviously false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):449-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   678 citations  
  • Critique of pure reason.Immanuel Kant - 1781/1998 - In Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Blackwell. pp. 449-451.
    One of the cornerstone books of Western philosophy, Critique of Pure Reason is Kant's seminal treatise, where he seeks to define the nature of reason itself and builds his own unique system of philosophical thought with an approach known as transcendental idealism. He argues that human knowledge is limited by the capacity for perception and attempts a logical designation of two varieties of knowledge: a posteriori, the knowledge acquired through experience; and a priori, knowledge not derived through experience. This accurate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   945 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1726 citations  
  • Understanding and sensibility.Stephen Engstrom - 2006 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):2 – 25.
    Kant holds that the human cognitive power is divided into two "stems", understanding and sensibility. This doctrine has seemed objectionably dualistic to many critics, who see these stems as distinct parts, each able on its own to produce representations, which must somehow interact, determining or constraining one another, in order to secure the fit, requisite for cognition, between concept and intuition. This reading cannot be squared, however, with what Kant actually says about theoretical cognition and the way understanding and sensibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Self-consciousness and the Unity of Knowledge.Stephen Engstrom - 2016 - In Sally Sedgwick & Dina Emundts (eds.), Bewusstsein/Consciousness. De Gruyter. pp. 25-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kants Theory of Freedom. [REVIEW]Roger J. Sullivan - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):865-867.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Robert Brandom - 1994 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    What would something unlike us--a chimpanzee, say, or a computer--have to be able to do to qualify as a possible knower, like us? To answer this question at the very heart of our sense of ourselves, philosophers have long focused on intentionality and have looked to language as a key to this condition. Making It Explicit is an investigation into the nature of language--the social practices that distinguish us as rational, logical creatures--that revises the very terms of this inquiry. Where (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   970 citations  
  • Die Spontaneität des Verstandes bei Kant und einigen Neokantianern.Matthew Boyle - 2015 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 63 (4).
    Kant famously characterizes our human understanding as a “spontaneous” faculty, but what can this mean? I criticize some recent interpretations of Kant’s claim and suggest that we can only understand what Kant means by “the spontaneity of understanding” if we recognize certain basic differences between how Kant conceived of cognition and how philosophers commonly think of it today. I go on to argue that Kant’s conception of cognition represents an appealing alternative to the unsatisfying options that contemporary ways of thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique.Matthew Boyle - 2016 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (3):527-555.
    Additive theories of rationality, as I use the term, are theories that hold that an account of our capacity to reflect on perceptually-given reasons for belief and desire-based reasons for action can begin with an account of what it is to perceive and desire, in terms that do not presuppose any connection to the capacity to reflect on reasons, and then can add an account of the capacity for rational reflection, conceived as an independent capacity to ‘monitor’ and ‘regulate’ our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • A progress of sentiments: reflections on Hume's Treatise.Annette Baier - 1991 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    " By the end, we can see the cause to which Hume has been true throughout the work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • A Progress of Sentiments. Reflections on Hume's Treatise.Peter Jones - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (170):114-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On Naturalizing Kant's Transcendental Psychology.Henry E. Allison - 1995 - Dialectica 49 (2‐4):335-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Review of Henry E. Allison: Kant's Theory of Freedom[REVIEW]Karl Ameriks - 1992 - Ethics 102 (3):655-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.P. H. Nidditch (ed.) - 1978 - Oxford University Press.
    A scholarly edition of a work by David Hume. The edition presents an authoritative text, together with an introduction, commentary notes, and scholarly apparatus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Kant’s Theory of the Self.Arthur Melnick - 2008 - Routledge.
    The reality of the thinking subject -- The paralogisms and transcendental idealism -- The first paralogism -- The second paralogism -- Transcendental self-consciousness -- Other interpretations of the paralogisms -- Empirical apperception -- Pure apperception -- The person as subject -- Apperception and inner sense -- The third paralogism and Kant's conception of a person -- The embodied subject -- The fourth paralogism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant’s Theoretical and Practical Philosophy.Henry E. Allison - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Allison is one of the foremost interpreters of the philosophy of Kant. This new volume collects all his recent essays on Kant's theoretical and practical philosophy. All the essays postdate Allison's two major books on Kant, and together they constitute an attempt to respond to critics and to clarify, develop and apply some of the central theses of those books. Two are published here for the first time. Special features of the collection are: a detailed defence of the author's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Empiricism and the philosophy of mind.Wilfrid Sellars - 1956 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1:253-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1189 citations  
  • Kant on Self-Consciousness.Patricia Kitcher - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (3):345-386.
    The highest principle of Kant’s theoretical philosophy is that all cognition must “be combined in one single self-consciousness”. Elsewhere I have tried to explain why he believed that all cognition must belong to a single self ; here I try to clarify the other half of the doctrine. What led him to the claim that all cognition involved self-consciousness? This question is pressing, because the thesis strikes many as obviously false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Having the world in view: Sellars, Kant, and intentionality.John Mcdowell - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (9):431-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   190 citations  
  • Kant's theory of judgment.Robert Hanna - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing and Discursive Commitment.Brandom Robert - 1995 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 68 (3):83-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • 'Making up Your Mind' and the Activity of Reason.Matthew Boyle - 2011 - Philosophers' Imprint 11.
    A venerable philosophical tradition holds that we rational creatures are distinguished by our capacity for a special sort of mental agency or self-determination: we can “make up” our minds about whether to accept a given proposition. But what sort of activity is this? Many contemporary philosophers accept a Process Theory of this activity, according to which a rational subject exercises her capacity for doxastic self-determination only on certain discrete occasions, when she goes through a process of consciously deliberating about whether (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations