Switch to: Citations

References in:

Toward a rational theory of progress

Synthese 99 (2):277 - 304 (1994)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach.Joseph Agassi - 1974 - Philosophia 4 (1):163-201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1986 - Philosophy 62 (241):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Logic of Scientific Discovery.K. Popper - 1959 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (37):55-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1325 citations  
  • Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge.Karl Raimund Popper - 1962 - London, England: Routledge.
    The way in which knowledge progresses, and especially our scientific knowledge, is by unjustified anticipations, by guesses, by tentative solutions to our problems, by conjectures. These conjectures are controlled by criticism: that is, by attempted refutations, which include severely critical tests. They may survive these tests; but they can never be positively justified: they can neither be established as certainly true nor even as 'probable'. Criticism of our conjectures is of decisive importance: by bringing out our mistakes it makes us (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • The problem of the rationality of magic.Ian C. Jarvie & Joseph Agassi - 1987 - In Joseph Agassi & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Rationality: the critical view. Hingham, MA, USA: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 363--383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach.Karl Raimund Popper - 1972 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The essays in this volume represent an approach to human knowledge that has had a profound influence on many recent thinkers. Popper breaks with a traditional commonsense theory of knowledge that can be traced back to Aristotle. A realist and fallibilist, he argues closely and in simple language that scientific knowledge, once stated in human language, is no longer part of ourselves but a separate entity that grows through critical selection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   302 citations  
  • (1 other version)Realism and the aim of science.Karl R. Popper - 1988 - New York: Routledge. Edited by William Warren Bartley.
    Popper formulates and explains his non-justificationist theory of knowledge. Science--empirical science--aims at true explanatory theories, yet it can never prove, finally establish, or justify any of its theories as true, not even if it is in fact a true theory. Science must continue to question and criticize all its theories, even those which happen to be true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • The structure of problems, (part I).J. N. Hattiangadi - 1978 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 8 (4):345-365.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Learning from the past: Reflections on the role of history in the philosophy of science.Daniel Garber - 1986 - Synthese 67 (1):91 - 114.
    In recent years philosophers of science have turned away from positivist programs for explicating scientific rationality through detailed accounts of scientific procedure and turned toward large-scale accounts of scientific change. One important motivation for this was better fit with the history of science. Paying particular attention to the large-scale theories of Lakatos and Laudan I argue that the history of science is no better accommodated by the new large-scale theories than it was by the earlier positivist philosophies of science; both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Whewell's Consilience of Inductions–An Evaluation.Menachem Fisch - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):239-255.
    The paper attempts to elucidate and evaluate William Whewell's notion of a "consilience of inductions." In section I Whewellian consilience is defined and shown to differ considerably from what latter-day writers talk about when they use the term. In section II a primary analysis of consilience is shown to yield two types of consilient processes, one in which one of the lower-level laws undergoes a conceptual change (the case aptly discussed in Butts [1977]), and one in which the explanatory theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Mind and body.Hilary Putnam - 1981 - In Reason, Truth and History. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   270 citations  
  • Objective knowledge, an evolutionary approach.Karl R. Popper - 1974 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 166 (1):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   369 citations  
  • The Scientific Image.William Demopoulos & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1798 citations  
  • (3 other versions)An Autobiography.F. G. Marcham & R. G. Collingwood - 1941 - Philosophical Review 50 (5):546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Magic and rationality again.Ian C. Jarvie & Joseph Agassi - 1987 - In Joseph Agassi & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Rationality: the critical view. Hingham, MA, USA: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 385--394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Science Naturalized, Science Denatured: An Evaluation of Ronald Giere's Cognitivist Approach to Explaining Science.Noah J. Efron & Menachem Fisch - 1991 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 13 (2):187 - 221.
    Ronald Giere and others aspire to 'naturalize science' by examining scientific activity as they would any other natural phenomenon — scientifically. Giere aims to fashion a theory of science that is naturalistic, realistic, and evolutionary, and to thus carve for himself a niche between foundationalist philosophies of science (positing abstract criteria of rationality) on the one hand, and relativist sociologies of science on the other. Giere's approach is appealing because it allows that science is a human endeavor pursued by humans (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An introduction to the philosophy of induction and probability.Laurence Jonathan Cohen - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Two new philosophical problems surrounding the gradation of certainty began to emerge in the 17th century and are still very much alive today. One is concerned with the evaluation of inductive reasoning, whether in science, jurisprudence, or elsewhere; the other with the interpretation of the mathematical calculus of change. This book, aimed at non-specialists, investigates both problems and the extent to which they are connected. Cohen demonstrates the diversity of logical structures that are available for judgements of probability, and explores (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Are methodologies theories of scientific rationality?Ronald C. Curtis - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (1):135-161.
    Historians should not use their own up-to-date methodologies to judge the rationality or correctness of the research strategies of scientists in history. For the history of science is, in part, the history of the rational growth of methodology and the historian's own up-to-date methodology is, in part, a product of the scientific revolutions of the past. Historians who use their own methodologies to judge the rationality of past research strategies are being too wise after the event. I show, using the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytic Philosophy.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1986 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 22 (1):78-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • III. Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action.Quentin Skinner - 1974 - Political Theory 2 (3):277-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)History of science and its rational reconstructions.Imre Lakatos - 1971 - In R. C. Buck & R. S. Cohen (eds.), Psa 1970. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Viii. D. Reidel. pp. 91-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The implications of induction.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1970 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 160:486-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Logic of Scientific Discovery.Karl Popper - 1959 - Studia Logica 9:262-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1558 citations  
  • Explaining Science.Ronald Giere - 1991 - Noûs 25 (3):386-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Einstein Versus Bohr: The Continuing Controversies in Physics.Elie Zahar - 1988 - Open Court Publishing Company.
    Einstein Versus Bohr is unlike other books on science written by experts for non-experts, because it presents the history of science in terms of problems, conflicts, contradictions, and arguments. Science normally "keeps a tidy workshop." Professor Sachs breaks with convention by taking us into the theoretical workshop, giving us a problem-oriented account of modern physics, an account that concentrates on underlying concepts and debate. The book contains mathematical explanations, but it is so-designed that the whole argument can be followed with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Charles Darwin and the Refutation of Whewellian Metascience: How the Philosophy of Science Learned From the History of Science.Ronald Clarence Curtis - 1983 - Dissertation, York University (Canada)
    How does the philosophy of science learn from history? Imre Lakatos argued that we can criticize various methodologies by testing them against the basic value judgments of working scientists in history. If a methodology gives a judgment which is dissonant with that of working scientists, this should be seen as a criticism of the methodology which may have to be rejected in favour of a better one. Lakatos based his argument on the view that methodologies are theories of scientific rationality. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The probable and the provable.Laurence Jonathan Cohen - 1977 - Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    The book was planned and written as a single, sustained argument. But earlier versions of a few parts of it have appeared separately. The object of this book is both to establish the existence of the paradoxes, and also to describe a non-Pascalian concept of probability in terms of which one can analyse the structure of forensic proof without giving rise to such typical signs of theoretical misfit. Neither the complementational principle for negation nor the multiplicative principle for conjunction applies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   276 citations  
  • (1 other version)History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions.Imre Lakatos - 1970 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1970:91-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • Action and Context.Martin Hollis & Quentin Skinner - 1978 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 52 (1):43 - 69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)An autobiography.Robin George Collingwood - 1939 - New York, etc.]: Oxford University Press.
    This early work by Robin G. Collingwood was originally published in 1939 and we are now republishing it with a brand new introductory biography. 'An Autobiography' is the story of Collingwood's personal and academic life. Robin George Collingwood was born on 22nd February 1889, in Cartmel, England. He was the son of author, artist, and academic, W. G. Collingwood. He was greatly influenced by the Italian Idealists Croce, Gentile, and Guido de Ruggiero. Another important influence was his father, a professor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • (1 other version)An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1990 - Mind 99 (394):313-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The Gentle Art of Philosophical Polemics: Selected Reviews and Comments.Joseph Agassi - 1988 - Open Court Publishing Company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Reply to Critics.Q. Skinner - 1988 - In James Tully (ed.), Meaning and context: Quentin Skinner and his critics. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press. pp. 233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Idea of History.R. G. Collingwood - 1946 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):252-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • (1 other version)Realism and the Aim of Science.Karl R. Popper & W. W. Bartley - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (4):669-671.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • (1 other version)Conjectures and Refutations.K. Popper - 1963 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 21 (3):431-434.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1389 citations  
  • Darwin as an epistemologist.Ronald Curtis - 1987 - Annals of Science 44 (4):379-408.
    SummaryIn this article I argue that Darwin was the author, quite contrary to his original intentions, of a fundamental revolution in the theory of scientific knowledge. In 1838, in order to meet the anti-evolutionist challenge of his professional colleague, William Whewell, he began to sketch a transmutationist theory of the origin of human ideas which would explain the success of inductive science: its discovery of what Whewell and his contemporaries thought were necessary and certain truths. But though it explained how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Hempel's ravens, the natural classification of hypotheses and the growth of knowledge.Menachem Fisch - 1984 - Erkenntnis 21 (1):45 - 62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Applications of Inductive Logic.L. J. Cohen & M. B. Hesse - 1983 - Mind 92 (365):145-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)An introduction to the philosophy of induction and probability.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1992 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (1):95-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rationality and problem- solving.John Kekes - 1977 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (4):351-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rationality and problem-solving.John Kekes - 1987 - In John Oulton Wisdom (ed.), Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Aldershot, England : Avebury. pp. 265--279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations