Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. What We Owe to Each Other.Thomas Scanlon (ed.) - 1998 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    How do we judge whether an action is morally right or wrong? If an action is wrong, what reason does that give us not to do it? Why should we give such reasons priority over our other concerns and values? In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other. According to his contractualist view, thinking about right and wrong is thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1662 citations  
  • (1 other version)Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1308 citations  
  • Mind and world: with a new introduction.John Henry McDowell - 1994 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Much as we would like to conceive empirical thought as rationally grounded in experience, pitfalls await anyone who tries to articulate this position, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   415 citations  
  • Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Practical Reality is a lucid original study of the relation between the reasons why we do things and the reasons why we should. Jonathan Dancy maintains that current philosophical orthodoxy bowdlerizes this relation, making it impossible to understand how anyone can act for a good reason. By giving a fresh account of values and reasons, he finds a place for normativity in philosophy of mind and action, and strengthens the connection between these areas and ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   394 citations  
  • The skeptic and the dogmatist.James Pryor - 2000 - Noûs 34 (4):517–549.
    Consider the skeptic about the external world. Let’s straightaway concede to such a skeptic that perception gives us no conclusive or certain knowledge about our surroundings. Our perceptual justification for beliefs about our surroundings is always defeasible—there are always possible improvements in our epistemic state which would no longer support those beliefs. Let’s also concede to the skeptic that it’s metaphysically possible for us to have all the experiences we’re now having while all those experiences are false. Some philosophers dispute (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   822 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1067 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Mind and World.John McDowell - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (182):99-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1014 citations  
  • Perception and Reason.Bill Brewer - 1999 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Bill Brewer presents an original view of the role of conscious experience in the acquisition of empirical knowledge. He argues that perceptual experiences must provide reasons for empirical beliefs if there are to be any determinate beliefs at all about particular objects in the world. This fresh approach to epistemology turns away from the search for necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge and works instead from a theory of understanding in a particular area.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Mind and World.John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):389-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   885 citations  
  • (1 other version)A coherence theory of truth and knowledge.Donald Davidson - 1986 - In Ernest LePore, Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 307-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   506 citations  
  • Nonconceptual content and the "space of reasons".Richard G. Heck - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):483-523.
    In Mind and World, John McDowell argues against the view that perceptual representation is non-conceptual. The central worry is that this view cannot offer any reasonable account of how perception bears rationally upon belief. I argue that this worry, though sensible, can be met, if we are clear that perceptual representation is, though non-conceptual, still in some sense 'assertoric': Perception, like belief, represents things as being thus and so.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations  
  • Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Philosophy 78 (305):414-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   486 citations  
  • (1 other version)Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge.John McDowell - 1988 - In Jonathan Dancy, Perceptual knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 455-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   344 citations  
  • There is immediate justification.James Pryor - 2013 - In Matthias Steup & John Turri, Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Blackwell. pp. 181--202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • The Humean theory of motivation.Michael Smith - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):36-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  • Concepts of Epistemic Justification.William P. Alston - 1985 - The Monist 68 (1):57-89.
    Justification, or at least ‘justification’, bulks large in recent epistemology. The view that knowledge consists of true-justified-belief has been prominent in this century, and the justification of belief has attracted considerable attention in its own right. But it is usually not at all clear just what an epistemologist means by ‘justified’, just what concept the term is used to express. An enormous amount of energy has gone into the attempt to specify conditions under which beliefs of one or another sort (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   264 citations  
  • Meaning, knowledge, and reality.John Henry McDowell - 1998 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    This is the second volume of John McDowell's selected papers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Knowledge and the internal.John McDowell - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):877-93.
    1. I am going to work with an idea from Sellars, that knowledge—at least as enjoyed by rational animals—is a certain sort of standing in the space of reasons. My concern is a familiar philosophical dialectic, which I shall approach in terms of what happens to the Sellarsian idea when the image of standings in the space of reasons undergoes a certain deformation. That it is a deformation is something we can learn from how unsatisfactory the familiar dialectic is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   199 citations  
  • The authority of desire.Dennis W. Stampe - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (July):335-81.
    The Aristotelian dictum that desire is the starting point of practical reasoning that ends in action can of course be denied. Its denial is a commonplace of moral theory in the tradition of Kant. But in this essay I am concerned with that issue only indirectly. I shall not contend that rational action always or necessarily does involve desire as its starting point; nor shall I deny it. My question concerns instead the possibility of its ever beginning in desire. For (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Singular thought and the extent of 'inner space'.John McDowell - 1986 - In Philip Pettit, Subject, Thought, And Context. NY: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • An introduction to contemporary epistemology.Jonathan Dancy - 1985 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Introduction As its title indicates, this book is intended to provide an introduction to the main topics currently discussed under the rather unclear ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • (1 other version)Responses.John McDowell - 2018 - In André J. Abath & Federico Sanguinetti, Mcdowell and Hegel: Perceptual Experience, Thought and Action. Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Can Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?Laurence Bonjour - 1978 - American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Knowledge by hearsay.John McDowell - 1994 - In A. Chakrabarti & B. K. Matilal, Knowing from Words. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 195--224.
    Language matters to epistemology for two separate reasons (although they are no doubt connected) -/- My interest in testimony derives from Gareth Evans, as does my conviction that it cannot be accommodated by the sort of account of knowledge which I attack in this paper. I believe I also owe to him my interest in the sorts of case I discuss in §4 below, where knowledge is retained under the risk that what would have been knowledge if the relevant fact (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Mind and World.Hilary Putnam - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (2):267.
    Quine has spoken of bringing our beliefs about the world before “the tribunal of experience.” In Mind and World, McDowell agrees that this is what we must do, but he argues forcefully that Quine’s conception of experience as nothing more than a neuronal cause of verbal responses loses the whole idea that experiences can justify beliefs. McDowell’s overarching aim is to determine conditions that experience must satisfy if it is to be genuinely a tribunal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology.Jonathan Dancy - 1985 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 49 (2):329-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • A Defense of Immediate Non-Inferential Justification.J. Pryor - 2013 - In Matthias Steup & John Turri, Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology.Jonathan Dancy - 1985 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 179 (4):649-649.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • (1 other version)Experiences.J. M. Hinton - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (66):1-13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Reading McDowell: On Mind and World.Nicholas Hugh Smith (ed.) - 2002 - New York: Routledge.
    John McDowell's Mind and World is widely acknowledged to be one of the most important contributions to philosophy in recent years. In this volume leading philosophers examine the nature and extent of McDowell's achievement in Mind and World and related writings. The chapters, most of which were specially commissioned for this volume, are divided into five parts. The essays in part one consider Mind and World 's location in the modern philosophical tradition, particularly its relation to Kant's critical project. Parts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)Experiences.J. M. Hinton - 1974 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (1):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology.Marie McGinn & Jonathan Dancy - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (145):574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Knowledge and the internal revisited.John Mcdowell - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1):97-105.
    In “Knowledge and the Social Articulation of the Space of Reasons,” Robert Brandom reads my “Knowledge and the Internal” as sketching a position that, when properly elaborated, opens into his own social-perspectival conception of knowledge . But this depends on taking me to hold that there cannot be justification for a belief sufficient to exclude the possibility that the belief is false. And that is exactly what I argued against in “Knowledge and the Internal.” Seeing that P constitutes falsehood-excluding justification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Human Nature?Crispin Wright - 1996 - European Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):235-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Sense-experience and the grounding of thought.Barry G. Stroud - 2002 - In Reading McDowell: On Mind and World. New York: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Lecture I.John McDowell - 1998 - Journal of Philosophy 95 (9):431-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • V*—The Rational Role of Experience.Michael Martin - 1993 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1):71-88.
    Michael Martin; V*—The Rational Role of Experience, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 93, Issue 1, 1 June 1993, Pages 71–88, https://doi.org/10.10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Reply to Gibson, Byrne, and Brandom.John McDowell - 1996 - Philosophical Issues 7:283-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Precis of Mind and world.John McDowell - 1996 - In Enrique Villanueva, Perception. Ridgeview Pub. Co. pp. 231--9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Precis of Mind and WorldMind and World.John McDowell - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):365.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Subjective, intersubjective, objective.John Mcdowell - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (3):675–681.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The given regained: Reflections on the sensuous content of experience.Richard Schantz - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):167-180.
    The major part of our beliefs and our knowledge of the world is based on, or grounded in, sensory experience. But, how is it that we can have perceptual beliefs that things are thus and so, and, moreover, be justified in having them? What conditions must experience satisfy to rationally warrant, and not merely to cause, our beliefs? Against the currently very popular contention that experience itself already has to be propositionally and conceptually structured, I will rehabilitate the claim that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Perception.Enrique Villanueva (ed.) - 1996 - Ridgeview Pub. Co.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Comment on Robert Brandom's 'some pragmatist themes in Hegel's idealism'.John McDowell - 1999 - European Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):190–193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Perception and rational constraint: McDowell's mind and world.Robert B. Brandom - 1996 - Philosophical Issues 7:241-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • XI*—Immediate Experience.Paul Gilbert - 1992 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92 (1):233-250.
    Paul Gilbert; XI*—Immediate Experience, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 92, Issue 1, 1 June 1992, Pages 233–250, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristot.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review: Reply to Commentators. [REVIEW]John McDowell - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):403 - 431.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Replies. [REVIEW]Robert Brandom - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1):189-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Précis of "mind and world". [REVIEW]John McDowell - 1996 - Philosophical Issues 7:231-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Epistemic Openness and Perceptual Defeasibility. [REVIEW]Michael Martin - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (2):441 - 448.
    Bill Brewer contends that we should embrace a principle he calls : perceptual experiences provide reasons for empirical beliefs. He rejects traditional foundationalist and coherentist pictures of perception and perceptual justification and argues for a view on which perceptual experiences themselves intrinsically give reason for empirical beliefs. Brewer sees perceptual experience as conceptual; imbued with a content which gives a subject a perspective on the elements of his or her immediate environment. This ‘epistemic openness’ to the environment provided by perceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations