Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Reasoning with logical bilattices.Ofer Arieli & Arnon Avron - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (1):25--63.
    The notion of bilattice was introduced by Ginsberg, and further examined by Fitting, as a general framework for many applications. In the present paper we develop proof systems, which correspond to bilattices in an essential way. For this goal we introduce the notion of logical bilattices. We also show how they can be used for efficient inferences from possibly inconsistent data. For this we incorporate certain ideas of Kifer and Lozinskii, which happen to suit well the context of our work. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • How a computer should think.Nuel Belnap - 1977 - In Gilbert Ryle (ed.), Contemporary aspects of philosophy. Boston: Oriel Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  • On Axiomatizing Shramko-Wansing’s Logic.Sergei P. Odintsov - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):407-428.
    This work treats the problem of axiomatizing the truth and falsity consequence relations, ⊨ t and ⊨ f, determined via truth and falsity orderings on the trilattice SIXTEEN 3 (Shramko and Wansing, 2005). The approach is based on a representation of SIXTEEN 3 as a twist-structure over the two-element Boolean algebra.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Bilattices and the Semantics of Logic Programming.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Bilattices, due to M. Ginsberg, are a family of truth value spaces that allow elegantly for missing or conflicting information. The simplest example is Belnap’s four-valued logic, based on classical two-valued logic. Among other examples are those based on finite many-valued logics, and on probabilistic valued logic. A fixed point semantics is developed for logic programming, allowing any bilattice as the space of truth values. The mathematics is little more complex than in the classical two-valued setting, but the result provides (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Bilattices In Logic Programming.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Bilattices, introduced by M. Ginsberg, constitute an elegant family of multiple-valued logics. Those meeting certain natural conditions have provided the basis for the semantics of a family of logic programming languages. Now we consider further restrictions on bilattices, to narrow things down to logic programming languages that can, at least in principle, be implemented. Appropriate bilattice background information is presented, so the paper is relatively self-contained.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Power of Belnap: Sequent Systems for SIXTEEN ₃. [REVIEW]Heinrich Wansing - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (4):369 - 393.
    The trilattice SIXTEEN₃ is a natural generalization of the wellknown bilattice FOUR₂. Cut-free, sound and complete sequent calculi for truth entailment and falsity entailment in SIXTEEN₃, are presented.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Some Useful 16-Valued Logics: How a Computer Network Should Think.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2):121-153.
    In Belnap's useful 4-valued logic, the set 2 = {T, F} of classical truth values is generalized to the set 4 = ������(2) = {Ø, {T}, {F}, {T, F}}. In the present paper, we argue in favor of extending this process to the set 16 = ᵍ (4) (and beyond). It turns out that this generalization is well-motivated and leads from the bilattice FOUR₂ with an information and a truth-and-falsity ordering to another algebraic structure, namely the trilattice SIXTEEN₃ with an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Hyper-contradictions, generalized truth values and logics of truth and falsehood.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2006 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15 (4):403-424.
    In Philosophical Logic, the Liar Paradox has been used to motivate the introduction of both truth value gaps and truth value gluts. Moreover, in the light of “revenge Liar” arguments, also higher-order combinations of generalized truth values have been suggested to account for so-called hyper-contradictions. In the present paper, Graham Priest's treatment of generalized truth values is scrutinized and compared with another strategy of generalizing the set of classical truth values and defining an entailment relation on the resulting sets of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Evidential bilattice logic and lexical inference.Andreas Schöter - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (1):65-105.
    This paper presents an information-based logic that is applied to the analysis of entailment, implicature and presupposition in natural language. The logic is very fine-grained and is able to make distinctions that are outside the scope of classical logic. It is independently motivated by certain properties of natural human reasoning, namely partiality, paraconsistency, relevance, and defeasibility: once these are accounted for, the data on implicature and presupposition comes quite naturally.The logic is based on the family of semantic spaces known as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On Axiomatizing Shramko-Wansing’s Logic.Sergei P. Odintsov - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):407 - 428.
    This work treats the problem of axiomatizing the truth and falsity consequence relations, $ \vDash _t $ and $ \vDash _f $, determined via truth and falsity orderings on the trilattice SIXTEEN₃. The approach is based on a representation of SIXTEEN₃ as a twist-structure over the two-element Boolean algebra.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Sequent calculi for some trilattice logics.Norihiro Kamide & Heinrich Wansing - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):374-395.
    The trilattice SIXTEEN3 introduced in Shramko & Wansing (2005) is a natural generalization of the famous bilattice FOUR2. Some Hilbert-style proof systems for trilattice logics related to SIXTEEN3 have recently been studied (Odintsov, 2009; Shramko & Wansing, 2005). In this paper, three sequent calculi GB, FB, and QB are presented for Odintsovs coordinate valuations associated with valuations in SIXTEEN3. The equivalence between GB, FB, and QB, the cut-elimination theorems for these calculi, and the decidability of B are proved. In addition, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Gentzen-Type Methods for Bilattice Negation.Norihiro Kamide - 2005 - Studia Logica 80 (2-3):265-289.
    A general Gentzen-style framework for handling both bilattice (or strong) negation and usual negation is introduced based on the characterization of negation by a modal-like operator. This framework is regarded as an extension, generalization or re- finement of not only bilattice logics and logics with strong negation, but also traditional logics including classical logic LK, classical modal logic S4 and classical linear logic CL. Cut-elimination theorems are proved for a variety of proposed sequent calculi including CLS (a conservative extension of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Knowledge, Uncertainty and Ignorance in Logic: Bilattices and beyond.George Gargov - 1999 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 9 (2-3):195-283.
    ABSTRACT In the paper we present a survey of some approaches to the semantics of many-valued propositional systems. These approaches are inspired on one hand by classical problems in the investigations of logical aspects of epistemic activity: knowledge and truth, contradictions, beliefs, reliability of data, etc. On the other hand they reflect contemporary concerns of researchers in Artificial Intelligence (and Cognitive Science in general) with inferences drawn from imperfect information, even from total ignorance. We treat the mathematical apparatus that has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and 'coupled trees'.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Philosophical Studies 29 (3):149-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • Truth values.Yaroslav Shramko - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The trilaticce of constructive truth values.Yaroslav Shramko, J. Michael Dunn & Tatsutoshi Takenaka - 2001 - Journal of Logic and Computation 11 (1):761--788.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • A useful four-valued logic.N. D. Belnap - 1977 - In J. M. Dunn & G. Epstein (eds.), Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic. D. Reidel.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Bilattices are nice things.Melvin Fitting - 2006 - In T. Bolander, V. Hendricks & S. A. Pedersen (eds.), Self-Reference. CSLI Publications.
    One approach to the paradoxes of self-referential languages is to allow some sentences to lack a truth value (or to have more than one). Then assigning truth values where possible becomes a fixpoint construction and, following Kripke, this is usually carried out over a partially ordered family of three-valued truth-value assignments. Some years ago Matt Ginsberg introduced the notion of bilattice, with applications to artificial intelligence in mind. Bilattices generalize the structure Kripke used in a very natural way, while making (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • A cut-free system for 16-valued reasoning.Norihiro Kamide - 2005 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 34 (4):213-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations