Switch to: Citations

References in:

Freedom as Independence

Ethics 126 (4):1043–1074 (2016)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant, Ripstein and the Circle of Freedom: A Critical Note.Laura Valentini - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):450-459.
    Much contemporary political philosophy claims to be Kant-inspired, but its aims and method differ from Kant's own. In his recent book, Force and Freedom, Arthur Ripstein advocates a more orthodox Kantian outlook, presenting it as superior to dominant (Kant-inspired) views. The most striking feature of this outlook is its attempt to ground the whole of political morality in one right: the right to freedom, understood as the right to be independent of others’ choices. Is Ripstein's Kantian project successful? In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4066 citations  
  • Robert Nozick and wilt Chamberlain: How patterns preserve liberty. [REVIEW]G. A. Cohen - 1977 - Erkenntnis 11 (1):5 - 23.
    Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State and Utopia is in large measure an ingenious elaboration of an argument for capitalism adumbrated by Plekhanov. The capitalism Nozick advocates is more pure than the one we know today. It lacks taxation for social welfare, and it permits degrees of inequality far greater than most apologists for contemporary bourgeois society would countenance. The present paper paper is only indirectly a critique of Nozick's defense of capitalism. Its immediate aim is to refute Nozick's major argument against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Being free to act, and being a free man.S. I. Benn & W. L. Weinstein - 1971 - Mind 80 (318):194-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. [REVIEW]Richard J. Arneson - 2002 - Ethics 112 (2):367-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   273 citations  
  • Freedom and the rule of law.Matthew H. Kramer - 2011 - In Jerzy Stelmach & Bartosz Brożek (eds.), The normativity of law. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Slaves, Prisoners, and Republican Freedom.Fabian Wendt - 2011 - Res Publica 17 (2):175-192.
    Philip Pettit’s republican conception of freedom is presented as an alternative both to negative and positive conceptions of freedom. The basic idea is to conceptualize freedom as non-domination, not as non-interference or self-mastery. When compared to negative freedom, Pettit’s republican conception comprises two controversial claims: the claim that we are unfree if we are dominated without actual interference, and the claim that we are free if we face interference without domination. Because the slave is a widely accepted paradigm of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Force and freedom: Kant's legal and political philosophy.Arthur Ripstein - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this masterful work, both an illumination of Kant's thought and an important contribution to contemporary legal and political theory, Arthur Ripstein gives a comprehensive yet accessible account of Kant's political philosophy. In addition to providing a clear and coherent statement of the most misunderstood of Kant's ideas, Ripstein also shows that Kant's views remain conceptually powerful and morally appealing today.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Form and Matter in Kantian Political Philosophy: A Reply.Arthur Ripstein - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):487-496.
    This paper responds briefly to four reviews of Force and Freedom. Valentini and Sangiovanni criticize what they see as the excessive formalism of the Kantian enterprise, contending that the Kantian project is circular, because it defines rights and freedom together, and that this circularity renders it unable to say anything determinate about appropriate restrictions and permissions. I show that the appearance of circularity arises from a misconstrual of the Kantian idea of a right. Properly understood, Kantian rights are partially indeterminate, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Instability of Freedom as Noninterference: The Case of Isaiah Berlin.Philip Pettit - 2011 - Ethics 121 (4):693-716.
    In Hobbes, freedom of choice requires nonfrustration: the option you prefer must be accessible. In Berlin, it requires noninterference: every option, preferred or unpreferred, must be accessible—every door must be open. But Berlin’s argument against Hobbes suggests a parallel argument that freedom requires something stronger still: that each option be accessible and that no one have the power to block access; the doors should be open, and there should be no powerful doorkeepers. This is freedom as nondomination. The claim is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon.Philip Pettit - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (3):275-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Symposium on Amartya Sen's philosophy: 1 capability and freedom: A defence of Sen.Philip Pettit - 2001 - Economics and Philosophy 17 (1):1-20.
    In a recent discussion of Amartya Sen's concept of the capabilities of people for functioning in their society – and the idea of targeting people's functioning capabilities in evaluating the society – G. A. Cohen accuses Sen of espousing an inappropriate, ‘athletic’ image of the person (Cohen, 1993, pp. 24–5). The idea is that if Sen's formulations are to be taken at face value, then life is valuable only so far as people actively choose most facets of their existence: if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Negative Liberty, Liberal and Republican1.Philip Pettit - 1993 - European Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):15-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Freedom and probability: A comment on Goodin and Jackson.Philip Pettit - 2008 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (2):206-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Constraints on freedom.David Miller - 1983 - Ethics 94 (1):66-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy.Christopher Mcmahon - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (1):67-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The impossibility of a Paretian republican? Some comments on Pettit and Sen.Christian List - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (1):65-87.
    Philip Pettit (2001) has suggested that there are parallels between his republican account of freedom and Amartya Sen's (1970) account of freedom as decisive preference. In this paper, I discuss these parallels from a social-choice-theoretic perspective. I sketch a formalization of republican freedom and argue that republican freedom is formally very similar to freedom as defined in Sen's “minimal liberalism” condition. In consequence, the republican account of freedom is vulnerable to a version of Sen's liberal paradox, an inconsistency between universal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Republican freedom and the rule of law.Christian List - 2006 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 5 (2):201-220.
    At the core of republican thought, on Philip Pettit’s account, lies the conception of freedom as non-domination, as opposed to freedom as noninterference in the liberal sense. I revisit the distinction between liberal and republican freedom and argue that republican freedom incorporates a particular rule-of-law requirement, whereas liberal freedom does not. Liberals may also endorse such a requirement, but not as part of their conception of freedom itself. I offer a formal analysis of this rule-of-law requirement and compare liberal and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government:Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government.John Christman - 1998 - Ethics 109 (1):202-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Security and Liberty: The Image of Balance.Waldron Jeremy - 2003 - Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (2):191-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Freedom from fear.Robert E. Goodin & Frank Jackson - 2007 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 35 (3):249–265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • A republican right to basic income?Philip Pettit - 2007 - Basic Income Studies 2 (2).
    The basic income proposal provides everyone in a society, as an unconditional right, with access to a certain level of income. Introducing such a right is bound to raise questions of institutional feasibility. Would it lead too many people to opt out of the workforce, for example? And even if it did not, could a constitution that allowed some members of the society to do this – at whatever relative cost – prove acceptable in a society of mutually reciprocal, equally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Republicanism.Frank Lovett - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency.Philip Pettit - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):498-501.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations