Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Gender and race: (What) are they? (What) do we want them to be?Sally Haslanger - 2000 - Noûs 34 (1):31–55.
    It is always awkward when someone asks me informally what I’m working on and I answer that I’m trying to figure out what gender is. For outside a rather narrow segment of the academic world, the term ‘gender’ has come to function as the polite way to talk about the sexes. And one thing people feel pretty confident about is their knowledge of the difference between males and females. Males are those human beings with a range of familiar primary and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   454 citations  
  • The seductions of clarity.C. Thi Nguyen - 2021 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 89:227-255.
    The feeling of clarity can be dangerously seductive. It is the feeling associated with understanding things. And we use that feeling, in the rough-and-tumble of daily life, as a signal that we have investigated a matter sufficiently. The sense of clarity functions as a thought-terminating heuristic. In that case, our use of clarity creates significant cognitive vulnerability, which hostile forces can try to exploit. If an epistemic manipulator can imbue a belief system with an exaggerated sense of clarity, then they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Meaning of Saphêneia in Plato’s Divided Line’.James Lesher - 2010 - In Plato's 'Republic': A Critical Guide. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. pp. 171-187.
    In Republic VI, Plato’s Socrates attempts to explain the nature of human understanding by means of a simile of a line divided into four unequal segments. Socrates directs Glaucon to accept as names for the four states ‘rational knowledge’ for the highest, ‘understanding’ for the second, ‘belief’ for the third, and for the last, ‘perception of images.’ He then directs Glaucon to arrange the four states in a proportion, ‘considering that they participate in saphēneia in the same degree to which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poetry and the Possibility of Paraphrase.Gregory Currie & Jacopo Frascaroli - 2021 - The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 79 (4):428-439.
    Why is there a long-standing debate about paraphrase in poetry? Everyone agrees that paraphrase can be useful; everyone agrees that paraphrase is no substitute for the poem itself. What is there to disagree about? Perhaps this: whether paraphrase can specify everything that counts as a contribution to the meaning of a poem. There are, we say, two ways to take the question; on one way of taking it, the answer is that paraphrase cannot. Does this entail that there is meaning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The new Leviathan.Robin George Collingwood - 1942 - Oxford,: The Clarendon press. Edited by David Boucher.
    The New Leviathan, originally published in 1942, a few months before the author's death, is the book which R. G. Collingwood chose to write in preference to ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • What do philosophers believe?David Bourget & David J. Chalmers - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (3):465-500.
    What are the philosophical views of contemporary professional philosophers? We surveyed many professional philosophers in order to help determine their views on 30 central philosophical issues. This article documents the results. It also reveals correlations among philosophical views and between these views and factors such as age, gender, and nationality. A factor analysis suggests that an individual's views on these issues factor into a few underlying components that predict much of the variation in those views. The results of a metasurvey (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   286 citations  
  • Hegel: Three Studies.Theodor W. Adorno - 1993 - MIT Press.
    Adorno's efforts to salvage the contemporaneity of Hegel's thought form part of his response to the increasingly tight net of social control in the aftermath of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Analytic Philosophy and Cognitive Norms.Pascal Engel - 1999 - The Monist 82 (2):218-234.
    What is the difference between analytic and Continental philosophy? That the former has not withdrawn norms of justification and truth, whereas the latter has bred suspicion about them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The principles of art.R. G. Collingwood - 1938 - New York,: Oxford University Press.
    This treatise on aesthetics criticizes various psychological theories of art, offers new theories and interpretations, and draws important inferences concerning ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Not Thinking Like a Liberal.Raymond Geuss - 2022 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
    Raymond Geuss is a critic of liberalism, a politics so pervasive in the West that it goes unnoticed. His attention sharpened by his own unorthodox intellectual journey, Geuss locates what we fail to see in the status quo: its shallowness and futility. Rejecting both authoritarian horror and liberal complacency, Geuss looks to genuinely new ideas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Living a feminist life.Sara Ahmed - 2017 - Durham: Duke University Press.
    Feminism is sensational -- On being directed -- Willfulness and feminist subjectivity -- Trying to transform -- Being in question -- Brick walls -- Fragile connections -- Feminist snap -- Lesbian feminism -- Conclusion 1: A killjoy survival kit -- Conclusion 2: A killjoy manifesto.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Articulating a Thought.Eli Alshanetsky - 2019 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Eli Alshanetsky considers how we make our thoughts clear to ourselves in the process of putting them into words and examines the paradox of those difficult cases where we do not already know what we are struggling to articulate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The "Analytic"/"Continental" Divide and the Question of Philosophy's Relation to Literature.Andreas Vrahimis - 2019 - Philosophy and Literature 43 (1):253-269.
    The history of the writing of philosophy could be seen as divided between two tendencies. One tendency involves a constant reconfiguration of the literary and stylistic elements involved in the way philosophy is written. Examples include most texts in the philosophical canon, from Plato's dialogues, or Aristotle's lecture notes, to Marcus Aurelius's diary, Augustine's confessions, the pseudepigrapha of the Areopagite, Anselm's prayer, Montaigne's essays, Descartes's meditations, Kierkegaard's play with pseudonymy, or Wittgenstein's "remarks."1 In such texts, we find a self-reflective attitude (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Politics of Clarity.Alison Stone - 2015 - Hypatia 30 (3):613-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On unclear and indistinct ideas.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8:75-100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Clarity in Philosophy.Bryan Magee - 2014 - Philosophy 89 (3):451-462.
    Some philosophy – Wittgenstein's would be an example – is written in clear sentences, yet most people find it obscure at a first reading. This is because the prime location of clarity in philosophy is not sentences but structures. Only if a reader can relate what he is currently reading to a wider framework does he know where he is. Coherent utterance in all discursive media – not only language but mathematics, for example, or music – possesses two kinds of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Saphêneia in Aristotle:'Clarity','Precision', and 'Knowledge'.J. H. Lesher - 2010 - Apeiron 43 (4):143-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Demystifying Mentalities.Geoffrey Ernest Richard Lloyd - 1990 - Cambridge University Press.
    If faraway peoples have different ideas from our own, is this because they have different mentalities? Did our remote ancestors lack logic? The notion of distinct mentalities has been used extensively by historians to describe and explain cultural diversity. Professor Lloyd rejects this psychologising talk of mentalities and proposes an alternative approach, which takes as its starting point the social contexts of communication. Discussing apparently irrational beliefs and behaviour, he shows how different forms of thought coexist in a single culture (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • How Should Philosophy Be Clear? Loaded Clarity, Default Clarity, and Adorno.N. Joll - 2009 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2009 (146):73-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How should philosophy be clear? Loaded clarity, default clarity, and Adorno.Nicholas Joll - 2009 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2009 (146):73–95.
    [First paragraph:] Part of the point of this article is to support the following claim by Adorno: “Rarely has anyone laid out a theory of philosophical clarity; instead, the concept of clarity has been used as though it were self-evident.” In fact, and again with Adorno, I shall argue for what I call the “loadedness thesis”: the thesis that philosophical conceptions of clarity are pervasively, and perhaps inevitably, philosophically partisan (section one). Yet I shall proceed to argue for a conception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Stance and engagement: a model of interaction in academic discourse.Ken Hyland - 2005 - Discourse Studies 7 (2):173-192.
    A great deal of research has now established that written texts embody interactions between writers and readers. A range of linguistic features have been identified as contributing to the writer's projection of a stance to the material referenced by the text, and, to a lesser extent, the strategies employed to presuppose the active role of an addressee. As yet, however, there is no overall typology of the resources writers employ to express their positions and connect with readers. Based on an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Looking Again at Clarity in Philosophy: Writing as a Shaper and Sharpener of Thought.Valerie Hobbs - 2015 - Philosophy 90 (1):135-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Analogical Investigations: Historical and Cross-Cultural Perspectives on Human Reasoning.G. E. R. Lloyd - 2015 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Western philosophy and science are responsible for constructing some powerful tools of investigation, aiming at discovering the truth, delivering robust explanations, verifying conjectures, showing that inferences are sound and demonstrating results conclusively. By contrast reasoning that depends on analogies has often been viewed with suspicion. Professor Lloyd first explores the origins of those Western ideals, criticises some of their excesses and redresses the balance in favour of looser, admittedly non-demonstrative analogical reasoning. For this he takes examples both from ancient Greek (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Mind, history, and dialectic: the philosophy of R.G. Collingwood.Louis O. Mink - 1969 - Scranton, Pa.: Harper & Row.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Question Concerning Technology, and Other Essays.Martin Heidegger - 1977 - New York: Harper & Row.
    The question concerning technology.--The turning.--The word of Nietzsche: "God is dead."--The age of the world picture.--Science and reflection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   455 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's private language: grammar, nonsense, and imagination in Philosophical investigations, sections 243-315.Stephen Mulhall - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Stephen Mulhall offers a new way of interpreting one of the most famous and contested texts in modern philosophy: remarks on "private language" in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. He sheds new light on a central controversy concerning Wittgenstein's early work by showing its relevance to a proper understanding of the later work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • How to make our ideas clear.C. S. Peirce - 1878 - Popular Science Monthly 12 (Jan.):286-302.
    This is one of the seminal articles of the pragmatist tradition where C.S. Peirce sets out his doctrine of doubt and belief --and their relationship to inquiry and clarity of our concepts. Originally published in the Popular Science Monthly; and widely available in reprints and collections of Peirce's writings.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   247 citations  
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Us 'Typical Western Scientists'.Alois Pichler - 2016 - In Sebastian Sunday Grève & J. Mácha (eds.), Wittgenstein and the Creativity of Language. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
    This piece continues my efforts to identify the link between the Philosophical Investigations’ criss-cross form and its conception of philosophy and philosophical methods. In my ‘The Philosophical Investigations and Syncretistic Writing’ I established a connection between the PI’s criss-cross form and Wittgenstein’s saying that philosophy proper is like ‘Dichtung’. In this chapter I link the criss-cross form with the PI’s conception of the example and the central role it receives in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. I contrast the PI’s conception of philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Nietzsche: Life as Literature.Alexander Nehamas - 1985 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 21 (3):240-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • To School with the Poets: Philosophy, Method and Clarity.Smith Richard - 2008 - Paedagogica Historica 44:635-645.
    There is a longstanding difficulty in distinguishing philosophy (and philosophy of education) from other kinds of writing. Even the notions of clarity and rigour, sometimes claimed as central and defining characteristics of philosophy at its best, turn out to have ineliminably figurative elements, and accounts of philosophical method often display the very rhetoricity that they describe philosophy as concerned to avoid. It is tempting to wonder how far notions of philosophy as austere and analytic are responsible for ideals of educational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Essay on Philosophical Method.R. G. Collingwood - 1934 - Philosophy 9 (35):350-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Principles of Art.R. G. Collingwood - 1938 - Philosophy 13 (52):492-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • This Is Art: A Defence of R. G. Collingwood's Philosophy of Art.James Camien McGuiggan - 2017 - Dissertation, University of Southampton
    R. G. Collingwood’s 'The Principles of Art' argues that art is the expression of emotion. This dissertation offers a new interpretation of that philosophy, and argues that this interpretation is both hermeneutically and philosophically plausible. The offered interpretation differs from the received interpretation most significantly in treating the concept of ‘art’ as primarily scalarly rather than binarily realisable (this is introduced in ch. 1), and in understanding Collingwood’s use of the term ‘emotion’ more broadly (introduced in ch. 2). -/- After (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Collingwood on Philosophical Literary Language.Niklas Forsberg - 2012 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 18 (1):31-64.
    Focusing on the penultimate chapter of Collingwood's An Essay on Philosophical Method, this paper offers a re-evaluation of several points in leading interpretations of his philosophy. It is argued that this chapter, 'Philosophy as a Branch of Literature', invites us to rethink the relation between a systematic or problem-oriented and an historical or exegetical philosophy; how linguistic analysis (particularly in the form of ordinary language philosophy) relates to the history of philosophy; and how the question of literature in philosophy is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation