Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)The Principles of Psychology.William James - 1890 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 11 (3):506-507.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1425 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Principles of Psychology.William James - 1890 - The Monist 1:284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1643 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Principles of Psychology.William James - 1891 - International Journal of Ethics 1 (2):143-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   709 citations  
  • Verbal reports as data.K. Anders Ericsson & Herbert A. Simon - 1980 - Psychological Review 87 (3):215-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   257 citations  
  • (1 other version)Implicit learning and tacit knowledge.Arthur S. Reber - 1989 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118 (3):219-235.
    I examine the phenomenon of implicit learning, the process by which knowledge about the rule-governed complexities of the stimulus environment is acquired independently of conscious attempts to do so. Our research with the two seemingly disparate experimental paradigms of synthetic grammar learning and probability learning, is reviewed and integrated with other approaches to the general problem of unconscious cognition. The conclusions reached are as follows: Implicit learning produces a tacit knowledge base that is abstract and representative of the structure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Feelings in the Fringe.Katharine McGovern - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):119-125.
    The Jamesian notion of fringe consciousness as elaborated by Mangan provides a theoretical motivation for drawing together a diverse class of experiences which are called "feelings" in everyday language. Thus, feelings of knowing and emotional feelings are seen not to differ in kind from each other. Further, both kinds of feelings are seen to reflect the consonance or dissonance of current conscious experience with unconscious contexts and may be used as "handles" to draw unconscious material into consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The neural-cognitive basis of the Jamesian stream of thought.Russell Epstein - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (4):550-575.
    William James described the stream of thought as having two components: (1) a nucleus of highly conscious, often perceptual material; and (2) a fringe of dimly felt contextual information that controls the entry of information into the nucleus and guides the progression of internally directed thought. Here I examine the neural and cognitive correlates of this phenomenology. A survey of the cognitive neuroscience literature suggests that the nucleus corresponds to a dynamic global buffer formed by interactions between different regions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Taking phenomenology seriously: The "fringe" and its implication for cognitive research.Bruce Mangan - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):89-108.
    Evidence and theory ranging from traditional philosophy to contemporary cognitive research support the hypothesis that consciousness has a two-part structure: a focused region of articulated experience surrounded by a field of relatively unarticulated, vague experience.William James developed an especially useful phenomenological analysis of this "fringe" of consciousness, but its relation to, and potential value for, the study of cognition has not been explored. I propose strengthening James′ work on the fringe with a functional analysis: fringe experiences work to radically condense (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Implicit learning: Below the subjective threshold.Zoltán Dienes & Dianne C. Berry - 1997 - Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 4:3-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Conscious and unconscious perception: An approach to the relations between phenomenal experience and perceptual processes.Anthony J. Marcel - 1983 - Cognitive Psychology 15:238-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Subliminal mere exposure effects.Robert F. Bornstein - 1992 - In Robert F. Bornstein & Thane S. Pittman (eds.), Perception Without Awareness: Cognitive, Clinical, and Social Perspectives. Guilford.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Sensation's ghost: The nonsensory fringe of consciousness.Bruce Mangan - 2001 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7.
    Non-sensory experiences represent almost all context information in consciousness. They condition most aspects of conscious cognition including voluntary retrieval, perception, monitoring, problem solving, emotion, evaluation, meaning recognition. Many peculiar aspects of non-sensory qualia (e.g., they resist being 'grasped' by an act of attention) are explained as adaptations shaped by the cognitive functions they serve. The most important nonsensory experience is coherence or "rightness." Rightness represents degrees of context fit among contents in consciousness, and between conscious and non-conscious processes. Rightness (not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • What Feeling Is the “Feeling of Knowing?”.Bruce Mangan - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (4):538-544.
    Rightness, not familiarity, is the feeling of knowing. Rightness and familiarity are distinct at both the functional and phenomenological levels of analysis. In problem solving, for example, an unfamiliar solution can still feel right. Rightness is the fringe experience permeating all cases of felt meaning in consciousness, and can occur even when the retrieval of specific content is for whatever reason blocked (e.g., in a tip of the tongue experience). For the most extensive published treatment of rightness and fringe experience, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Memory and the feeling-of-knowing experience.J. T. Hart - 1965 - Journal of Educational Psychology 56:208-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Conscious experience is one of the most difficult and thorny problems in psychological science. Its study has been neglected for many years, either because it was thought to be too difficult, or because the relevant evidence was thought to be poor. Bernard Baars suggests a way to specify empirical constraints on a theory of consciousness by contrasting well-established conscious phenomena - such as stimulus representations known to be attended, perceptual, and informative - with closely comparable unconscious ones - such as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   549 citations  
  • The functions of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   559 citations  
  • Novelty monitoring, metacognition, and control in a composite holographic associative recall model: Implications for Korsakoff amnesia.Janet Metcalfe - 1993 - Psychological Review 100 (1):3-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Putting the Focus on the Fringe: Three Empirical Cases.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):126-136.
    After suggesting an operational definition for fringe experiences—as opposed to clearly conscious and clearly unconscious phenomena—we examine three empirical cases: The tip-of-the-tongue experience, the fringe experience of "wrongness," and the case of conscious focus on abstract, hard-to-image conscious contents. In each case, Mangan′s four major claims are explored in some detail. Most tasks seem to involve a combination of conscious experiences, complex unconscious representations, and multiple fringe experiences. The chief disagreement from this analysis involves vague experiences that are generally believed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How to differentiate implicit and explicit modes of acquisition.Arthur S. Reber - 1997 - In Jonathan D. Cohen & Jonathan W. Schooler (eds.), Scientific Approaches to Consciousness. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 137--159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Implicit learning and tacit knowledge.Arthur S. Reber - 1989 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 118:219-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   189 citations  
  • The structure of awareness: Contemporary applications of William James' forgotten concept of "the fringe".David Galin - 1994 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 15 (4):375-401.
    Modern psychology does not address the great variety of elements constituting subjective experience or the relations among them. This essay examines ideas on the fine structure of awareness and suggests a more precisely characterized set of variables, useful to all psychologists interested in awareness, whether their focus is on computer simulation, neuroscience, or clinical intervention. This view builds on William James' insight into the qualitative differences among the parts of subjective experience, a concept nearly forgotten until recently reinterpreted in contemporary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The "tip of the tongue" phenomenon.R. Brown & David N. McNeill - 1966 - Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 5:325-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations