Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Truth and objectivity.Crispin Wright - 1992 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Recasting important questions about truth and objectivity in new and helpful terms, his book will become a focus in the contemporary debates over realism, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   728 citations  
  • Wise choices, apt feelings: a theory of normative judgment.Allan Gibbard - 1990 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    This book examines some of the deepest questions in philosophy: What is involved in judging a belief, action, or feeling to be rational?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   685 citations  
  • (1 other version)Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Clarendon Press.
    Provides a comprehensive introduction to the major philosophical theories attempting to explain the workings of language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   552 citations  
  • Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Simon Blackburn puts forward a compelling original philosophy of human motivation and morality. He maintains that we cannot get clear about ethics until we get clear about human nature. So these are the sorts of questions he addresses: Why do we behave as we do? Can we improve? Is our ethics at war with our passions, or is it an upshot of those passions? Blackburn seeks the answers in an exploration of guilt, shame, disgust, and other moral emotions; he draws (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   345 citations  
  • Essays in quasi-realism.Simon Blackburn - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This volume collects some influential essays in which Simon Blackburn, one of our leading philosophers, explores one of the most profound and fertile of philosophical problems: the way in which our judgments relate to the world. This debate has centered on realism, or the view that what we say is validated by the way things stand in the world, and a variety of oppositions to it. Prominent among the latter are expressive and projective theories, but also a relaxed pluralism that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   333 citations  
  • Wise Choices, Apt Feelings.Alan Gibbard - 1990 - Ethics 102 (2):342-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   887 citations  
  • Thinking How to Live.Allan Gibbard - 2003 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Philosophers have long suspected that thought and discourse about what we ought to do differ in some fundamental way from statements about what is. But the difference has proved elusive, in part because the two kinds of statement look alike. Focusing on judgments that express decisions--judgments about what is to be done, all things considered--Allan Gibbard offers a compelling argument for reconsidering, and reconfiguring, the distinctions between normative and descriptive discourse--between questions of "ought" and "is." Gibbard considers how our actions, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   283 citations  
  • Being for: evaluating the semantic program of expressivism.Mark Andrew Schroeder - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Mark Schroeder.
    Expressivism - the sophisticated contemporary incarnation of the noncognitivist research program of Ayer, Stevenson, and Hare - is no longer the province of metaethicists alone. Its comprehensive view about the nature of both normative language and normative thought has also recently been applied to many topics elsewhere in philosophy - including logic, probability, mental and linguistic content, knowledge, epistemic modals, belief, the a priori, and even quantifiers. Yet the semantic commitments of expressivism are still poorly understood and have not been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Assertion.Peter Geach - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (4):449-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   374 citations  
  • Ruling Passions.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - Philosophy 75 (293):454-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   562 citations  
  • Thinking How to Live.Allan Gibbard - 2004 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2):381-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   499 citations  
  • Truth and Objectivity.Crispin Wright - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4):883-890.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   421 citations  
  • On the aim of belief.David Velleman - 1996 - In J. David Velleman, The Possibility of Practical Reason. Monograph Collection (Matt - Pseudo). pp. 244--81.
    This paper explores the sense in which belief "aims at the truth". In this course of this exploration, it discusses the difference between belief and make-believe, the nature of psychoanalytic explanation, the supposed "normativity of meaning", and related topics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   246 citations  
  • The emotive meaning of ethical terms.Charles Leslie Stevenson - 1937 - Mind 46 (181):14-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essays on Quasi-Realism.Simon Blackburn - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (186):96-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   357 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Mind 94 (374):310-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   357 citations  
  • The Guise of the Good.J. David Velleman - 1992 - Noûs 26 (1):3 - 26.
    The agent portrayed in much philosophy of action is, let's face it, a square. He does nothing intentionally unless he regards it or its consequences as desirable. The reason is that he acts intentionally only when he acts out of a desire for some anticipated outcome; and in desiring that outcome, he must regard it as having some value. All of his intentional actions are therefore directed at outcomes regarded sub specie boni: under the guise of the good. This agent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Spreading the world.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 176 (3):385-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   330 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essays in Quasi-Realism.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - Noûs 32 (3):386-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   315 citations  
  • Morals and Modals.Simon Blackburn - 1993 - In Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  • Hybrid Expressivism: Virtues and Vices.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Ethics 119 (2):257-309.
    This paper is a survey of recent ‘hybrid’ approaches to metaethics, according to which moral sentences, in some sense or other, express both beliefs and desires. I try to show what kinds of theoretical issues come up at the different choice points we encounter in developing such a view, to raise some problems and explain where they come from, and to begin to get a sense for what the payoff of such views can be, and what they will need to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (2):211-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Ecumenical expressivism: Finessing Frege.Michael Ridge - 2006 - Ethics 116 (2):302-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Direction of fit.I. Lloyd Humberstone - 1992 - Mind 101 (401):59-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • How Expressivists Can and Should Solve Their Problem with Negation.Mark Schroeder - 2008 - Noûs 42 (4):573-599.
    Expressivists have a problem with negation. The problem is that they have not, to date, been able to explain why ‘murdering is wrong’ and ‘murdering is not wrong’ are inconsistent sentences. In this paper, I explain the nature of the problem, and why the best efforts of Gibbard, Dreier, and Horgan and Timmons don’t solve it. Then I show how to diagnose where the problem comes from, and consequently how it is possible for expressivists to solve it. Expressivists should accept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Cognitivist expressivism.Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons - 2006 - In Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons, Metaethics After Moore. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 255--298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Attitudes and contents.Simon Blackburn - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):501-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • (1 other version)Extreme and restricted utilitarianism.J. J. C. Smart - 1956 - Philosophical Quarterly 6 (25):344-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Moral realism.Simon Blackburn - 1971 - In John Casey, Morality and Moral Reasoning : Five Essays in Ethics. London,: Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Quasi-realism, negation and the Frege-Geach problem.Nicholas Unwin - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196):337-352.
    Expressivists, such as Blackburn, analyse sentences such as 'S thinks that it ought to be the case that p' as S hoorays that p'. A problem is that the former sentence can be negated in three different ways, but the latter in only two. The distinction between refusing to accept a moral judgement and accepting its negation therefore cannot be accounted for. This is shown to undermine Blackburn's solution to the Frege-Geach problem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Metaethics After Moore.Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons (eds.) - 2006 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Metaethics, understood as a distinct branch of ethics, is often traced to G. E. Moore's 1903 classic, Principia Ethica. Whereas normative ethics is concerned to answer first order moral questions about what is good and bad, right and wrong, metaethics is concerned to answer second order non-moral questions about the semantics, metaphysics, and epistemology of moral thought and discourse. Moore has continued to exert a powerful influence, and the sixteen essays here represent the most up-to-date work in metaethics after, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Meaning and speech acts.R. M. Hare - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (1):3-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Meaning and speech acts.John R. Searle - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (4):423-432.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Realism, Antirealism, Irrealism, Quasi-Realism.Crispin Wright - 1988 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1):25-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • (1 other version)How to Be an Ethical Antirealist.Simon Blackburn - 1988 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1):361-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Antirealist expressivism and quasi-realism.Simon Blackburn - 2006 - In David Copp, The Oxford handbook of ethical theory. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 146--162.
    Expressivism is the view that the function of normative sentences is not to represent a kind of fact, but to avow attitudes, prescribe behavior, or the like. The idea can be found in David Hume. In the 20th century, G.E. Moore’s Open Question Argument provided important support for the view. Elizabeth Anscombe introduced the notion of “direction of fit,” which helped distinguish expressivism from a kind of naive subjectivism. The central advantage of expressivism is that it easily explains the motivational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • (1 other version)Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism.J. J. C. Smart - 1998 - In James Rachels, Ethical Theory 2: Theories About How We Should Live. Oxford University Press UK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Modus ponens and moral realism.G. F. Schueler - 1988 - Ethics 98 (3):492-500.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • (1 other version)Negation for Expressivists: A Collection of Problems with a Suggestion for their Solution.James Dreier - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1:217-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Can there be a Logic of Attitudes?Bob Hale - 1993 - In John Haldane & Crispin Wright, Reality, representation, and projection. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 337--63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Free Thinking for Expressivists.Neil Sinclair - 2008 - Philosophical Papers 37 (2):263-287.
    This paper elaborates and defends an expressivist account of the claims of mind-independence embedded in ordinary moral thought. In response to objections from Zangwill and Jenkins it is argued that the expressivist 'internal reading' of such claims is compatible with their conceptual status and that the only 'external reading' available doesn't commit expressivisists to any sort of subjectivism. In the process a 'commitment-theoretic' account of the semantics of conditionals and negations is defended.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Negation for expressivists: a collection of problems with a suggestion for their solution.James Dreier - 2006 - In Russ Shafer-Landau, Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 1. Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Can Arboreal Knotwork Help Blackburn out of Frege's Abyss?Bob Hale - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1):144-149.
    An early objection to Simon Blackburn’s first attempts to breathe new life into expressivism—by solving the Frege-Geach problem—was that whilst viewing compound sentences featuring moral components as expressive of attitudes towards combinations of attitudes might enable one to make out that a thinker who, to take the usual example, asserts the premisses but will not accept the conclusion of a moral modus ponens is at fault because they are involved in a “clash of attitudes”, this does no justice to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Why emotivists love inconsistency.Gunnar Björnsson - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 104 (1):81 - 108.
    Emotivists hold that moral opinions are wishes and desires, and that the function of moral language is to “express” such states. But if moral opinions were but wishes or desires, why would we see certain opinions as inconsistent with, or following from other opinions? And why should our reasoning include complex opinions such as the opinion that a person ought to be blamed only if he has done something wrong? Indeed, why would we think that anything is conditional on his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Truth and the expressing in expressivism.Stephen Barker - 2006 - In Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons, Metaethics After Moore. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Spreading the Word. [REVIEW]Kent Bach - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (1):120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Replies.Simon Blackburn - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1):164–176.
    Dreier’s sympathy with expressivism is welcome, and yet he comes upon an ‘uncomfortable surprise’, in a circularity or regress that he detects in my attempt to place ethical commitments in a natural world. The circularity is that the expressivist analysis of what is going on, when we invoke norms, identifies particular states of mind: valuings, or acceptance of norms, or complexes of attitude. But states of mind are themselves normatively tainted. Hence: ‘the kernel of expressivist analysis invokes normative concepts’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The guise of the good.David Velleman - 1992 - Noûs 26 (1):3–26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • BLACKBURN, S.-Ruling Passions.T. Baldwin, F. Jackson, S. Svavarsdottir & S. Blackburn - 2001 - Philosophical Books 42 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Being for: Evaluating the semantic program of expressivism * by mark Schroeder * clarendon press, 2008. XVI + 198 pp. {pound}27.50: Summary. [REVIEW]Mark Schroeder - 2010 - Analysis 70 (1):101-104.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations