Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?Colin McGinn - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • (1 other version)Minds, Brains, and Programs.John Searle - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   666 citations  
  • Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.Ned Block - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):615-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   352 citations  
  • The Imagery Debate.Alastair Hannay - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (171):246-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Descartes's Method of Doubt.Janet Broughton & Joseph Almog - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (212):437-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Tractatus logico-philosophicus.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1922 - Filosoficky Casopis 52:336-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1919 citations  
  • Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid. [REVIEW]Catherine Wilson - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (1):105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Problems of Philosophy.Bertrand Russell - 1912 - Mind 21 (84):556-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   811 citations  
  • (1 other version)Descartes' Philosophy of Science.Margaret Morrison - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (1):140-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man.Thomas Reid - 1785 - University Park, Pa.: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Derek R. Brookes & Knud Haakonssen.
    Thomas Reid was a philosopher who founded the Scottish school of 'common sense'. Much of Reid's work is a critique of his contemporary, David Hume, whose empiricism he rejects. In this work, written after Reid's appointment to a professorship at the university of Glasgow, and published in 1785, he turns his attention to ideas about perception, memory, conception, abstraction, judgement, reasoning and taste. He examines the work of his predecessors and contemporaries, arguing that 'when we find philosophers maintaining that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   500 citations  
  • Review of Cummins' Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. [REVIEW]Frances Egan - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):118.
    “Naturalistic” semantic theories attempt to specify, in nonintentional and nonsemantic terms, a sufficient condition for a mental representation’s having a particular meaning. Such theories have trouble accounting for the possibility of representational error. In his latest book, Robert Cummins traces the problem to the fact that the theories currently on offer identify the meaning of a representation with certain features of its use. Only a theory that takes meaning to be an intrinsic feature of a representation, Cummins argues, can both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Why should analytic philosophers do history of philosophy?John Cottingham - 2005 - In Tom Sorell & Graham Alan John Rogers (eds.), Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 25-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Laudan's Progress and Its ProblemsProgress and Its Problems. Larry Laudan.Ernan McMullin - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (4):623-644.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   294 citations  
  • (1 other version)Why Isn't There More Progress in Philosophy?David J. Chalmers - 2015 - Philosophy 90 (1):3-31.
    Is there progress in philosophy? A glass-half-full view is that there is some progress in philosophy. A glass-half-empty view is that there is not as much as we would like. I articulate a version of the glass-half-empty view, argue for it, and then address the crucial question of what explains it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature[REVIEW]Alvin I. Goldman - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (3):424-429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   642 citations  
  • Ideas and Mechanism: Essays on Early Modern Philosophy.Margaret Dauler Wilson - 1999 - Princeton University Press.
    IDEAS. and. MECHANISM. Essays on Early Modern Philosophy MARGARET DAULER WILSON For more than three decades, Margaret Wilson's essays on early modern philosophy have influenced scholarly debate. Many are considered  ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Newcomb’s problem and two principles of choice.Robert Nozick - 1970 - In Carl G. Hempel, Donald Davidson & Nicholas Rescher (eds.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht,: D. Reidel. pp. 114–46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • On the Gettier problem problem.William G. Lycan - 2006 - In Stephen Cade Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology futures. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 148--168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The Turning Point in Philosophy.Moritz Schlick - 1930 - In . pp. 53--59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • There Is No Progress in Philosophy.Eric Dietrich - 2011 - Essays in Philosophy 12 (2):9.
    Except for a patina of twenty-first century modernity, in the form of logic and language, philosophy is exactly the same now as it ever was; it has made no progress whatsoever. We philosophers wrestle with the exact same problems the Pre-Socratics wrestled with. Even more outrageous than this claim, though, is the blatant denial of its obvious truth by many practicing philosophers. The No-Progress view is explored and argued for here. Its denial is diagnosed as a form of anosognosia, a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Edmund L. Gettier - 1963 - Analysis 23 (6):121-123.
    Edmund Gettier is Professor Emeritus at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst. This short piece, published in 1963, seemed to many decisively to refute an otherwise attractive analysis of knowledge. It stimulated a renewed effort, still ongoing, to clarify exactly what knowledge comprises.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1231 citations  
  • Situated action: A neuropsychological interpretation.William J. Clancey - forthcoming - Philosophical Explorations.
    Symbols in computer programs are not necessarily isomorphic in form or capability to neural processes. Representations in our models are stored descriptions of the world and human behavior, created by a human interpreter; representations in the brain are neither immutable forms nor encoded in some language. Although the term " symbol " can be usefully applied to describe words, smoke signals, neural maps, and graphic icons, a science of symbol processing requires distinguishing between the structural, developmental, and interactive nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Dialogues with the dead.Edwin Curley - 1986 - Synthese 67 (1):33 - 49.
    Serious work in history of philosophy requires doing something very difficult: conducting a hypothetical dialogue with dead philosophers. Is it worth devoting to it the time and energy required to do it well? Yes. Quite apart from the intrinsic interest of understanding the past, making progress toward solving philosophical problems requires a good grasp of the range of possible solutions to those problems and of the arguments which motivate alternative positions, a grasp we can only have if we understand well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The inescapability of Gettier problems.Linda Zagzebski - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174):65-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   198 citations  
  • (1 other version)History of philosophy in philosophy today; and the case of the sensible qualities.Margaret D. Wilson - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (1):191-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Sense, nonsense, and the senses: An inquiry into the powers of the human mind.Hilary Putnam - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy 91 (9):445-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • (1 other version)Epiphenomenal qualia.Frank Jackson - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (April):127-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1274 citations  
  • The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Tim van Gelder - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):615-28.
    According to the dominant computational approach in cognitive science, cognitive agents are digital computers; according to the alternative approach, they are dynamical systems. This target article attempts to articulate and support the dynamical hypothesis. The dynamical hypothesis has two major components: the nature hypothesis (cognitive agents are dynamical systems) and the knowledge hypothesis (cognitive agents can be understood dynamically). A wide range of objections to this hypothesis can be rebutted. The conclusion is that cognitive systems may well be dynamical systems, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  • Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist challenge in cognitive science.William Bechtel - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):295-317.
    Advocates of dynamical systems theory (DST) sometimes employ revolutionary rhetoric. In an attempt to clarify how DST models differ from others in cognitive science, I focus on two issues raised by DST: the role for representations in mental models and the conception of explanation invoked. Two features of representations are their role in standing-in for features external to the system and their format. DST advocates sometimes claim to have repudiated the need for stand-ins in DST models, but I argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • (1 other version)Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1772 citations  
  • The imagery debate: Analog media vs. tacit knowledge.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Psychological Review 88 (December):16-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Descartes’s Dualism.Marleen Rozemond - 1998 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In her first book, Marleen Rozemond explicates Descartes's aim to provide a metaphysics that would accommodate mechanistic science and supplant scholasticism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The adverbial approach to visual experience.Michael Tye - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (April):195-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Misrepresentation.Fred Dretske - 1986 - In Radu J. Bogdan (ed.), Belief: Form, Content, and Function. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 17--36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   272 citations  
  • Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap.Joseph Levine - 1983 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 (October):354-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   739 citations  
  • (5 other versions)What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (4):435-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2289 citations  
  • (5 other versions)What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: a guide and anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   691 citations  
  • Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness.Daniel Dennett - 2016 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 (11-12):65-72.
    Using a parallel with stage magic, it is argued that far from being seen as an extreme alternative, illusionism as articulated by Frankish should be considered the front runner, a conservative theory to be developed in detail, and abandoned only if it demonstrably fails to account for phenomena, not prematurely dismissed as 'counterintuitive'. We should explore the mundane possibilities thoroughly before investing in any magical hypotheses.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (3 other versions)An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.John Locke - 1979 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 169 (2):221-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   713 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Perceptual Acquaintance: From Descartes to Reid.John Yolton - 1988 - Synthese 77 (3):409-413.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)Perception and Reality: A History from Descartes to Kant.Nancy Kendrick & John W. Yolton - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (2):332.
    This book does several things, and it does them all well. Yolton firmly contextualizes the debates about perception within the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, while showing how these debates are often repeated in contemporary philosophy of mind. Along the way, he provides novel interpretations of Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant that are clearly and convincingly presented. Perhaps the most important feature of his treatment is that it so vividly shows the Moderns grappling with issues about perception that continue to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas. [REVIEW]Thomas M. Lennon - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):644-647.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Indexical Expressions. Y. Bar-Hillel - 1954 - Mind 63:359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Descartes: An Intellectual Biography by Stephen Gaukroger. [REVIEW]Steven Nadler - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (2):101-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On True and False Ideas.Antoine Arnauld & Stephen Gaukroger - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):849-851.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Man on His Nature.H. B. Adelmann - 1942 - Philosophical Review 51 (2):227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   155 citations  
  • Malebranche’s Theory of the Soul: A Cartesian Interpretation.Fred Ablondi & Tad M. Schmaltz - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (2):334.
    While there has been a resurgence in Malebranche scholarship in the anglophone world over the last twenty years, most of it has focused on Malebranche’s theory of ideas, and little attention has been paid to his philosophy of mind. Schmaltz’s book thus comes as a welcome addition to the Malebranche literature; that he has given us such a well-researched and carefully argued study is even more welcome. The focus of this work is Malebranche’s split with Descartes on the question of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology.James van Cleve - 2004 - Mind 113 (450):405-416.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The breakdown of cartesian metaphysics.Richard A. Watson - 1963 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 (2):177-197.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Breakdown of C i M phy " artes an eta sacs RICHARD A. WATSON WITHIN CARTESIANISMthere arose many problems deriving from conflicts between Cartesian principles. Inadequate attempts to solve these problems were crucial reasons for the breakdown of Cartesian metaphysics in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. The major difficulties derived from the acceptance of a dualism of substances seated in a system which included epistemological and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Descartes's Dualism.Steven Nadler, Gordon Baker & Katherine Morris - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):157-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations