Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science.Davis Baird - 1988 - Noûs 22 (2):299-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • History, Philosophy, and the Central Metaphor.Peter Galison - 1988 - Science in Context 2 (1):197-212.
    The ArgumentBehind the dispute over the relative priority of theory and experiment lie conflicting philosophical images of the nature of scientific inquiry. One crucial image arose in the 1920s, when the logical positivists agitated for a “unity of science” that would ground all meaningful scientific activity on an observational foundation. Their goals and rhetoric dovetailed with the larger movements of architectural, literary, and philosophical modernism. Historians of science followed the positivists by tracking experimental science as the basis for scientific progress. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate.Larry Laudan - 1984 - University of California Press.
    Laudan constructs a fresh approach to a longtime problem for the philosopher of science: how to explain the simultaneous and widespread presence of both agreement and disagreement in science. Laudan critiques the logical empiricists and the post-positivists as he stresses the need for centrality and values and the interdependence of values, methods, and facts as prerequisites to solving the problems of consensus and dissent in science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   377 citations  
  • Progress or Rationality? The Prospects for Normative Naturalism.Larry Laudan - 1987 - American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1):19 - 31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • (1 other version)The quest for certainty: a study of the relation of knowledge and action.John Dewey - 1929 - New York,: Putnam.
    John Dewey's Gifford Lectures, given at Edinburgh in 1929.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas Samuel Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Otto Neurath.
    A scientific community cannot practice its trade without some set of received beliefs. These beliefs form the foundation of the "educational initiation that prepares and licenses the student for professional practice". The nature of the "rigorous and rigid" preparation helps ensure that the received beliefs are firmly fixed in the student's mind. Scientists take great pains to defend the assumption that scientists know what the world is like...To this end, "normal science" will often suppress novelties which undermine its foundations. Research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2709 citations  
  • Progress and its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth.Larry Laudan - 1977 - University of California Press.
    (This insularity was further promoted by the guileless duplicity of scholars in other fields, who were all too prepared to bequeath "the problem of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   636 citations  
  • Kuhn’s Epistemological Relativism: An Interpretation and Defense.Gerald Doppelt - 1978 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 21 (1-4):33 – 86.
    This article attempts to develop a rational reconstruction of Kuhn's epistemological relativism which effectively defends it against an influential line of criticism in the work of Shapere and Scheffler. Against the latter's reading of Kuhn, it is argued (1) that it is the incommensurability of scientific problems, data, and standards, not that of scientific meanings which primarily grounds the relativism argument; and (2) that Kuhnian incommensurability is compatible with far greater epistemological continuity from one theory to another than is implied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
    Thomas S. Kuhn's classic book is now available with a new index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4756 citations  
  • The concept of observation in science and philosophy.Dudley Shapere - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (4):485-525.
    Through a study of a sophisticated contemporary scientific experiment, it is shown how and why use of the term 'observation' in reference to that experiment departs from ordinary and philosophical usages which associate observation epistemically with perception. The role of "background information" is examined, and general conclusions are arrived at regarding the use of descriptive language in and in talking about science. These conclusions bring out the reasoning by which science builds on what it has learned, and, further, how that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Normative naturalism and the role of philosophy.Alexander Rosenberg - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (1):34-43.
    The prescriptive force of methodological rules rests, I argue, on the acceptance of scientific theories; that of the most general methodological rules rests on theories in the philosophy of science, which differ from theories in the several sciences only in generality and abstraction. I illustrate these claims by reference to methodological disputes in social science and among philosophers of science. My conclusions substantiate those of Laudan except that I argue for the existence of transtheoretical goals common to all scientists and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Recent Work on Naturalized Epistemology.James Maffie - 1990 - American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (4):281 - 293.
    Continuity lies at the heart of the recent naturalistic turn in epistemology. Naturalists are united by a shared commitment to the continuity of science and epistemology, and tend to advocate one or more species of continuity: contextual, semantic, epistemological methodological, metaphysical, and axiological. Naturalists divide, however, over the interpretation and scope of this continuity. The naturalism of Goldman, Kim and Sosa is criticised for leaving meta-epistemology methodologically and epistemologically autonomous from science. A more plausible approach naturalizes epistemology 'all the way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • (1 other version)What Pragmatism Is.Charles S. Peirce - 1905 - The Monist 15 (2):161-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth.L. Laudan - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32 (1):57-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   251 citations  
  • Multiple Constraints, Simultaneous Solutions.Peter Galison - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:157 - 163.
    In the 1960s, the history and philosophy of science made common cause in the search for universal patterns of theory change: philosophers provided models, historians offered examples. But the two enterprises pulled apart during the 1970s. Now there is a new arena of joint concern. Historians and philosophers are searching for the conditions under which standards of theoretical and experimental demonstration are established. I argue against the picture of these standards as independent of (or reducible to) the context of their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Two dogmas of methodology.Larry Laudan - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (4):585-597.
    This paper argues that it has been widely assumed by philosophers of science that the cumulative retention of explanatory success is a "sine qua non" for making judgements about the progress or rational preferability of one theory over another. It has also been assumed that it is impossible to make objective, Comparative judgements of the acceptability of rival theories unless all the statements of both theories could be translated into a common language. This paper seeks to show that both these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The value of a fixed methodology. [REVIEW]John Worrall - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (2):263-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The new Organon.Francis Bacon - 2007 - In Aloysius Martinich, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Early Modern Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
    When the New Organon appeared in 1620, part of a six-part programme of scientific inquiry entitled 'The Great Renewal of Learning', Francis Bacon was at the high point of his political career, and his ambitious work was groundbreaking in its attempt to give formal philosophical shape to a new and rapidly emerging experimentally-based science. Bacon combines theoretical scientific epistemology with examples from applied science, examining phenomena as various as magnetism, gravity, and the ebb and flow of the tides, and anticipating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Relativism and the reticulational model of scientific rationality.Gerald Doppelt - 1986 - Synthese 69 (2):225 - 252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Fix it and be damned: A reply to Laudan.John Worrall - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (3):376-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Renormalizing epistemology.Jarrett Leplin - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (1):20-33.
    The fact that the goals and methods of science, as well as its empirical conclusions, are subject to change, is shown to allow at once for: (a) the objectivity of warrant for knowledge claims; (b) the absence of a priori standards from epistemology; (c) the normative character of epistemology; and (d) the rationality of axiological innovation. In particular, Laudan's attempt to make axiological constraints undercut epistemic realism is confuted.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • If It Ain’t Broke, Don’t Fix It.Larry Laudan - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (3):369-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Broken bootstraps. [REVIEW]John Worrall - 1982 - Erkenntnis 18 (1):105 - 130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Normative naturalism.Larry Laudan - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (1):44-59.
    Normative naturalism is a view about the status of epistemology and philosophy of science; it is a meta-epistemology. It maintains that epistemology can both discharge its traditional normative role and nonetheless claim a sensitivity to empirical evidence. The first sections of this essay set out the central tenets of normative naturalism, both in its epistemic and its axiological dimensions; later sections respond to criticisms of that species of naturalism from Gerald Doppelt, Jarrett Leplin and Alex Rosenberg.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • The philosophical requirements for an adequate conception of scientific rationality.Gerald Doppelt - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (1):104-133.
    I argue that post-Kuhnian approaches to rational scientific change fail to appreciate several distinct philosophical requirements and relativist challenges that have been assumed to be, and may in fact be essential to any adequate conception of scientific rationality. These separate requirements and relativist challenges are clearly distinguished and motivated. My argument then focuses on Shapere's view that there are typically good reasons for scientific change. I argue: that contrary to his central aim, his account of good reasons ultimately presupposes the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Epistemological realism and the basis of scepticism.Michael Williams - 1988 - Mind 97 (387):415-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Dimensions of observability.Peter Kosso - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4):449-467.
    The concept of observability of entities in physical science is typically analysed in terms of the nature and significance of a dichotomy between observables and unobservables. In the present work, however, this categorization is resisted and observability is analysed in a descriptive way in terms of the information which one can receive through interaction with objects in the world. The account of interaction and the transfer of information is done using applicable scientific theories. In this way, the question of observability (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Doppelt crossed.Dudley Shapere - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (1):134-140.
    The chief objections raised by Doppelt (this issue, "The Philosophical Requirements for an Adequate Conception of Scientific Rationality") against my views fall into three groups: ones having to do with my concept of "success" (that I have provided no analysis of it, and that therefore my concept of "reason" in science is likewise unexplained; that it requires appeal to some universal criterion); ones having to do with the role of standards or criteria in science (how they are related to substantive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relativism, naturalism and reticulation.Larry Laudan - 1987 - Synthese 71 (3):221 - 234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Philosophy of Science Naturalized? Some Problems with Giere's Naturalism.Harvey Siegel - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3):365.
    The main thesis is that the study of science must itself be a science. the only viable philosophy of science is a naturalized philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Historicist Relativism and Bootstrap Rationality.Larry Briskman - 1987 - In Joseph Agassi & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Rationality: the critical view. Hingham, MA, USA: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 317--338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Historicist Relativism and Bootstrap Rationality.Larry Briskman - 1977 - The Monist 60 (4):509-539.
    Epistemology as traditionally conceived seems to have fallen upon hard times. Not only has the cry arisen from diverse philosophical quarters that epistemology is dead, but we have even been offered a plethora of suggestions as to how best fill the vacuum left by her sudden demise. Thus Quine, for example, has recently urged that epistemology be “naturalized” and replaced by empirical psychology and an empirical semantics. Others suggest that epistemology be “historicized” and replaced by a study of the history (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Background to the Forefront: A Response to Levi and Shapere.John Worrall - 1984 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984:672 - 682.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations