Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Critique of Pure Reason.I. Kant - 1787/1998 - Philosophy 59 (230):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1921 citations  
  • From Kant to Husserl: selected essays.Charles Parsons - 2012 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    The transcendental aesthetic -- Arithmetic and the categories -- Remarks on pure natural science -- Two studies in the reception of Kant's philosophy of arithmetic: postscript to part I -- Some remarks on Frege's conception of extension -- Postscript to essay 5 -- Frege's correspondence: postscript to essay 6 -- Brentano on judgment and truth -- Husserl and the linguistic turn.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Cardinality, Counting, and Equinumerosity.Richard G. Heck - 2000 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 41 (3):187-209.
    Frege, famously, held that there is a close connection between our concept of cardinal number and the notion of one-one correspondence, a connection enshrined in Hume's Principle. Husserl, and later Parsons, objected that there is no such close connection, that our most primitive conception of cardinality arises from our grasp of the practice of counting. Some empirical work on children's development of a concept of number has sometimes been thought to point in the same direction. I argue, however, that Frege (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Gesammelte Schriften. Kant - 1912 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 73:105-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   229 citations  
  • Kant and the exact sciences.Michael Friedman - 1992 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    In this new book, Michael Friedman argues that Kant's continuing efforts to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the sciences is of the utmost ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   253 citations  
  • Arithmetic and the categories.Charles Parsons - 1984 - Topoi 3 (2):109-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Metaphysics, mathematics and the distinction between the sensible and the intelligible in Kant's inaugural dissertation.Emily Carson - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2):165-194.
    In this paper I argue that Kant's distinction in the Inaugural Dissertation between the sensible and the intelligible arises in part out of certain open questions left open by his comparison between mathematics and metaphysics in the Prize Essay. This distinction provides a philosophical justification for his distinction between the respective methods of mathematics and metaphysics and his claim that mathematics admits of a greater degree of certainty. More generally, this illustrates the importance of Kant's reflections on mathematics for the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant on the method of mathematics.Emily Carson - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (4):629-652.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Kant on the Method of MathematicsEmily Carson1. INTRODUCTIONThis paper will touch on three very general but closely related questions about Kant’s philosophy. First, on the role of mathematics as a paradigm of knowledge in the development of Kant’s Critical philosophy; second, on the nature of Kant’s opposition to his Leibnizean predecessors and its role in the development of the Critical philosophy; and finally, on the specific role of intuition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Kant on the `symbolic construction' of mathematical concepts.Lisa Shabel - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (4):589-621.
    In the chapter of the Critique of Pure Reason entitled ‘The Discipline of Pure Reason in Dogmatic Use’, Kant contrasts mathematical and philosophical knowledge in order to show that pure reason does not (and, indeed, cannot) pursue philosophical truth according to the same method that it uses to pursue and attain the apodictically certain truths of mathematics. In the process of this comparison, Kant gives the most explicit statement of his critical philosophy of mathematics; accordingly, scholars have typically focused their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Evolution of Logic.W. D. Hart - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Examines the relations between logic and philosophy over the last 150 years. Logic underwent a major renaissance beginning in the nineteenth century. Cantor almost tamed the infinite, and Frege aimed to undercut Kant by reducing mathematics to logic. These achievements were threatened by the paradoxes, like Russell's. This ferment generated excellent philosophy by excellent philosophers up to World War II. This book provides a selective, critical history of the collaboration between logic and philosophy during this period. After World War II, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An Aristotelian notion of size.Vieri Benci, Mauro Di Nasso & Marco Forti - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 143 (1-3):43-53.
    The naïve idea of “size” for collections seems to obey both Aristotle’s Principle: “the whole is greater than its parts” and Cantor’s Principle: “1-to-1 correspondences preserve size”. Notoriously, Aristotle’s and Cantor’s principles are incompatible for infinite collections. Cantor’s theory of cardinalities weakens the former principle to “the part is not greater than the whole”, but the outcoming cardinal arithmetic is very unusual. It does not allow for inverse operations, and so there is no direct way of introducing infinitesimal numbers. Here (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Kant's philosophy of arithmetic.Charles Parsons - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2026 citations  
  • Measuring the Size of Infinite Collections of Natural Numbers: Was Cantor’s Theory of Infinite Number Inevitable?Paolo Mancosu - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):612-646.
    Cantor’s theory of cardinal numbers offers a way to generalize arithmetic from finite sets to infinite sets using the notion of one-to-one association between two sets. As is well known, all countable infinite sets have the same ‘size’ in this account, namely that of the cardinality of the natural numbers. However, throughout the history of reflections on infinity another powerful intuition has played a major role: if a collectionAis properly included in a collectionBthen the ‘size’ ofAshould be less than the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • The Role of Magnitude in Kant's Critical Philosophy.Daniel Sutherland - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (3):411-441.
    In theCritique of Pure Reason,Kant argues for two principles that concern magnitudes. The first is the principle that ‘All intuitions are extensive magnitudes,’ which appears in the Axioms of Intuition (B202); the second is the principle that ‘In all appearances the real, which is an object of sensation, has an intensive magnitude, that is, a degree,’ which appears in the Anticipations of Perception (B207). A circle drawn in geometry and the space occupied by an object such as a book are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Kant and the Exact Sciences.William Harper & Michael Friedman - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (4):587.
    This is a very important book. It has already become required reading for researchers on the relation between the exact sciences and Kant’s philosophy. The main theme is that Kant’s continuing program to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the science of his day is of crucial importance to understanding the development of his philosophical thought from its earliest precritical beginnings in the thesis of 1747, right through the highwater years of the critical philosophy, to his last (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • The point of Kant's axioms of intuition.Daniel Sutherland - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1):135–159.
    Kant's Critique of Pure Reason makes important claims about space, time and mathematics in both the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Axioms of Intuition, claims that appear to overlap in some ways and contradict in others. Various interpretations have been offered to resolve these tensions; I argue for an interpretation that accords the Axioms of Intuition a more important role in explaining mathematical cognition than it is usually given. Appreciation for this larger role reveals that magnitudes are central to Kant's philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's Elements.Ian Mueller - 1981 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    A survey of Euclid's Elements, this text provides an understanding of the classical Greek conception of mathematics and its similarities to modern views as well as its differences. It focuses on philosophical, foundational, and logical questions — rather than strictly historical and mathematical issues — and features several helpful appendixes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Kant on arithmetic, algebra, and the theory of proportions.Daniel Sutherland - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (4):533-558.
    Daniel Sutherland - Kant on Arithmetic, Algebra, and the Theory of Proportions - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44:4 Journal of the History of Philosophy 44.4 533-558 Muse Search Journals This Journal Contents Kant on Arithmetic, Algebra, and the Theory of Proportions Daniel Sutherland Kant's philosophy of mathematics has both enthralled and exercised philosophers since the appearance of the Critique of Pure Reason. Neither the Critique nor any other work provides a sustained and focused account of his mature views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Michael Boylan - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (4):665-668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The View from 1763: Kant on the Arithmetical Method before Intuition.Ofra Rechter - 2006 - In Emily Carson & Renate Huber (eds.), Intuition and the Axiomatic Method. Springer. pp. 21--46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant on fundamental geometrical relations.Daniel Sutherland - 2005 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 87 (2):117-158.
    Equality, similarity and congruence are essential elements of Kant’s theory of geometrical cognition; nevertheless, Kant’s account of them is not well understood. This paper provides historical context for treatments of these geometrical relations, presents Kant’s views on their mathematical definitions, and explains Kant’s theory of their cognition. It also places Kant’s theory within the larger context of his understanding of the quality-quantity distinction. Most importantly, it argues that the relation of equality, in conjunction with the categories of quantity, plays a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Frege versus Cantor and dedekind: On the concept of number.William Tait - manuscript
    There can be no doubt about the value of Frege's contributions to the philosophy of mathematics. First, he invented quantification theory and this was the first step toward making precise the notion of a purely logical deduction. Secondly, he was the first to publish a logical analysis of the ancestral R* of a relation R, which yields a definition of R* in second-order logic.1 Only a narrow and arid conception of philosophy would exclude these two achievements. Thirdly and very importantly, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics and the Greek Mathematical Tradition.Daniel Sutherland - 2004 - Philosophical Review 113 (2):157-201.
    The aggregate EIRP of an N-element antenna array is proportional to N 2. This observation illustrates an effective approach for providing deep space networks with very powerful uplinks. The increased aggregate EIRP can be employed in a number of ways, including improved emergency communications, reaching farther into deep space, increased uplink data rates, and the flexibility of simultaneously providing more than one uplink beam with the array. Furthermore, potential for cost savings also exists since the array can be formed using (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Commentar zu Kants Kritik der Reinen Vernunft.H. Vaihinger - 1883 - Mind 8 (31):440-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Eudoxos and dedekind: On the ancient greek theory of ratios and its relation to modern mathematics.Howard Stein - 1990 - Synthese 84 (2):163 - 211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The evolution of logic.Kenny Easwaran - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (4):533-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant on the Construction of Arithmetical Concepts.J. Michael Young - 1982 - Kant Studien 73 (1-4):17-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Arithmetic from Kant to Frege: Numbers, Pure Units, and the Limits of Conceptual Representation.Daniel Sutherland - 2008 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 63:135-164.
    There is evidence in Kant of the idea that concepts of particular numbers, such as the number 5, are derived from the representation of units, and in particular pure units, that is, units that are qualitatively indistinguishable. Frege, in contrast, rejects any attempt to derive concepts of number from the representation of units. In the Foundations of Arithmetic, he softens up his reader for his groundbreaking and unintuitive analysis of number by attacking alternative views, and he devotes the majority of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Commentar zu Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft.E. Adickes & Hans Vaihinger - 1894 - Philosophical Review 3 (1):119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (1 other version)ssays on the Theory of Numbers. [REVIEW]R. Dedekind - 1903 - Ancient Philosophy (Misc) 13:314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Ian Mueller - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1):57-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations