Switch to: Citations

References in:

Working from Within: The Nature and Development of Quine's Naturalism

New York: Oxford University Press (2018)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On Carnap's Views on Ontology.John Myhill & W. V. Quine - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Quine against Lewis (and Carnap) on Truth by Convention.Sean Morris - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (3):366-391.
    Many commentators now view Quine's ‘Truth by Convention’ as a flawed criticism of Carnap. Gary Ebbs argued recently that Quine never intended Carnap as his target. Quine's criticisms were part of his attempt to work out his own scientific naturalism. I agree that Carnap was not Quine's target but object that Quine's criticisms were wholly internal to his own philosophy. Instead, I argue that C.I. Lewis held the kind of truth‐by‐convention thesis that Quine rejects. This, however, leaves Carnap out of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Just how controversial is evidential holism?Joe Morrison - 2010 - Synthese 173 (3):335-352.
    This paper is an examination of evidential holism, a prominent position in epistemology and the philosophy of science which claims that experiments only ever confirm or refute entire theories. The position is historically associated with W.V. Quine, and it is at once both popular and notorious, as well as being largely under-described. But even though there’s no univocal statement of what holism is or what it does, philosophers have nevertheless made substantial assumptions about its content and its truth. Moreover they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Principia Ethica.Evander Bradley McGilvary - 1904 - Philosophical Review 13 (3):351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   575 citations  
  • The Positive Philosophy of Aguste Comte.Harriet Martineau & Frederic Harrison - 1897 - International Journal of Ethics 7 (2):261-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Some Ontological Policies.Joseph Margolis - 1969 - The Monist 53 (2):231-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes.Charles E. Marks - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Are necessary propositions really verbal?Norman Malcolm - 1940 - Mind 49 (194):189-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Three Forms of Naturalism.Penelope Maddy - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford University Press.
    This chapter compares and contrasts Quine’s naturalism with the versions of two post-Quineans on the nature of science, logic, and mathematics. The role of indispensability in the philosophy of mathematics is treated in detail.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Quinean Naturalism in Question.David Macarthur - 2008 - Philo 11 (1):5-18.
    This paper is a critical discussion of Quine’s naturalist credos: (1) physicalism; (2) there is no first philosophy; (3) philosophy is continuous with science; and (4) the only responsible theory of the world as a whole is scientific theory. The aim is to show that Quine’s formulations admit of two readings: a strong reading (often Quine’s own) which is compatible with reductive forms of naturalism but implausible; and a mild reading which is plausible but suggestive of more liberal forms of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intertheoretical Identity And Ontological Reductions.Ronald Loeffler - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (2):157-187.
    I argue that there are good reasons to assume that Quine’s theory of reference and ontology is incompatible with reductive statements – such as ‘Heat is molecular motion’ or ‘Rabbits are conglomerations of cells’. Apparently, reductive statements imply certain intertheoretical identities, yet Quine’s theory of reference and ontology seems incompatible with intertheoretical identities. I argued that treating, for the sake of reconciliation, reductive statements along the lines of Quine’s theory of an ontological reduction (which does not imply intertheoretical identity) fails. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Inception of Quine's ontology.Lieven Decock - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (2):111-129.
    This paper traces the development of Quine's ontological ideas throughout his early logical work in the period before 1948. It shows that his ontological criterion critically depends on this work in logic. The use of quantifiers as logical primitives and the introduction of general variables in 1936, the search for adequate comprehension axioms, and problems with proper classes, all forced Quine to consider ontological questions. I also show that Quine's rejection of intensional entities goes back to his generalisation of Principia (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mind and the World-Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. [REVIEW]Charles A. Baylis - 1930 - Journal of Philosophy 27 (12):320-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation.Carl G. Hempel - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):40-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Quine and pragmatism.Heikki J. Koskinen & Sami Pihlström - 2006 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42 (3):309-346.
    : This paper discusses critically W.V. Quine's relation to the tradition of pragmatism. Even though Quine is often regarded as a pragmatist, it is far from clear what his commitment to pragmatism actually amounts to. It is argued that while there are pragmatist elements in Quine's position, this is not sufficient to classify him as a pragmatist in any strong historical sense; indeed, he was not even clear himself what it means to be a pragmatist. It is also shown that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Quine and Pragmatism.Heikki J. Koskinen & Sami Pihlström - 2006 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42 (3):309-346.
    This paper discusses critically W.V. Quine's relation to the tradition of pragmatism. Even though Quine is often regarded as a pragmatist, it is far from clear what his commitment to pragmatism actually amounts to. It is argued that while there are pragmatist elements in Quine's position, this is not sufficient to classify him as a pragmatist in any strong historical sense; indeed, he was not even clear himself what it means to be a pragmatist. It is also shown that neither (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The naturalists return.Philip Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (1):53-114.
    This article reviews the transition between post-Fregean anti-naturalistic epistemology and contemporary naturalistic epistemologies. It traces the revival of naturalism to Quine’s critique of the "a priori", and Kuhn’s defense of historicism, and use the arguments of Quine and Kuhn to identify a position, "traditional naturalism", that combines naturalistic themes with the claim that epistemology is a normative enterprise. Pleas for more radical versions of naturalism are articulated, and briefly confronted.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Quine: Language, Experience and Reality.Robert Kirk & Christopher Hookway - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • What is "naturalized epistemology?".Jaegwon Kim - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:381-405.
    This paper analyzes and evaluates quine's influential thesis that epistemology should become a chapter of empirical psychology. quine's main point, it is argued, is that normativity must be banished from epistemology and, more generally, philosophy. i claim that without a normative concept of justification, we lose the very concept of knowledge, and that belief ascription itself becomes impossible without a normative concept of rationality. further, the supervenience of concepts of epistemic appraisal shows that normative epistemology is indeed possible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • The American Origins of Philosophical Naturalism.Jaegwon Kim - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Research 28 (9999):83-98.
    If contemporary analytic philosophy can be said to have a philosophical ideology, it undoubtedly is naturalism. Naturalism is often invoked as a motivating ground for many philosophical projects, and “naturalization” programs abound everywhere, in theory of knowledge, philosophy of mind, theory of meaning, metaphysics, and ethics. But what is naturalism, and where does it come from? This paper examines the naturalism debate in midtwentieth-century America as a proximate source of contemporary naturalism. Views of philosophers like Roy Wood Sellars, John Dewey, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • On the de-naturalization of epistemology.András Kertész - 2002 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 33 (2):269-288.
    Starting from an overview of approaches to naturalized epistemology, the paper shows, firstly, that Quine's programme yields a sceptical paradox. This means that Quine's attempt to defeat scepticism itself yields a rather strong argument for scepticism and thus against his own programme of naturalized epistemology. Secondly, it is shown that this paradox can be solved by an approach called reflexive-heuristic naturalism. Finally, the paper also raises some fundamental problems which the solution proposed has to leave open.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Refutation of Indeterminacy.Jerrold J. Katz - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (5):227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Philosophy of Logic.Michael Jubien & W. V. Quine - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • How to Read “Epistemology Naturalized”.Bredo C. Johnsen - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy 102 (2):78-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Canonizing Dewey: Naturalism, logical empiricism, and the idea of american philosophy*: Andrew Jewett.Andrew Jewett - 2011 - Modern Intellectual History 8 (1):91-125.
    Between World War I and World War II, the students of Columbia University's John Dewey and Frederick J. E. Woodbridge built up a school of philosophical naturalism sharply critical of claims to value-neutrality. In the 1930s and 1940s, the second-generation Columbia naturalists and their students who later joined the department reacted with dismay to the arrival on American shores of logical empiricism and other analytic modes of philosophy. These figures undermined their colleague Ernest Nagel's attempt to build an alliance with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap.Richard C. Jeffrey & Paul Arthur Schilpp - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (4):534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Identity and Difference: A Hundred Years of Analytic Philosophy.Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2000 - Metaphilosophy 31 (4):365-381.
    At its origins, analytic philosophy is an interest in language, science, logic, analysis, and a systematic rather than a historical approach to philosophical problems. Early analytic philosophers were famous for making clear conceptual distinctions and for couching them in comprehensible and lucid sentences. It is argued that this situation is changing, that analytic philosophy is turning into its mirror image and is thereby becoming more like the kind of philosophy that it used to oppose.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Signigicance in Quine.Peter Hylton - 2014 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 89 (1):113-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Russell, idealism, and the emergence of analytic philosophy.Peter Hylton - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Analytic philosophy has become the dominant philosophical tradition in the English-speaking world. This book illuminates that tradition through a historical examination of a crucial period in its formation: the rejection of Idealism by Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore at the beginning of the twentieth century, and the subsequent development of Russell's thought in the period before the First World War.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Analyticity and Holism in Quine’s Thought.Peter Hylton - 2002 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 10 (1):11-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Scepticism and Animal Faith.Marten Ten Hoor & George Santayana - 1923 - Journal of Philosophy 20 (24):653.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Quine: Language, Experience, and Reality.Christopher Hookway - 1988 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    Introduction Quine was born in. He studied as a graduate student at Harvard, and apart from short visits to Oxford, Paris and other centres of learning, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science.Edward Poznański - 1967 - University of Chicago Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Methods of Logic.P. L. Heath & Willard Van Orman Quine - 1955 - Philosophical Quarterly 5 (21):376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Purposes and Methods of Writing the History of Recent American Philosophy. [REVIEW]Peter H. Hare - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 6 (4):269-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Naturalized epistemology and ?First philosophy?Harvey Siegel - 1995 - Metaphilosophy 26 (1-2):46-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Alfred Tarski: Drei Briefe an Otto Neurath.Rudolf Haller & Jan Tarski - 1992 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 43 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Rise of Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy.P. M. S. Hacker - 2006 - Ratio 9 (3):243-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Passing by the Naturalistic Turn: On Quine’s Cul-de-Sac.P. M. S. Hacker - 2006 - Philosophy 81 (2):231-253.
    1. Naturalism Naturalism, it has been said, is the distinctive development in philosophy over the last thirty years. There has been a naturalistic turn away from the a priori methods of traditional philosophy to a conception of philosophy as continuous with natural science. The doctrine has been extensively discussed and has won considerable following in the USA. This is, on the whole, not true of Britain and continental Europe, where the pragmatist tradition never took root, and the temptations of scientism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The two faces of Quine's naturalism.Susan Haack - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):335 - 356.
    Quine's naturalized epistemology is ambivalent between a modest naturalism according to which epistemology is an a posteriori discipline, an integral part of the web of empirical belief, and a scientistic naturalism according to which epistemology is to be conducted wholly within the natural sciences. This ambivalence is encouraged by Quine's ambiguous use of science, to mean sometimes, broadly, our presumed empirical knowledge and sometimes, narrowly, the natural sciences. Quine's modest naturalism is reformist, tackling the traditional epistemological problems in a novel (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Precis of Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in EpistemologyEvidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. [REVIEW]Susan Haack - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3):611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology.Susan Haack - 1993 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    In this important new work, Haack develops an original theory of empirical evidence or justification, and argues its appropriateness to the goals of inquiry. In so doing, Haack provides detailed critical case studies of Lewis's foundationalism; Davidson's and Bonjour's coherentism; Popper's 'epistemology without a knowing subject'; Quine's naturalism; Goldman's reliabilism; and Rorty's, Stich's, and the Churchlands' recent obituaries of epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • Analyticity and logical truth in The roots of reference.Susan Haack - 1977 - Theoria 43 (2):129-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Mind and Language.Simon Blackburn - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (105):354-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Relativity without inscrutability.Douglas Greenlee - 1973 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 33 (4):574-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Steps toward a constructive nominalism.Nelson Goodman & Willard van Orman Quine - 1947 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 12 (4):105-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Steps Toward a Constructive Nominalism.Nelson Goodman & W. V. Quine - 1947 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • What is Analytic Philosophy.Hanjo Glock - 2008 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (2).
    Special Issue: What is Analytic Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Quine and Davidson on Language, Thought and Reality.G. Kemp - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):154-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Does ontology exist?Hans-Johann Glock - 2002 - Philosophy 77 (2):235-260.
    Early analytic philosophers like Carnap, Wittgenstein and Ryle regarded ontology as a branch of metaphysics that is either trivial or meaningless. But at present it is generally assumed that philosophy can make substantial discoveries about what kinds of things exist and about the essence of these kinds. My paper challenges this ontological turn. The currently predominant conceptions of the subject, at any rate, do not license the idea that ontology can provide distinctively philosophical insights into the constituents of reality. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations