Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind.Paul Bloom - 2000 - Cognition 77 (1):25-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Why the Child’s Theory of Mind Really Is a Theory.Alison Gopnik & Henry M. Wellman - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (1-2):145-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong.Jerry A. Fodor - 1998 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    The renowned philosopher Jerry Fodor, a leading figure in the study of the mind for more than twenty years, presents a strikingly original theory on the basic constituents of thought. He suggests that the heart of cognitive science is its theory of concepts, and that cognitive scientists have gone badly wrong in many areas because their assumptions about concepts have been mistaken. Fodor argues compellingly for an atomistic theory of concepts, deals out witty and pugnacious demolitions of rival theories, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   619 citations  
  • Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind.".Alan M. Leslie - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (4):412-426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   591 citations  
  • Representational and executive selection resources in ‘theory of mind’: Evidence from compromised belief-desire reasoning in old age.T. German & J. Hehman - 2006 - Cognition 101 (1):129-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Solving belief problems: toward a task analysis.Daniel Roth & Alan M. Leslie - 1998 - Cognition 66 (1):1-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”?Simon Baron-Cohen, Alan M. Leslie & Uta Frith - 1985 - Cognition 21 (1):37–46.
    We use a new model of metarepresentational development to predict a cognitive deficit which could explain a crucial component of the social impairment in childhood autism. One of the manifestations of a basic metarepresentational capacity is a ‘ theory of mind ’. We have reason to believe that autistic children lack such a ‘ theory ’. If this were so, then they would be unable to impute beliefs to others and to predict their behaviour. This hypothesis was tested using Wimmer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   653 citations  
  • (6 other versions)Logic and conversation.Herbert Paul Grice - 1989 - In Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 41-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   274 citations  
  • Three- and four-year-old children's ability to use desire- and belief- based reasoning.Kimberly Wright Cassidy - 1998 - Cognition 66 (1):B1-B11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The many faces of belief: reflections on Fodor's and the child's theory of mind.Josef Perner - 1995 - Cognition 57 (3):241-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The scientist as child.Alison Gopnik - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):485-514.
    This paper argues that there are powerful similarities between cognitive development in children and scientific theory change. These similarities are best explained by postulating an underlying abstract set of rules and representations that underwrite both types of cognitive abilities. In fact, science may be successful largely because it exploits powerful and flexible cognitive devices that were designed by evolution to facilitate learning in young children. Both science and cognitive development involve abstract, coherent systems of entities and rules, theories. In both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Modularity, development and "theory of mind".Alan M. Leslie & Brian J. Scholl - 1999 - Mind and Language 14 (1):131-153.
    Psychologists and philosophers have recently been exploring whether the mechanisms which underlie the acquisition of ‘theory of mind’ (ToM) are best charac- terized as cognitive modules or as developing theories. In this paper, we attempt to clarify what a modular account of ToM entails, and why it is an attractive type of explanation. Intuitions and arguments in this debate often turn on the role of develop- ment: traditional research on ToM focuses on various developmental sequences, whereas cognitive modules are thought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • The child as scientist.Alison Gopnik - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):485-514.
    This paper argues that there are powerful similarities between cognitive development in children and scientific theory change. These similarities are best explained by postulating an underlying abstract set of rules and representations that underwrite both types of cognitive abilities. In fact, science may be successful largely because it exploits powerful and flexible cognitive devices that were designed by evolution to facilitate learning in young children. Both science and cognitive development involve abstract, coherent systems of entities and rules, theories. In both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Children's early understanding of false belief.Peter Mitchell & Hazel Lacohée - 1991 - Cognition 39 (2):107-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM.Alan M. Leslie - 1994 - Cognition 50 (1-3):211-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • A developmental shift in processes underlying successful belief‐desire reasoning.Ori Friedman & Alan M. Leslie - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (6):963-977.
    Young children’s failures in reasoning about beliefs and desires, and especially about false beliefs, have been much studied. However, there are few accounts of successful belief-desire reasoning in older children or adults. An exception to this is a model in which belief attribution is treated as a process wherein an inhibitory system selects the most likely content for the belief to be attributed from amongst several competing contents [Leslie, A. M., & Polizzi, P. (1998). Developmental Science, 1, 247–254]. We tested (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Young children's reasoning about beliefs.Henry M. Wellman & Karen Bartsch - 1988 - Cognition 30 (3):239-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Understanding children's and adults' limitations in mental state reasoning.Paul Bloom - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (6):255-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Domain specificity in conceptual development: Neuropsychological evidence from autism.Alan M. Leslie & Laila Thaiss - 1992 - Cognition 43 (3):225-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • No (social) construction without (meta-)representation: Modular mechanisms as a basis for the capacity to acquire an understanding of mind.Tim P. German & Alan M. Leslie - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):106-107.
    Theories that propose a modular basis for developing a “theory of mind” have no problem accommodating social interaction or social environment factors into either the learning process, or into the genotypes underlying the growth of the neurocognitive modules. Instead, they can offer models which constrain and hence explain the mechanisms through which variations in social interaction affect development. Cognitive models of both competence and performance are critical to evaluating the basis of correlations between variations in social interaction and performance on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ‘Theory of Mind’ and Tracking Speakers’ Intentions.Francesca Happé & Eva Loth - 2002 - Mind and Language 17 (1-2):24-36.
    Typical theory of mind tasks assess children’s ability to attribute a false belief in order to predict or explain an action. According to these standard tasks, young children do not represent the independent (mistaken) beliefs of others until the fourth year—yet long before this, children are able to track speakers’ intentions in order to learn new words. Might communication be a privileged domain for theory of mind? In the present study we explored pre‐schoolers’ ability to track a false belief in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Attending to and learning about mental states.Tim P. German & Alan M. Leslie - 2000 - In Peter Mitchell & Kevin John Riggs (eds.), Children's Reasoning and the Mind. Psychology Press/Taylor & Francis. pp. 229--252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Where to look first for children's knowledge of false beliefs.Michael Siegal & Karen Beattie - 1991 - Cognition 38 (1):1-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Making explicit 3-year-olds' implicit competence with their own false beliefs.Norman H. Freeman & Hazel Lacohée - 1995 - Cognition 56 (1):31-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Pulling smarties out of a bag: a Headed Records analysis of children's recall of their own past beliefs.Sofka Barreau & John Morton - 1999 - Cognition 73 (1):65-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations