Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Groundwork for Dialectic in Statesman 277a-287b.Colin C. Smith - 2018 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 12 (2):132-150.
    In Plato’s Statesman, the Eleatic Stranger leads Socrates the Younger and their audience through an analysis of the statesman in the service of the interlocutors’ becoming “more capable in dialectic regarding all things”. In this way, the dialectical exercise in the text is both intrinsically and instrumentally valuable, as it yields a philosophically rigorous account of statesmanship and exhibits a method of dialectical inquiry. After the series of bifurcatory divisions in the Sophist and early Statesman, the Stranger changes to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Understanding Problem‐Based Learning1.Don Margetson - 1993 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 25 (1):40-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Treading the Aether: Lucretius, De Rerum Natura 1.62–79.M. J. Edwards - 1990 - Classical Quarterly 40 (2):465-469.
    As befits the proem to so original and immense an undertaking, this passage echoes, in order to retort them upon their inventors, the mythopoeic commonplaces of other ancient schools. One such commonplace was the assertion that some man was the first to effect a revolution in life or thought: those who held with Empedocles that Pythagoras was the first to see beyond his generation, or with Aristotle that Thales was the earliest cosmogonist and Plato the first discoverer of happiness, must (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commentary on Fine.Deborah De Chiara-Quenzer - 1994 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 10 (1):244-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anamnesis: Platonic Doctrine or Sophistic Absurdity?William S. Cobb - 1973 - Dialogue 12 (4):604-628.
    There are two basic ways in which the phenomenon of learning is explicated in the Platonic dialogues: First, by means of an analogy with vision, and second, by arguing that the acquisition of knowledge is really anamnesis. The analogy with vision is the more common of the two and occurs throughout the dialogues. The passage in the Republic comparing the sun and the good is the best known instance of this approach to the clarification of learning. The basic point of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reading the περιτρoπη: Theaetetus 170c-171c. Chappell - 2006 - Phronesis 51 (2):109-139.
    Two readings of the much-discussed περιτροπή argument of "Theaetetus" 170c-171c have dominated the literature. One I call "the relativity reading". On this reading, the argument fails by ignoratio elenchi because it "carelessly" omits "the qualifications 'true for so-and-so' which [Protagoras'] theory insists on" (Bostock 1988: 90). The other reading I call "the many-worlds interpretation". On this view, Plato's argument succeeds in showing that "Protagoras' position becomes utterly self-contradictory" because "he claims that everyone lives in his own relativistic world, yet at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plato on the Grammar of Perceiving.M. F. Burnyeat - 1976 - Classical Quarterly 26 (01):29-.
    The question contrasts two ways of expressing the role of the sense organ in perception. In one the expression referring to the sense organ is put into the dative case ; the other is a construction with the preposition δiá governing the genitive case of the word for the sense organ.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Apology 30b 2-4: Socrates, money, and the grammar of γίγνεσθαι.M. F. Burnyeat - 2003 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 123:1-25.
    The framework of this paper is a defence of Burnet's construal ofApology30b 2-4. Socrates does not claim, as he is standardly translated, that virtue makes you rich, but that virtue makes money and everything else good for you. This view of the relation between virtue and wealth is paralleled in dialogues of every period, and a sophisticated development of it appears in Aristotle. My philological defence of the philosophically preferable translation extends recent scholarly work on εἶναι in Plato and Aristotle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Commentary on Dixsaut.Klaus Brinkmann - 1997 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 13 (1):28-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • No-existing beings: phantasmata in Plato.Barbara Botter - 2016 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 18:113-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Procheirisis: Porphyry Sent. 16 and Plotinus on the similes of the waxen block and the aviary.Robbert van den Berg - 2010 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 4 (2):163-180.
    This paper studies Sentence 16 of Porphyry's Pathways to the Intelligible. It is argued that it should be understood against the background of Plotinus' discussions of the similes of the waxen block and the aviary from Plato's Theaetetus. The first part of the paper concentrates on Plotinus' reception of these similes. In the second part of the paper Plotinus' discussions of the two similes are used to shed light on Sentence 16, in particular on the term προχείρισις. Furthermore it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What the forms are not: Plato on conceptualism in Parmenides 132b–c.Sosseh Assaturian - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (2):353-368.
    Conceptualism—the view that universals are mental entities without an external, independent, or substantial reality—has enjoyed popularity at various points throughout the history of philosophy. While Plato’s Theory of Forms is not a conceptualist theory of universals, we find at Parmenides 132b–c the startling conceptualist suggestion from a young Socrates that each Form might be a noēma, or a mental entity. This suggestion and Parmenides’ cryptic objections to it have been overshadowed by their placement directly after the notoriously difficult Third Man (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Case of Theaetetus.Gokhan Adalier - 2001 - Phronesis 46 (1):1-37.
    Any comprehensive interpretation of the "Theaetetus" has to provide answers to, among others, two very general questions concerning that dialogue: "What is Plato's relation to the problems faced in the "Theaetetus"?" and "What is the significance of the absence of the Forms from the discussion of the "Theaetetus", given their undoubted relevance to the topic of the dialogue, i.e. knowledge?" Predominantly, the answer given to the first question in the literature has been that the problems are those that Plato is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philebus.Verity Harte - 2012 - In Associate Editors: Francisco Gonzalez Gerald A. Press (ed.), The Continuum Companion to Plato. Continuum International Publishing Group. pp. 81-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speaking of Something: Plato’s Sophist and Plato’s Beard.Christine J. Thomas - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4):pp. 631-667.
    The Eleatic Visitor speaks forcefully when he insists, ‘Necessarily, whenever there is speech, it is speech of something; it is impossible for it not to be of something’. For ‘if it were not of anything, it would not be speech at all; for we showed that it is impossible for there to be speech that is speech of nothing’. Presumably, at 263c10, when he claims to have ‘shown’ that it is impossible for speech to be of nothing, the Visitor is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Tyranny of Abstractions.William P. D. Wightman - 1973 - British Journal for the History of Science 6 (3):233-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding Team Learning Dynamics Over Time.Christopher W. Wiese & C. Shawn Burke - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on Joint Perception and Perceiving that We Perceive.Rosemary Twomey - 2019 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 13 (1):147-180.
    While most interpreters take the opening of De Anima III 2 to be an oblique reference to some sort of conscious awareness, I argue that Aristotle intends to explain what I call ‘joint perception’: when conjoined with Aristotle’s subsequent claim that perceiving and being perceived are the same activity, the metaperception underpins the perception of a unified object. My interpretation is shown to have a more satisfactory account of the aporiai that follow. While I argue that the immediate focus of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Perception and Knowledge in Plato's Theaetetus.Naly Thaler - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (3):160-167.
    In this paper, I examine several key issues relating to the definition of knowledge as perception in the first part of Plato's Theaetetus. I begin by explaining the workings of the ‘secret doctrine’ of perception, which is introduced in order to support the idea that perception is incorrigible, and then turn to examine the two refutations of the definition of knowledge as perception which appear at the end of the first part of the Theaetetus. I shall present and explain distinct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Judgment, Logos, and Knowledge in Plato's Theaetetus.Naly Thaler - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (5):246-255.
    In this second installment on the Theaetetus, I discuss Theaetetus' second and third definitions of knowledge, namely, ‘true judgment’ and then ‘true judgment with the addition of an account’. I offer a brief description of Socrates' intricate examination of these suggestions, concentrating especially on the discussion of false judgment and that of the so-called ‘Dream Theory’. I then proceed to map different lines of interpretation for these passages that have been offered by scholars writing in the last 40 years.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consonnes et voyelles: les fonctions de l'Être et de l'Autre dans le Sophiste de Platon.Fulcran Teisserenc - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (2):231-264.
    ABSTRACTThis article aims at understanding the functions of the forms of Being and the Other in Plato's Sophist. In contrast with a linguistic interpretation purporting to draw a distinction between uses of the verb “to be,” I shed light on the ontological role ascribed to “the great genus” in the interweaving of forms. Focusing on the vowel analogy, I argue that the roles of Being and the Other respectively are that of a connector and a separator actualizing the participations and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consonnes et voyelles: les fonctions de l'Être et de l'Autre dans le Sophiste de Platon.Fulcran Teisserenc - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (2):231-264.
    ABSTRACTThis article aims at understanding the functions of the forms of Being and the Other in Plato's Sophist. In contrast with a linguistic interpretation purporting to draw a distinction between uses of the verb “to be,” I shed light on the ontological role ascribed to “the great genus” in the interweaving of forms. Focusing on the vowel analogy, I argue that the roles of Being and the Other respectively are that of a connector and a separator actualizing the participations and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reading the περιτροπή: "Theaetetus" 170c-171c. Chappell - 2006 - Phronesis 51 (2):109 - 139.
    Two readings of the much-discussed περιτροπή argument of "Theaetetus" 170c-171c have dominated the literature. One I call "the relativity reading". On this reading, the argument fails by ignoratio elenchi because it "carelessly" omits "the qualifications 'true for so-and-so' which [Protagoras'] theory insists on" (Bostock 1988: 90). The other reading I call "the many-worlds interpretation". On this view, Plato's argument succeeds in showing that "Protagoras' position becomes utterly self-contradictory" because "he claims that everyone lives in his own relativistic world, yet at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Puzzle of False Judgement in the Theaetetus.Nathanael Stein - 2016 - Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy 61 (3):260–283.
    A puzzle about false judgement is raised in the Theaetetus (187d-200c), but not successfully answered there. On the proposed account, the confusion that explicitly vitiates Theaetetus’ final attempt to define knowledge is already at work implicitly in this puzzle. Theaetetus shares popular assumptions about knowledge (epistēmē), but also accepts that there are cognitive constraints on judgement (doxa): the puzzle arises because he fails to distinguish the one cognitive condition from the other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La inversión del platonismo en la obra de Gilles Deleuze.Valeria Sonna - 2018 - Dianoia 63 (80):97-118.
    Resumen Propongo interpretar la inversión de Deleuze del platonismo como la creación de conceptos nuevos a partir de elementos teóricos tomados de la filosofía del propio Platón. En primer lugar, consideraré el origen nietzscheano de la inversión y su interpretación heideggeriana, de la cual, creo, Deleuze se vale para ciertos argumentos. En segundo lugar, me basaré en la hipótesis de Francis Wolff e Isabelle Ginoux de que la filosofía platónica tiene un carácter ambiguo en la obra deleuziana para analizar esa (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plato on Perception and ‘Commons’.Allan Silverman - 1990 - Classical Quarterly 40 (1):148-175.
    On the face of it, Plato's treatment of aisthesis is decidedly ambiguous. Sometimes he treats aisthesis as a faculty which, though distinct from all rational capacities, is nonetheless capable of forming judgments such as ‘This stick is bent’ or ‘The same thing is hard and soft’. In the Theaetetus, however, he appears to separate aisthesis from judgment, isolating the former from all prepositional, identificatory and recognitional capacities. The dilemma is easily expressed: Is perception a judgmental or cognitive capacity, or is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Platonic Anamnesis Revisited.Dominic Scott - 1987 - Classical Quarterly 37 (2):346-366.
    The belief in innate knowledge has a history almost as long as that of philosophy itself. In our own century it has been propounded in a linguistic context by Chomsky, who sees himself as the heir to a tradition including such philosophers as Descartes, the Cambridge Platonists and Leibniz. But the ancestor of all these is, of course, Plato's theory of recollection or anamnesis. This stands out as unique among all other innatist theses not simply because it was the first, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sophist 237-239.George Rudebusch - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (4):521-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge, Perception and Memory: Theaetetus 166 B.C. J. Rowe, M. Welbourne & C. J. F. Williams - 1982 - Classical Quarterly 32 (2):304-306.
    At Theaetetus 163d-164b Socrates objects to the thesis that knowledge is perception by pointing out that a man who has seen something can still remember it, and so has knowledge of it; but this is impossible, if knowledge is perception, since he is no longer perceiving it.To this Protagoras is made to reply with two sentences at 166b 1–4:.Cornford translates ‘ For instance, do you think you will find anyone to admit that one's present memory of a past impression is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Motion of Intellect On the Neoplatonic Reading of Sophist 248e-249d.Eric D. Perl - 2014 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2):135-160.
    This paper defends Plotinus’ reading ofSophist248e-249d as an expression of the togetherness or unity-in-duality of intellect and intelligible being. Throughout the dialogues Plato consistently presents knowledge as a togetherness of knower and known, expressing this through the myth of recollection and through metaphors of grasping, eating, and sexual union. He indicates that an intelligible paradigm is in the thought that apprehends it, and regularly regards the forms not as extrinsic “objects” but as the contents of living intelligence. A meticulous reading (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Science of Philosophy: Discourse and Deception in Plato’s Sophist.Pettersson Olof - 2018 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (2):221-237.
    At 252e1 to 253c9 in Plato’s Sophist, the Eleatic Visitor explains why philosophy is a science. Like the art of grammar, philosophical knowledge corresponds to a generic structure of discrete kinds and is acquired by systematic analysis of how these kinds intermingle. In the literature, the Visitor’s science is either understood as an expression of a mature and authentic platonic metaphysics, or as a sophisticated illusion staged to illustrate the seductive lure of sophistic deception. By showing how the Visitor’s account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What the Dialectician Discerns: a new reading of Sophist 253d-e.Mitchell Miller - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (2):321-352.
    At Sophist 253d-e the Eleatic Visitor offers a notoriously obscure description of the fields of one-and-many that the dialectician “adequately discerns.” Against the readings of Stenzel, Cornford, Sayre, and Gomez-Lobo, I propose an interpretation of that passage that takes into account the trilogy of Theaetetus-Sophist-Statesman as its context. The key steps are to respond to the irony of Socrates’ refutations at the end of the Theaetetus by reinterpreting the last two senses of logos as directed to forms and to recognize (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Socrate 'Dream' in the Theaetetus.Hans Meyerhoff - 1958 - Classical Quarterly 8 (3-4):131-.
    AT the beginning of the third part of the Theaetetus , Socrates entertains an interesting theory of knowledge in the form of a ‘dream’. In Cornford's translation, it reads as follows: I seem to have heard some people say that what might be called the first elements () of which we and all other things consist are such that no account () can be given of them. Each of them just by itself can only be named; we cannot attribute to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Colloquium 3.Mark L. McPherran - 1993 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 9 (1):112-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception, Relativism, and Truth: Reflections on Plato's Theaetetus 152–160.Mohan Matthen - 1985 - Dialogue 24 (1):33-.
    The standard interpretation of "Theaetetus" 152-160 has Plato attribute to Protagoras a relativistic theory of truth and existence. It is argued here that in fact the individuals of Protagorean worlds are inter-Personal. (thus the Protagorean theory has public objects, but private truth). Also, a new interpretation is offered of Plato's use of heraclitean flux to model relativism. The philosophical and semantic consequences of the interpretation are explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Talking Philosophy with Children.Gareth B. Matthews - 1976 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 10:46-62.
    When our oldest daughter, Sarah, was four years old the family kitten, Fluffy, contracted fleas. There ensued a primitive ritual of flea extermination that touched off the following discussion:Sarah: ‘Daddy, how did Fluffy get fleas?’Me: ‘Oh, I suspect she was playing with a cat that already had fleas. The fleas on that cat jumped off on to Fluffy.’Sarah : ‘And how did that cat get fleas?’Me : ‘Oh, probably from another cat.’Sarah : ‘But, Daddy, it can't go on and on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Plato’s methodological strategy in the first part of the Theaetetus.Graciela Marcos de Pinotti - 2016 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 16:31-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Peers on Socrates and Plato.Jim Mackenzie - 2014 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 46 (7):764-777.
    There is more to be said about two of the topics Chris Peers addresses in his article Freud, Plato and Irigaray: A morpho-logic of teaching and learning (2012, Educational Philosophy and Theory, 44, 760–774), namely the Socratic method of teaching and Plato’s stance with regard to women and feminism. My purpose in this article is to continue Peers’s discussion of these two topics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Commentary on Bett.Eric Lewis - 1999 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):167-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ΓΝΩΣΙΣ and ΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΗ in Socrates' Dream in the Theaetetus.James H. Lesher - 1969 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 89:72-78.
    At Theaetetus 201d-202c5 Socrates claims to have dreamt that we can have no knowledge of the simple elements of which we and all other things are composed, since no logos or ‘rational account’ can be given of them. We can, however, give a logos, and thereby acquire knowledge of a complex entity, a logos being understood in a minimal way as a combination of names. I argue that in his presentation and criticism of his ‘dream theory’ Plato systematically employs two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • X-RestlessForms andChangelessCauses.Fiona Leigh - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (2pt2):239-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Restless Forms and Changeless Causes.Fiona Leigh - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (2pt2):239-261.
    It is widely held that in Plato's Sophist, Forms rest or change or both. The received opinion is, however, false—or so I will argue. There is no direct support for it in the text and several passages tell against it. I will further argue that, contrary to the view of some scholars, Plato did not in this dialogue advocate a kind of change recognizable as 'Cambridge change', as applicable to his Forms. The reason that Forms neither change nor rest is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Plato on kinds of animals.David B. Kitts - 1987 - Biology and Philosophy 2 (3):315-328.
    Some biologists and philosophers of biology have seen in Plato an especially objectionable version of essentialism or topology. Although kinds of animals are mentioned in almost all of Plato's dialogues, in none of them is there an explicity stated doctrine of animal kinds. An examination of the dialogues has, moreover, failed to reveal some implicit but consistent and unambiguous view of kinds that Plato might have held.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plato's Task in the Sophist.R. W. Jordan - 1984 - Classical Quarterly 34 (1):113-129.
    It is often thought that Plato sets himself an important task in the Sophist – that of disentangling different uses, or senses, of the verb einai. Plato is thought to have confused different senses or uses of the verb in his philosophical youth; here he is supposed to correct his mistake, and to mark out a danger area for his successors.1 Plato is also often supposed, by commentators, to have set himself the task of disentangling a second confusion – a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Praesens de futuris: Whitehead on How to Be Going to Move Forward into the Future.Gottfried Heinemann - 2019 - Axiomathes 29 (1):17-32.
    Whitehead’s metaphysics involves an event ontology. Fundamental—that is, in Whitehead’s language: “actual”—entities are events, described as acts of experience. It also involves presentism since past events have perished and future events do not yet exist according to Whitehead. Hence the question alluded to in the title of the present paper: “How are you going to move forward into the future?… If you conceive it under the guise of a temporal transition into the non-existent, you can’t get going.” I will argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Notes on Heraclitus in the Theaetetus, Symposium and Sophist.Ana Flaksman - 2015 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 15:87-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alcidamas of Elaea in Plato's Phaedrus.Slobodan Dušanić - 1992 - Classical Quarterly 42 (2):347-357.
    In Bk. 3 of the Institutio oratoria, Quintilian gives a list of the Greek artium scriptores of the classical epoch. It contains a controversial entry: ‘…et, quem Palameden Plato appellat, Alcidamas Elaites’. The historicity of the rhetorician and sophist from Elaea named Alcidamas, Gorgias' pupil, is of course beyond doubt; scholars disagree only as to the ‘quem Palameden Plato appellat’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • πολλαχῶς ἔστι; Plato’s Neglected Ontology.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    This paper aims to suggest a new approach to Plato’s theory of being in Republic V and Sophist based on the notion of difference and the being of a copy. To understand Plato’s ontology in these two dialogues we are going to suggest a theory we call Pollachos Esti; a name we took from Aristotle’s pollachos legetai both to remind the similarities of the two structures and to reach a consistent view of Plato’s ontology. Based on this theory, when Plato (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Onto-Epistemological Chronology of Plato’s Dialogues.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    This paper aims to suggest a new arrangement of Plato’s dialogues based on a different theory of the ontological as well as epistemological development of his philosophy. In this new arrangement, which proposes essential changes in the currently agreed upon chronology of the dialogues, Parmenides must be considered as criticizing an elementary theory of Forms and not the theory of so-called middle dialogues. Dated all as later than Parmenides, the so-called middle and late dialoguesare regarded as two consecutive endeavors to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Critique of the Standard Chronology of Plato's Dialogues.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - manuscript
    That i) there is a somehow determined chronology of Plato’s dialogues among all the chronologies of the last century and ii) this theory is subject to many objections, are points this article intends to discuss. Almost all the main suggested chronologies of the last century agree that Parmenides and Theaetetus should be located after dialogues like Meno, Phaedo and Republic and before Sophist, Politicus, Timaeus, Laws and Philebus. The eight objections we brought against this arrangement claim that to place the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark