Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Interaction with autonomy: Multiple Output models and the inadequacy of the Great Divide.Julie E. Boland & Anne Cutler - 1996 - Cognition 58 (3):309-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A two-tiered cognitive architecture for moral reasoning.John Bolender - 2001 - Biology and Philosophy 16 (3):339-356.
    The view that moral cognition is subserved by a two-tieredarchitecture is defended: Moral reasoning is the result both ofspecialized, informationally encapsulated modules which automaticallyand effortlessly generate intuitions; and of general-purpose,cognitively penetrable mechanisms which enable moral judgment in thelight of the agent's general fund of knowledge. This view is contrastedwith rival architectures of social/moral cognition, such as Cosmidesand Tooby's view that the mind is wholly modular, and it is argued thata two-tiered architecture is more plausible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The architectural nonchalance of commonsense psychology.Radu J. Bogdan - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (2):189-205.
    Eliminativism assumes that commonsense psychology describes and explains the mind in terms of the internal design and operation of the mind. If this assumption is invalidated, so is eliminativism. The same conditional is true of intentional realism. Elsewhere (Bogdan 1991) I have argued against this 'folk- theory-theory' assumption by showing that commonsense psychology is not an empirical prototheory of the mind but a biosocially motivated practice of coding, utilizing, and sharing information from and about conspecifics. Here, without presupposing a specific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Architectural Nonchalance of Commonsense Psychology.Radu J. Bogdan - 2007 - Mind and Language 8 (2):189-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Experience, Phenomenal Character and Epistemic Justification.Paul Boghossian - 2015 - Philosophical Issues 25 (1):243-251.
    Suppose that, while looking at a red strawberry under normal conditions, I form the judgment that there is something red in front of me. We may stipulate that my judgment is based on my experience of the red strawberry. As a result, my judgment is justified by my experience. In virtue of what aspects of my experience is my judgment justified? In particular: Does the phenomenal character of my experience of something red play an important role in the justification of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The shape of the human language-ready brain.Cedric Boeckx - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • New elements of a theory of mind in wild chimpanzees.Christophe Boesch - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Philosophy of Cognitive Science.Margaret A. Boden - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 48:209-226.
    If the Trade Descriptions Act were applied to academic labels, cognitive scientists would be in trouble. For what they do is much wider than the name suggests—and wider, too, than most philosophers assume. They give you more for your money than you may have expected.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representational redescription: A question of sequence.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):708-708.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Fodorian guide to Switzerland: Jung and Piaget combined?Péter Bodor & Csaba Pléh - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):709-710.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The social construction of mind and the future of cognitive science.Jerzy Bobryk - 2002 - Foundations of Science 7 (4):481-495.
    Cognitive activity, which essentially consistsof the use of signs, does not only depend onthe internal (mental, or brain) processes. Thefirst part of the paper presents severalversions of the idea of the external andcultural organization of individual''s mentalprocesses. The second part of the paperconsiders a future development of cognitivescience as a science of the extended andsocially constructed mind. KazimierzTwardowski''s theory of intentionality and histheory of actions and products provide theconceptual framework of the undertaken analysis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanation in personality psychology: “Verbal magic” and the five-factor model.Simon Boag - 2011 - Philosophical Psychology 24 (2):223-243.
    Scientific psychology involves both identifying and classifying phenomena of interest (description) and revealing the causes and mechanisms that contribute towards these phenomena arising (explanation). Within personality psychology, some propose that aspects of behavior and cognition can be explained with reference to personality traits. However, certain conceptual and logical issues cast doubt upon the adequacy of traits as coherent explanatory constructs. This paper discusses ?explanation? in psychology and the problems of circularity and reification. An analysis of relations and intrinsic properties is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • No Need for Alarm: A Critical Analysis of Greene’s Dual-Process Theory of Moral Decision-Making.Robyn Bluhm - 2014 - Neuroethics 7 (3):299-316.
    Joshua Greene and his colleagues have proposed a dual-process theory of moral decision-making to account for the effects of emotional responses on our judgments about moral dilemmas that ask us to contemplate causing direct personal harm. Early formulations of the theory contrast emotional and cognitive decision-making, saying that each is the product of a separable neural system. Later formulations emphasize that emotions are also involved in cognitive processing. I argue that, given the acknowledgement that emotions inform cognitive decision-making, a single-process (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond the Basics: The Evolution and Development of Human Emotions.Robyn Bluhm - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (sup1):73-94.
    The suggestion that at least some emotions are modular captures a number of our intuitions about emotions: they are generally fast responses to a stimulus, they are involuntary, and they are easily distinguished from one another; we simply know that, for example, anger feels different than fear. Candidates for modular emotions are usually the so-called “basic” emotions - anger and fear are good examples of these. Defenders of emotion theories that focus on basic emotions, such as Paul Ekman in psychology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The real problem with constructivism.Paul Bloom & Karen Wynn - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):707-708.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foundational Questions about Concepts: Context‐sensitivity and Embodiment.Corinne L. Bloch-Mullins - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (12):940-952.
    This review discusses recent work on foundational questions about concepts. The first of these questions is whether concepts are context-independent bodies of knowledge, or context-dependent constructs, created on the fly. The second question is whether concepts are abstract, amodal representations, or whether they are embedded within the sensory-motor system. I discuss these two questions in light of empirical data from psychology and neuroscience, as well as theoretical considerations, and examine their implications for theories of concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Evidence against epiphenomenalism.Ned Block - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):670-672.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh between Psychology and Neuroscience.Ned Block - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5):481--548.
    How can we disentangle the neural basis of phenomenal consciousness from the neural machinery of the cognitive access that underlies reports of phenomenal consciousness? We can see the problem in stark form if we ask how we could tell whether representations inside a Fodorian module are phenomenally conscious. The methodology would seem straightforward: find the neural natural kinds that are the basis of phenomenal consciousness in clear cases when subjects are completely confident and we have no reason to doubt their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.Ned Block - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):615-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   346 citations  
  • Unarticulated meaning.James Blachowicz - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (1):43 - 70.
    It is a common experience of mental life that we come to articulate meanings which we had initially grasped in only a sketchy way. In this paper, I consider how this idea of an initially unarticulated meaning may fit in a general theory of mental representation. I propose to identify unarticulated meanings with what I callspecific concepts, which are quite similar to Rosch's categories of basic objects and are distinct both from images and generic concepts (which come to articulate meanings). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does the nervous system use equilibrium-point control to guide single and multiple joint movements?E. Bizzi, N. Hogan, F. A. Mussa-Ivaldi & S. Giszter - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):603-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Evidence of divergence in vertebrate learning.M. E. Bitterman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Through the looking-glass and what cognitive psychology found there.Edoardo Bisiach - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):24-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The supremacy of syntax.Derek Bickerton - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unified cognitive theory: You can't get there from here.Derek Bickerton - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):437-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Putting cognitive carts before linguistic horses.Derek Bickerton - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):749-750.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An innate language faculty needs neither modularity nor localization.Derek Bickerton - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):631-632.
    Müller misconstrues autonomy to mean strict locality of brain function, something quite different from the functional autonomy that linguists claim. Similarly, he misperceives the interaction of learned and innate components hypothesized in current generative models. Evidence from sign languages, Creole languages, and neurological studies of rare forms of aphasia also argues against his conclusions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What properly belongs to grammar? A response to Lepore and Stone.Anne Bezuidenhout - 2016 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 59 (2):175-194.
    Lepore and Stone devote Part I of their book to setting out a number of views that act as foils for their own positive ‘disambiguation’ view of interpretation developed in Part II. They divide their opposition into three camps: The Gricean rationalists, the neo-Gricean lexicalists, and the empirical psychologists. I try to show why a ‘disambiguation’ view of such phenomena is unappealing and why Relevance Theory provides a better account of these phenomena. I end with some brief remarks about what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Where are the bastards' daddies?Laura Betzig - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):284-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When weak explanations prevail.Carl Bereiter & Marlene Scardamalia - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):468-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is at stake in the debate on nonconceptual content?José Luis Bermúdez - 2007 - Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1):55–72.
    It is now 25 years since Gareth Evans introduced the distinction between conceptual and nonconceptual content in The Varieties of Reference. This is a fitting time to take stock of what has become a complex and extended debate both within philosophy and at the interface between philosophy and psychology. Unfortunately, the debate has become increasingly murky as it has become increasingly ramified. Much of the contemporary discussion does not do full justice to the powerful theoretical tool originally proposed by Evans (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The syntactic process: Language, speech, and communication, mark Steedman. [REVIEW]Raffaella Bernardi - 2004 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 13 (4):526-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Muller-Lyer illusion explained and its theoretical importance reconsidered.Bob Bermond & Jaap Van Heerden - 1996 - Biology and Philosophy 11 (3):321-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Muller-lyer illusion explained and its theoretical importance reconsidered.Bob Bermond & Jaap Heerden - 1996 - Biology and Philosophy 11 (3):321-338.
    The Müller-Lyer illusion is the natural consequence of the construction of the vertebrate eye, retina and visual processing system. Due to imperfections in the vertebrate eye and retina and due to the subsequent processing in the system by ever increasing receptive fields, the visual information becomes less and less precise with respect to exact location and size. The consequence of this is that eventually the brain has to calculate a weighted mean value of the information, which is spread out over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The anecdotal nature of religious disagreements.Daniele Bertini - 2019 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 80 (3):215-229.
    Most literature on religious disagreements focuses on the epistemic problems related to doctrinal disputes. While, the main argument of my paper does not address such a topic, my purpose is to point at a practical exit strategy from the blind spot to which most disagreements lead. However, in order to argue for my views, I need to provide a substantive account of how religious beliefs work and which epistemic obligations they involve. Such account challenges most mainstream assumptions, and needs to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Going Beyond the Catch-22 of Autism Diagnosis and Research. The Moral Implications of (Not) Asking “What Is Autism?”.Jo Bervoets & Kristien Hens - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Psychiatric diagnoses such as Autism Spectrum Disorder (ASD) are primarily attributed on the basis of behavioral criteria. The aim of most of the biomedical research on ASD is to uncover the underlying mechanisms that lead to or even cause pathological behavior. However, in the philosophical and sociological literature, it has been suggested that autism is also to some extent a ‘social construct’ that cannot merely be reduced to its biological explanation. We show that a one-sided adherence to either a biological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Cognitive explanations: Plausibility is not enough.Irwin S. Bernstein - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):593-594.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Assembling the Emotions.Vincent Bergeron & Mohan Matthen - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (sup1):185-212.
    Endogenous depression is highly correlated with low levels of serotonin in the central nervous system. Does this imply or suggest that this sort of depression just is this neurochemical deficit? Scorning such an inference, Antonio Damasio writes:If feeling happy or sad … corresponds in part to the cognitive modes under which your thoughts are operating, then the explanation also requires that the chemical acts on the circuits which generate and manipulate [such thoughts]. Which means that reducing depression to a statement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Anatomical and functional modularity in cognitive science: Shifting the focus.Vincent Bergeron - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (2):175 – 195.
    Much of cognitive science is committed to the modular approach to the study of cognition. The core of this approach consists of a pair of assumptions - the anatomical and the functional modularity assumptions - which motivate two kinds of inference: the anatomical and the functional modularity inferences. The legitimacy of both of these inferences has been strongly challenged, a situation that has had surprisingly little impact on most theorizing in the field. Following the introduction of an important, yet rarely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Use of the phrase “personal relationship with jesus”: Toward a comprehensive interdisciplinary explanation.Benjamin Bennett-Carpenter - 2017 - Zygon 52 (3):663-690.
    When people use the phrase “personal relationship with Jesus,” how does one explain its significance? Normally attributed to evangelical Protestant Christians, use of the phrase “personal relationship with Jesus” is a complicated phenomenon, and an explanation of it requires drawing upon resources from across multiple disciplines rather than a single discipline only. Attempts to explain exactly what the phrase “personal relationship with Jesus” means frequently can be mystifying, on the one hand, or dismissive and simplistic, on the other hand. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Recognition of Emotions in Music and Landscapes: Extending Contour Theory.Marta Benenti & Cristina Meini - 2018 - Philosophia 46 (3):647-664.
    While inanimate objects can neither experience nor express emotions, in principle they can be expressive of emotions. In particular, music is a paradigmatic example of something expressive of emotions that surely cannot feel anything at all. The Contour theory accounts for music expressiveness in terms of those resemblances that hold between its external and perceivable properties and the typical contour of human emotional behavior. Provided that some critical aspects are emended – notably, the stress on the perception of similarity instead (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Problems with explaining the perceptual environment.Aaron Ben-Ze'ev - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):30-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A critique of the inferential paradigm in perception.Aaron Ben-Zeev - 1987 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 17 (3):243–263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two constructive themes.Richard K. Belew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):25-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dual Process Theory: Systems, Types, Minds, Modes, Kinds or Metaphors? A Critical Review.Samuel C. Bellini-Leite - 2018 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 9 (2):213-225.
    Dual process theory proposes clusters of features that form two dichotomous groups in cognition. One standing internal issue is defining what the reference of these two dichotomous groups could be in the mind or brain. Does dual process theory speak of two systems, types, minds, modes, kinds or just metaphors? A particular common answer is that differences in clusters of features are evidence of different underlying systems, often called system 1 and system 2. However, the suggestion to abandon the ‘system’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alteraciones del Relato.Mercedes Belinchón & Patricia Insúa - 2004 - Arbor 177 (697):157-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tools, terms, and telencephalons: Neural correlates of “complex’ and “intelligent” behavior”.Marc Bekoff - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):591-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptual expansion under cognitive guidance: Lessons from language processing.Endre Begby - 2017 - Mind and Language 32 (5):564-578.
    This paper aims to provide an empirically informed sketch of how our perceptual capacities can interact with cognitive processes to give rise to new perceptual attributives. In section 1, I present ongoing debates about the reach of perception and direct focus toward arguments offered in recent work by Tyler Burge and Ned Block. In section 2, I draw on empirical evidence relating to language processing to argue against the claim that we have no acquired, culture-specific, high-level perceptual attributives. In section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Constraints on perceptual learning: objects and dimensions.Felice L. Bedford - 1995 - Cognition 54 (3):253-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Looking down, around, and up: Mechanistic explanation in psychology.William Bechtel - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (5):543-564.
    Accounts of mechanistic explanation have emphasized the importance of looking down—decomposing a mechanism into its parts and operations. Using research on visual processing as an exemplar, I illustrate how productive such research has been. But once multiple components of a mechanism have been identified, researchers also need to figure out how it is organized—they must look around and determine how to recompose the mechanism. Although researchers often begin by trying to recompose the mechanism in terms of sequential operations, they frequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations