Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Quantifier Variance and the Collapse Argument.Jared Warren - 2015 - Philosophical Quarterly 65 (259):241-253.
    Recently a number of works in meta-ontology have used a variant of J.H. Harris's collapse argument in the philosophy of logic as an argument against Eli Hirsch's quantifier variance. There have been several responses to the argument in the literature, but none of them have identified the central failing of the argument, viz., the argument has two readings: one on which it is sound but doesn't refute quantifier variance and another on which it is unsound. The central lesson I draw (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Recursively enumerable complexity sequences and measure independence.Victor L. Bennison - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):417-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representability in second-order propositional poly-modal logic.G. Aldo Antonelli & Richmond H. Thomason - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1039-1054.
    A propositional system of modal logic is second-order if it contains quantifiers ∀p and ∃p, which, in the standard interpretation, are construed as ranging over sets of possible worlds (propositions). Most second-order systems of modal logic are highly intractable; for instance, when augmented with propositional quantifiers, K, B, T, K4 and S4 all become effectively equivalent to full second-order logic. An exception is S5, which, being interpretable in monadic second-order logic, is decidable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Empiricism, Probability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic.Sean Walsh - 2014 - Journal of Applied Logic 12 (3):319–348.
    The topic of this paper is our knowledge of the natural numbers, and in particular, our knowledge of the basic axioms for the natural numbers, namely the Peano axioms. The thesis defended in this paper is that knowledge of these axioms may be gained by recourse to judgements of probability. While considerations of probability have come to the forefront in recent epistemology, it seems safe to say that the thesis defended here is heterodox from the vantage point of traditional philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vaught's theorem on axiomatizability by a scheme.Albert Visser - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):382-402.
    In his 1967 paper Vaught used an ingenious argument to show that every recursively enumerable first order theory that directly interprets the weak system VS of set theory is axiomatizable by a scheme. In this paper we establish a strengthening of Vaught's theorem by weakening the hypothesis of direct interpretability of VS to direct interpretability of the finitely axiomatized fragment VS2 of VS. This improvement significantly increases the scope of the original result, since VS is essentially undecidable, but VS2 has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Axiomatizability by a schema.Robert L. Vaught - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (4):473-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A mathematical characterization of interpretation between theories.J. Van Benthem - 1984 - Studia Logica 43:295.
    Of the various notions of reduction in the logical literature, relative interpretability in the sense of Tarskiet al. [6] appears to be the central one. In the present note, this syntactic notion is characterized semantically, through the existence of a suitable reduction functor on models. The latter mathematical condition itself suggests a natural generalization, whose syntactic equivalent turns out to be a notion of interpretability quite close to that of Ershov [1], Szczerba [5] and Gaifman [2].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Address at the Princeton University Bicentennial Conference on Problems of Mathematics (December 17–19, 1946), By Alfred Tarski.Alfred Tarski & Hourya Sinaceur - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):1-44.
    This article presents Tarski's Address at the Princeton Bicentennial Conference on Problems of Mathematics, together with a separate summary. Two accounts of the discussion which followed are also included. The central topic of the Address and of the discussion is decision problems. The introductory note gives information about the Conference, about the background of the subjects discussed in the Address, and about subsequent developments to these subjects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why There is no General Solution to the Problem of Software Verification.John Symons & Jack K. Horner - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (3):541-557.
    How can we be certain that software is reliable? Is there any method that can verify the correctness of software for all cases of interest? Computer scientists and software engineers have informally assumed that there is no fully general solution to the verification problem. In this paper, we survey approaches to the problem of software verification and offer a new proof for why there can be no general solution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Języki i teorie adekwatne z ontologią języka nauki.Henryk Stonert - 1964 - Studia Logica 15 (1):49-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sequential theories and infinite distributivity in the lattice of chapters.Alan S. Stern - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):190-206.
    We introduce a notion of complexity for interpretations, which is used to prove some new results about interpretations of sequential theories. In particular, we give a new, elementary proof of Pudlák's theorem that sequential theories are connected. We also demonstrate a counterexample to the infinitary distributive law $a \vee \bigwedge_{i \in I} b_i = \bigwedge_{i \in I} (a \vee b_i)$ in the lattice of chapters, in which the chapters a and b i are compact. (Counterexamples in which a is not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some new results on decidability for elementary algebra and geometry.Robert M. Solovay, R. D. Arthan & John Harrison - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1765-1802.
    We carry out a systematic study of decidability for theories of real vector spaces, inner product spaces, and Hilbert spaces and of normed spaces, Banach spaces and metric spaces, all formalized using a 2-sorted first-order language. The theories for list turn out to be decidable while the theories for list are not even arithmetical: the theory of 2-dimensional Banach spaces, for example, has the same many-one degree as the set of truths of second-order arithmetic.We find that the purely universal and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Measure independent Gödel speed‐ups and the relative difficulty of recognizing sets.Martin K. Solomon - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):384-392.
    We provide and interpret a new measure independent characterization of the Gödel speed-up phenomenon. In particular, we prove a theorem that demonstrates the indifference of the concept of a measure independent Gödel speed-up to an apparent weakening of its definition that is obtained by requiring only those measures appearing in some fixed Blum complexity measure to participate in the speed-up, and by deleting the “for all r” condition from the definition so as to relax the required amount of speed-up. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theories with Effectively Inseparable Nuclei.Raymond M. Smullyan - 1960 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 6 (15-22):219-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Undecidability and recursive inseparability.Raymond M. Smullyan - 1958 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 4 (7-11):143-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Elementary intuitionistic theories.C. Smorynski - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):102-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Some Notes on Truths and Comprehension.Thomas Schindler - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (3):449-479.
    In this paper we study several translations that map models and formulae of the language of second-order arithmetic to models and formulae of the language of truth. These translations are useful because they allow us to exploit results from the extensive literature on arithmetic to study the notion of truth. Our purpose is to present these connections in a systematic way, generalize some well-known results in this area, and to provide a number of new results. Sections 3 and 4 contain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logical consequence revisited.José M. Sagüillo - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):216-241.
    Tarski's 1936 paper, “On the concept of logical consequence”, is a rather philosophical, non-technical paper that leaves room for conflicting interpretations. My purpose is to review some important issues that explicitly or implicitly constitute its themes. My discussion contains four sections: terminological and conceptual preliminaries, Tarski's definition of the concept of logical consequence, Tarski's discussion of omega-incomplete theories, and concluding remarks concerning the kind of conception that Tarski's definition was intended to explicate. The third section involves subsidiary issues, such as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • An introduction to hyperarithmetical functions.Julia Robinson - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):325-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • String theory.John Corcoran, William Frank & Michael Maloney - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (4):625-637.
    For each positive n , two alternative axiomatizations of the theory of strings over n alphabetic characters are presented. One class of axiomatizations derives from Tarski's system of the Wahrheitsbegriff and uses the n characters and concatenation as primitives. The other class involves using n character-prefixing operators as primitives and derives from Hermes' Semiotik. All underlying logics are second order. It is shown that, for each n, the two theories are definitionally equivalent [or synonymous in the sense of deBouvere]. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Cuts, consistency statements and interpretations.Pavel Pudlák - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):423-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • The axiomatic system of the factorial implication.August Pieczkowski - 1966 - Studia Logica 18 (1):41 - 64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Über Theorien im erweiterten Sinne.August Pieczkowski - 1974 - Studia Logica 33 (4):317-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On a Question of Krajewski's.Fedor Pakhomov & Albert Visser - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):343-358.
    In this paper, we study finitely axiomatizable conservative extensions of a theoryUin the case whereUis recursively enumerable and not finitely axiomatizable. Stanisław Krajewski posed the question whether there are minimal conservative extensions of this sort. We answer this question negatively.Consider a finite expansion of the signature ofUthat contains at least one predicate symbol of arity ≥ 2. We show that, for any finite extensionαofUin the expanded language that is conservative overU, there is a conservative extensionβofUin the expanded language, such that$\alpha (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Decidability of ∀*∀‐Sentences in Membership Theories.Eugenio G. Omodeo, Franco Parlamento & Alberto Policriti - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):41-58.
    The problem is addressed of establishing the satisfiability of prenex formulas involving a single universal quantifier, in diversified axiomatic set theories. A rather general decision method for solving this problem is illustrated through the treatment of membership theories of increasing strength, ending with a subtheory of Zermelo-Fraenkel which is already complete with respect to the ∀*∀ class of sentences. NP-hardness and NP-completeness results concerning the problems under study are achieved and a technique for restricting the universal quantifier is presented.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Analysis without actual infinity.Jan Mycielski - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (3):625-633.
    We define a first-order theory FIN which has a recursive axiomatization and has the following two properties. Each finite part of FIN has finite models. FIN is strong enough to develop that part of mathematics which is used or has potential applications in natural science. This work can also be regarded as a consistency proof of this hitherto informal part of mathematics. In FIN one can count every set; this permits one to prove some new probabilistic theorems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Restricted Decision Problems in Some Classes of Algebraic Systems.Michałl Muzalewski - 1978 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 24 (17-18):279-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • We Turing Machines Can’t Even Be Locally Ideal Bayesians.Beau Madison Mount - 2016 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 5 (4):285-290.
    Vann McGee has argued that, given certain background assumptions and an ought-implies-can thesis about norms of rationality, Bayesianism conflicts globally with computationalism due to the fact that Robinson arithmetic is essentially undecidable. I show how to sharpen McGee's result using an additional fact from recursion theory—the existence of a computable sequence of computable reals with an uncomputable limit. In conjunction with the countable additivity requirement on probabilities, such a sequence can be used to construct a specific proposition to which Bayesianism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Partially ordered interpretations.Nobuyoshi Motohashi - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):83-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Theories incomparable with respect to relative interpretability.Richard Montague - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (2):195-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Intertheoretic Reduction, Confirmation, and Montague’s Syntax-Semantics Relation.Kristina Liefke & Stephan Hartmann - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (4):313-341.
    Intertheoretic relations are an important topic in the philosophy of science. However, since their classical discussion by Ernest Nagel, such relations have mostly been restricted to relations between pairs of theories in the natural sciences. This paper presents a case study of a new type of intertheoretic relation that is inspired by Montague’s analysis of the linguistic syntax-semantics relation. The paper develops a simple model of this relation. To motivate the adoption of our new model, we show that this model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Coordinate-free logic.Joop Leo - 2016 - Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):522-555.
    A new logic is presented without predicates—except equality. Yet its expressive power is the same as that of predicate logic, and relations can faithfully be represented in it. In this logic we also develop an alternative for set theory. There is a need for such a new approach, since we do not live in a world of sets and predicates, but rather in a world of things with relations between them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Generalization of Definitional Equivalence to Non-Disjoint Languages.Koen Lefever & Gergely Székely - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (4):709-729.
    For simplicity, most of the literature introduces the concept of definitional equivalence only for disjoint languages. In a recent paper, Barrett and Halvorson introduce a straightforward generalization to non-disjoint languages and they show that their generalization is not equivalent to intertranslatability in general. In this paper, we show that their generalization is not transitive and hence it is not an equivalence relation. Then we introduce another formalization of definitional equivalence due to Andréka and Németi which is equivalent to the Barrett–Halvorson (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Notion of Interpretation and Nonelementary Languages.Michal Krynicki - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (6):541-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Notion of Interpretation and Nonelementary Languages.Michal Krynicki - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (6):541-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A survey of proof theory.G. Kreisel - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (3):321-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Some Theorems on the Lattice of Local Interpretability Types.Jan Krajíček - 1985 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 31 (29-30):449-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Predicative Expansions of Axiomatic Theories.Stanissław Krajewski - 1974 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 20 (28-29):435-452.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ultraproducts which are not saturated.H. Jerome Keisler - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (1):23-46.
    In this paper we continue our study, begun in [5], of the connection between ultraproducts and saturated structures. IfDis an ultrafilter over a setI, andis a structure, the ultrapower ofmoduloDis denoted byD-prod. The ultrapower is important because it is a method of constructing structures which are elementarily equivalent to a given structure. Our ultimate aim is to find out what kinds of structure are ultrapowers of. We made a beginning in [5] by proving that, assuming the generalized continuum hypothesis, for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Effectively retractable theories and degrees of undecidability.J. P. Jones - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):597-604.
    In this paper a new property of theories, called effective retractability is introduced and used to obtain a characterization for the degrees of subtheories of arithmetic and set theory. By theory we understand theory in standard formalization as defined by Tarski [10]. The word degree refers to the Kleene-Post notion of degree of recursive unsolvability [2]. By the degree of a theory we mean, of course, the degree associated with its decision problem via Gödel numbering.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non‐Effectiveness in S. Orey's Arithmetical Compactness Theorem.R. G. Jeroslow - 1971 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 17 (1):285-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Restrictiveness relative to notions of interpretation.Luca Incurvati & Benedikt Löwe - 2016 - Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (2): 238-250.
    Maddy gave a semi-formal account of restrictiveness by defining a formal notion based on a class of interpretations and explaining how to handle false positives and false negatives. Recently, Hamkins pointed out some structural issues with Maddy's definition. We look at Maddy's formal definitions from the point of view of an abstract interpretation relation. We consider various candidates for this interpretation relation, including one that is close to Maddy's original notion, but fixes the issues raised by Hamkins. Our work brings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The semantic view of theories and higher-order languages.Laurenz Hudetz - 2017 - Synthese 196 (3):1131-1149.
    Several philosophers of science construe models of scientific theories as set-theoretic structures. Some of them moreover claim that models should not be construed as structures in the sense of model theory because the latter are language-dependent. I argue that if we are ready to construe models as set-theoretic structures (strict semantic view), we could equally well construe them as model-theoretic structures of higher-order logic (liberal semantic view). I show that every family of set-theoretic structures has an associated language of higher-order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The härtig quantifier: A survey.Heinrich Herre, Michał Krynicki, Alexandr Pinus & Jouko Väänänen - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1153-1183.
    A fundamental notion in a large part of mathematics is the notion of equicardinality. The language with Hartig quantifier is, roughly speaking, a first-order language in which the notion of equicardinality is expressible. Thus this language, denoted by LI, is in some sense very natural and has in consequence special interest. Properties of LI are studied in many papers. In [BF, Chapter VI] there is a short survey of some known results about LI. We feel that a more extensive exposition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • In memoriam: Raphael Mitchel Robinson.Leon Henkin - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):340-343.
    About a month after his 83rd birthday Raphael Robinson was almost wholly incapacitated by a massive stroke, and 8 weeks later, on January 27, 1995, he died of ensuing complications. Mathematics was his life. He was always working on problems—those brought to him in journals or by colleagues, and others that he invented. Just three days before his death he received word that a paper of his, originating in a published problem, was accepted for publication. His 64 publications spanned a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Interpretability suprema in Peano Arithmetic.Paula Henk & Albert Visser - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (5-6):555-584.
    This paper develops the philosophy and technology needed for adding a supremum operator to the interpretability logic ILM\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathsf {ILM}$$\end{document} of Peano Arithmetic. It is well-known that any theories extending PA\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathsf {PA}$$\end{document} have a supremum in the interpretability ordering. While provable in PA\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathsf {PA}$$\end{document}, this fact is not reflected in the theorems of the modal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is Frege's Definition of the Ancestral Adequate?Richard G. Heck - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (1):91-116.
    Why should one think Frege's definition of the ancestral correct? It can be proven to be extensionally correct, but the argument uses arithmetical induction, and that seems to undermine Frege's claim to have justified induction in purely logical terms. I discuss such circularity objections and then offer a new definition of the ancestral intended to be intensionally correct; its extensional correctness then follows without proof. This new definition can be proven equivalent to Frege's without any use of arithmetical induction. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consistency and the theory of truth.Richard Heck - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):424-466.
    This paper attempts to address the question what logical strength theories of truth have by considering such questions as: If you take a theory T and add a theory of truth to it, how strong is the resulting theory, as compared to T? Once the question has been properly formulated, the answer turns out to be about as elegant as one could want: Adding a theory of truth to a finitely axiomatized theory T is more or less equivalent to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Über die Universalität Axiomatisierbarer Fragmente der Zahlentheorie.Kurt Hauschild - 1972 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 18 (16‐18):255-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Substitutional Analysis of Logical Consequence.Volker Halbach - 2019 - Noûs 54 (2):431-450.
    A substitutional account of logical validity for formal first‐order languages is developed and defended against competing accounts such as the model‐theoretic definition of validity. Roughly, a substitution instance of a sentence is defined as the result of uniformly substituting nonlogical expressions in the sentence with expressions of the same grammatical category and possibly relativizing quantifiers. In particular, predicate symbols can be replaced with formulae possibly containing additional free variables. A sentence is defined to be logically true iff all its substitution (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations