Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logic and the epistemic foundations of game theory: special issue.Michael O. L. Bacharach & Philippe Mongin - 1994 - Theory and Decision 37 (1):1-6.
    An introduction to the special issue on epistemic logic and the foundations of game theory edited by Michael Bacharach and Philippe Mongin. Contributors are Michael Bacharach, Robert Stalnaker, Salvatore Modica and Aldo Rustichini, Luc Lismont and Philippe Mongin, and Hyun-Song Shin and Timothy Williamson.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • BDD-based decision procedures for the modal logic K ★.Guoqiang Pan, Ulrike Sattler & Moshe Y. Vardi - 2006 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 16 (1-2):169-207.
    We describe BDD-based decision procedures for the modal logic K. Our approach is inspired by the automata-theoretic approach, but we avoid explicit automata construction. Instead, we compute certain fixpoints of a set of types — which can be viewed as an on-the-fly emptiness of the automaton. We use BDDs to represent and manipulate such type sets, and investigate different kinds of representations as well as a “level-based” representation scheme. The latter turns out to speed up construction and reduce memory consumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Algorithmic correspondence and completeness in modal logic. IV. Semantic extensions of SQEMA.Willem Conradie & Valentin Goranko - 2008 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 18 (2):175-211.
    In a previous work we introduced the algorithm \SQEMA\ for computing first-order equivalents and proving canonicity of modal formulae, and thus established a very general correspondence and canonical completeness result. \SQEMA\ is based on transformation rules, the most important of which employs a modal version of a result by Ackermann that enables elimination of an existentially quantified predicate variable in a formula, provided a certain negative polarity condition on that variable is satisfied. In this paper we develop several extensions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Logic of Common Belief.Giacomo Bonanno - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):305-311.
    We investigate an axiomatization of the notion of common belief that makes use of no rules of inference and highlight the property of the set of accessibility relations that characterizes each axiom.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On the logic of common belief and common knowledge.Luc Lismont & Philippe Mongin - 1994 - Theory and Decision 37 (1):75-106.
    The paper surveys the currently available axiomatizations of common belief (CB) and common knowledge (CK) by means of modal propositional logics. (Throughout, knowledge- whether individual or common- is defined as true belief.) Section 1 introduces the formal method of axiomatization followed by epistemic logicians, especially the syntax-semantics distinction, and the notion of a soundness and completeness theorem. Section 2 explains the syntactical concepts, while briefly discussing their motivations. Two standard semantic constructions, Kripke structures and neighbourhood structures, are introduced in Sections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Cooperation, knowledge, and time: Alternating-time temporal epistemic logic and its applications.Wiebe van der Hoek & Michael Wooldridge - 2003 - Studia Logica 75 (1):125-157.
    Branching-time temporal logics have proved to be an extraordinarily successful tool in the formal specification and verification of distributed systems. Much of their success stems from the tractability of the model checking problem for the branching time logic CTL, which has made it possible to implement tools that allow designers to automatically verify that systems satisfy requirements expressed in CTL. Recently, CTL was generalised by Alur, Henzinger, and Kupferman in a logic known as Alternating-time Temporal Logic (ATL). The key insight (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Complexity of interpolation and related problems in positive calculi.Larisa Maksimova - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (1):397-408.
    We consider the problem of recognizing important properties of logical calculi and find complexity bounds for some decidable properties. For a given logical system L, a property P of logical calculi is called decidable over L if there is an algorithm which for any finite set Ax of new axiom schemes decides whether the calculus L + Ax has the property P or not. In [11] the complexity of tabularity, pre-tabularity, and interpolation problems over the intuitionistic logic Int and over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Iterative and fixed point common belief.Aviad Heifetz - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1):61-79.
    We define infinitary extensions to classical epistemic logic systems, and add also a common belief modality, axiomatized in a finitary, fixed-point manner. In the infinitary K system, common belief turns to be provably equivalent to the conjunction of all the finite levels of mutual belief. In contrast, in the infinitary monotonic system, common belief implies every transfinite level of mutual belief but is never implied by it. We conclude that the fixed-point notion of common belief is more powerful than the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the decision problem for two-variable first-order logic.Erich Grädel, Phokion G. Kolaitis & Moshe Y. Vardi - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):53-69.
    We identify the computational complexity of the satisfiability problem for FO 2 , the fragment of first-order logic consisting of all relational first-order sentences with at most two distinct variables. Although this fragment was shown to be decidable a long time ago, the computational complexity of its decision problem has not been pinpointed so far. In 1975 Mortimer proved that FO 2 has the finite-model property, which means that if an FO 2 -sentence is satisfiable, then it has a finite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • On modal logics characterized by models with relative accessibility relations: Part II.Stéphane Demri & Dov Gabbay - 2000 - Studia Logica 66 (3):349-384.
    This work is divided in two papers (Part I and Part II). In Part I, we introduced the class of Rare-logics for which the set of terms indexing the modal operators are hierarchized in two levels: the set of Boolean terms and the set of terms built upon the set of Boolean terms. By investigating different algebraic properties satisfied by the models of the Rare-logics, reductions for decidability were established by faithfully translating the Rare-logics into more standard modal logics (some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Every finitely reducible logic has the finite model property with respect to the class of ♦-formulae.Stéphane Demri & Ewa Orłowska - 1999 - Studia Logica 62 (2):177 - 200.
    In this paper a unified framework for dealing with a broad family of propositional multimodal logics is developed. The key tools for presentation of the logics are the notions of closure relation operation and monotonous relation operation. The two classes of logics: FiRe-logics (finitely reducible logics) and LaFiRe-logics (FiRe-logics with local agreement of accessibility relations) are introduced within the proposed framework. Further classes of logics can be handled indirectly by means of suitable translations. It is shown that the logics from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A logic with relative knowledge operators.Stéphane Demri - 1999 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 8 (2):167-185.
    We study a knowledge logic that assumes that to each set of agents, an indiscernibility relation is associated and the agents decide the membership of objects or states up to this indiscernibility relation. Its language contains a family of relative knowledge operators. We prove the decidability of the satisfiability problem, we show its EXPTIME-completeness and as a side-effect, we define a complete Hilbert-style axiomatization.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An overview of tableau algorithms for description logics.Franz Baader & Ulrike Sattler - 2001 - Studia Logica 69 (1):5-40.
    Description logics are a family of knowledge representation formalisms that are descended from semantic networks and frames via the system Kl-one. During the last decade, it has been shown that the important reasoning problems (like subsumption and satisfiability) in a great variety of description logics can be decided using tableau-like algorithms. This is not very surprising since description logics have turned out to be closely related to propositional modal logics and logics of programs (such as propositional dynamic logic), for which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Synchronic information, knowledge and common knowledge in extensive games.Giacomo Bonanno - 1999 - Research in Economics 53 (1):77-99.
    Restricting attention to the class of extensive games defined by von Neumann and Morgenstern with the added assumption of perfect recall, we specify the information of each player at each node of the game-tree in a way which is coherent with the original information structure of the extensive form. We show that this approach provides a framework for a formal and rigorous treatment of questions of knowledge and common knowledge at every node of the tree. We construct a particular information (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Logics and collaboration.Liz Sonenberg - 2023 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 31 (6):1024-1046.
    Since the early days of artificial intelligence (AI), many logics have been explored as tools for knowledge representation and reasoning. In the spirit of the Crossley Festscrift and recognizing John Crossley’s diverse interests and his legacy in both mathematical logic and computer science, I discuss examples from my own research that sit in the overlap of logic and AI, with a focus on supporting human–AI interactions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Super-Strict Implications.Guido Gherardi & Eugenio Orlandelli - 2021 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 50 (1):1-34.
    This paper introduces the logics of super-strict implications, where a super-strict implication is a strengthening of C.I. Lewis' strict implication that avoids not only the paradoxes of material implication but also those of strict implication. The semantics of super-strict implications is obtained by strengthening the (normal) relational semantics for strict implication. We consider all logics of super-strict implications that are based on relational frames for modal logics in the modal cube. it is shown that all logics of super-strict implications are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A logic for reasoning about counterfactual emotions.Emiliano Lorini & François Schwarzentruber - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence 175 (3-4):814-847.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reaching agreements through argumentation: a logical model and implementation.Sarit Kraus, Katia Sycara & Amir Evenchik - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 104 (1-2):1-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Hidden protocols: Modifying our expectations in an evolving world.Hans van Ditmarsch, Sujata Ghosh, Rineke Verbrugge & Yanjing Wang - 2014 - Artificial Intelligence 208 (1):18--40.
    When agents know a protocol, this leads them to have expectations about future observations. Agents can update their knowledge by matching their actual observations with the expected ones. They eliminate states where they do not match. In this paper, we study how agents perceive protocols that are not commonly known, and propose a semantics-driven logical framework to reason about knowledge in such scenarios. In particular, we introduce the notion of epistemic expectation models and a propositional dynamic logic-style epistemic logic for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Exploring the tractability border in epistemic tasks.Cédric Dégremont, Lena Kurzen & Jakub Szymanik - 2014 - Synthese 191 (3):371-408.
    We analyse the computational complexity of comparing informational structures. Intuitively, we study the complexity of deciding queries such as the following: Is Alice’s epistemic information strictly coarser than Bob’s? Do Alice and Bob have the same knowledge about each other’s knowledge? Is it possible to manipulate Alice in a way that she will have the same beliefs as Bob? The results show that these problems lie on both sides of the border between tractability (P) and intractability (NP-hard). In particular, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Tableau-based decision procedure for the multiagent epistemic logic with all coalitional operators for common and distributed knowledge.M. Ajspur, V. Goranko & D. Shkatov - 2013 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 21 (3):407-437.
    We develop a conceptually clear, intuitive, and feasible decision procedure for testing satisfiability in the full multi\-agent epistemic logic \CMAELCD\ with operators for common and distributed knowledge for all coalitions of agents mentioned in the language. To that end, we introduce Hintikka structures for \CMAELCD\ and prove that satisfiability in such structures is equivalent to satisfiability in standard models. Using that result, we design an incremental tableau-building procedure that eventually constructs a satisfying Hintikka structure for every satisfiable input set of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Formalizing Concurrent Common Knowledge as Product of Modal Logics.Vania Costa & Mario Benevides - 2005 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 13 (6):665-684.
    This work introduces a two-dimensional modal logic to represent agents' Concurrent Common Knowledge in distributed systems. Unlike Common Knowledge, Concurrent Common Knowledge is a kind of agreement reachable in asynchronous environments. The formalization of such type of knowledge is based on a model for asynchronous systems and on the definition of Concurrent Knowledge introduced before in paper [5]. As a proper semantics, we review our concept of closed sub-product of modal logics which is based on the product of modal logics. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical omniscience as infeasibility.Sergei Artemov & Roman Kuznets - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (1):6-25.
    Logical theories for representing knowledge are often plagued by the so-called Logical Omniscience Problem. The problem stems from the clash between the desire to model rational agents, which should be capable of simple logical inferences, and the fact that any logical inference, however complex, almost inevitably consists of inference steps that are simple enough. This contradiction points to the fruitlessness of trying to solve the Logical Omniscience Problem qualitatively if the rationality of agents is to be maintained. We provide a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Positive provability logic for uniform reflection principles.Lev Beklemishev - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (1):82-105.
    We deal with the fragment of modal logic consisting of implications of formulas built up from the variables and the constant ‘true’ by conjunction and diamonds only. The weaker language allows one to interpret the diamonds as the uniform reflection schemata in arithmetic, possibly of unrestricted logical complexity. We formulate an arithmetically complete calculus with modalities labeled by natural numbers and ω, where ω corresponds to the full uniform reflection schema, whereas n<ω corresponds to its restriction to arithmetical Πn+1-formulas. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Zero-one laws for modal logic.Joseph Y. Halpern & Bruce Kapron - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (2-3):157-193.
    We show that a 0–1 law holds for propositional modal logic, both for structure validity and frame validity. In the case of structure validity, the result follows easily from the well-known 0–1 law for first-order logic. However, our proof gives considerably more information. It leads to an elegant axiomatization for almost-sure structure validity and to sharper complexity bounds. Since frame validity can be reduced to a Π11 formula, the 0–1 law for frame validity helps delineate when 0–1 laws exist for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Doxastic Conditions for Backward Induction.Thorsten Clausing - 2003 - Theory and Decision 54 (4):315-336.
    The problem of finding sufficient doxastic conditions for backward induction in games of perfect information is analyzed in a syntactic framework with subjunctive conditionals. This allows to describe the structure of the game by a logical formula and consequently to treat beliefs about this structure in the same way as beliefs about rationality. A backward induction and a non-Nash equilibrium result based on higher level belief in rationality and the structure of the game are derived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Terminating tableau systems for hybrid logic with difference and converse.Mark Kaminski & Gert Smolka - 2009 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18 (4):437-464.
    This paper contributes to the principled construction of tableau-based decision procedures for hybrid logic with global, difference, and converse modalities. We also consider reflexive and transitive relations. For converse-free formulas we present a terminating control that does not rely on the usual chain-based blocking scheme. Our tableau systems are based on a new model existence theorem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intransitivity and vagueness.Joseph Y. Halpern - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (4):530-547.
    There are many examples in the literature that suggest that indistinguishability is intransitive, despite the fact that the indistinguishability relation is typically taken to be an equivalence relation (and thus transitive). It is shown that if the uncertainty perception and the question of when an agent reports that two things are indistinguishable are both carefully modeled, the problems disappear, and indistinguishability can indeed be taken to be an equivalence relation. Moreover, this model also suggests a logic of vagueness that seems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Majority merging by adaptive counting.Giuseppe Primiero & Joke Meheus - 2008 - Synthese 165 (2):203 - 223.
    The present paper introduces a belief merging procedure by majority using the standard format of Adaptive Logics. The core structure of the logic ADM c (Adaptive Doxastic Merging by Counting) consists in the formulation of the conflicts arising from the belief bases of the agents involved in the procedure. A strategy is then defined both semantically and proof-theoretically which selects the consistent contents answering to a majority principle. The results obtained are proven to be equivalent to a standard majority operator (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A sound and complete tableau calculus for reasoning about only knowing and knowing at most.Riccardo Rosati - 2001 - Studia Logica 69 (1):171-191.
    We define a tableau calculus for the logic of only knowing and knowing at most ON, which is an extension of Levesque's logic of only knowing O. The method is based on the possible-world semantics of the logic ON, and can be considered as an extension of known tableau calculi for modal logic K45. From the technical viewpoint, the main features of such an extension are the explicit representation of "unreachable" worlds in the tableau, and an additional branch closure condition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Common knowledge logic and game logic.Mamoru Kaneko - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):685-700.
    We show the faithful embedding of common knowledge logic CKL into game logic GL, that is, CKL is embedded into GL and GL is a conservative extension of the fragment obtained by this embedding. Then many results in GL are available in CKL, and vice versa. For example, an epistemic consideration of Nash equilibrium for a game with pure strategies in GL is carried over to CKL. Another important application is to obtain a Gentzen-style sequent calculus formulation of CKL and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rethinking epistemic logic with belief bases.Emiliano Lorini - 2020 - Artificial Intelligence 282 (C):103233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • -Connections of abstract description systems.Oliver Kutz, Carsten Lutz, Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2004 - Artificial Intelligence 156 (1):1-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Limited reasoning in first-order knowledge bases with full introspection.Gerhard Lakemeyer - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 84 (1-2):209-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Integration of weighted knowledge bases.Jinxin Lin - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 83 (2):363-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Doxastic logic: a new approach.Daniel Rönnedal - 2018 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 28 (4):313-347.
    In this paper, I develop a new set of doxastic logical systems and I show how they can be used to solve several well-known problems in doxastic logic, for example the so-called problem of logical omniscience. According to this puzzle, the notions of knowledge and belief that are used in ordinary epistemic and doxastic symbolic systems are too idealised. Hence, those systems cannot be used to model ordinary human or human-like agents' beliefs. At best, they can describe idealised individuals. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conditional beliefs: From neighbourhood semantics to sequent calculus.Marianna Girlando, Sara Negri, Nicola Olivetti & Vincent Risch - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):736-779.
    The logic of Conditional Beliefs has been introduced by Board, Baltag, and Smets to reason about knowledge and revisable beliefs in a multi-agent setting. In this article both the semantics and the proof theory for this logic are studied. First, a natural semantics forCDLis defined in terms of neighbourhood models, a multi-agent generalisation of Lewis’ spheres models, and it is shown that the axiomatization ofCDLis sound and complete with respect to this semantics. Second, it is shown that the neighbourhood semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Definability in the class of all -frames – computability and complexity.D. T. Georgiev - 2017 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 27 (1-2):1-26.
    In the basic modal language and in the basic modal language with the added universal modality, first-order definability of all formulas over the class of all frames is shown. Also, it is shown that the problems of modal definability of first-order sentences over the class of all frames in the languages and are both PSPACE-complete.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamics of lying.Hans van Ditmarsch - 2014 - Synthese 191 (5):1-33.
    We propose a dynamic logic of lying, wherein a ‘lie that $\varphi $ ’ (where $\varphi $ is a formula in the logic) is an action in the sense of dynamic modal logic, that is interpreted as a state transformer relative to the formula $\varphi $ . The states that are being transformed are pointed Kripke models encoding the uncertainty of agents about their beliefs. Lies can be about factual propositions but also about modal formulas, such as the beliefs of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Asynchronous knowledge with hidden actions in the situation calculus.Ryan F. Kelly & Adrian R. Pearce - 2015 - Artificial Intelligence 221 (C):1-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Possible world semantics and autoepistemic reasoning.Liwu Li - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 71 (2):281-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Naming and identity in epistemic logic part II: a first-order logic for naming.Adam J. Grove - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 74 (2):311-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A semantics for reasoning consistently in the presence of inconsistency.Jinxin Lin - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 86 (1):75-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Dynamics of Epistemic Attitudes in Resource-Bounded Agents.Philippe Balbiani, David Fernández-Duque & Emiliano Lorini - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (3):457-488.
    The paper presents a new logic for reasoning about the formation of beliefs through perception or through inference in non-omniscient resource-bounded agents. The logic distinguishes the concept of explicit belief from the concept of background knowledge. This distinction is reflected in its formal semantics and axiomatics: we use a non-standard semantics putting together a neighborhood semantics for explicit beliefs and relational semantics for background knowledge, and we have specific axioms in the logic highlighting the relationship between the two concepts. Mental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Interplays of knowledge and non-contingency.Alexandre Costa-Leite - 2016 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 25 (4):521-534.
    This paper combines a non-contingency logic with an epistemic logic by means of fusions and products of modal systems. Some consequences of these interplays are pointed out.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hybrid Logics: Characterization, Interpolation and Complexity.Carlos Areces, Patrick Blackburn & Maarten Marx - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):977-1010.
    Hybrid languages are expansions of propositional modal languages which can refer to worlds. The use of strong hybrid languages dates back to at least [Pri67], but recent work has focussed on a more constrained system called $\mathscr{H}$. We show in detail that $\mathscr{H}$ is modally natural. We begin by studying its expressivity, and provide model theoretic characterizations and a syntactic characterization. The key result to emerge is that $\mathscr{H}$ corresponds to the fragment of first-order logic which is invariant for generated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Infinitary S5‐Epistemic Logic.Aviad Heifetz - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (3):333-342.
    It is known that a theory in S5‐epistemic logic with several agents may have numerous models. This is because each such model specifies also what an agent knows about infinite intersections of events, while the expressive power of the logic is limited to finite conjunctions of formulas. We show that this asymmetry between syntax and semantics persists also when infinite conjunctions (up to some given cardinality) are permitted in the language. We develop a strengthened S5‐axiomatic system for such infinitary logics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Public announcement logic with distributed knowledge: expressivity, completeness and complexity.Yì N. Wáng & Thomas Ågotnes - 2013 - Synthese 190 (S1).
    While dynamic epistemic logics with common knowledge have been extensively studied, dynamic epistemic logics with distributed knowledge have so far received far less attention. In this paper we study extensions of public announcement logic ( $\mathcal{PAL }$ ) with distributed knowledge, in particular their expressivity, axiomatisations and complexity. $\mathcal{PAL }$ extended only with distributed knowledge is not more expressive than standard epistemic logic with distributed knowledge. Our focus is therefore on $\mathcal{PACD }$ , the result of adding both common and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A completeness proof for a logic with an alternative necessity operator.Stéphane Demri - 1997 - Studia Logica 58 (1):99-112.
    We show the completeness of a Hilbert-style system LK defined by M. Valiev involving the knowledge operator K dedicated to the reasoning with incomplete information. The completeness proof uses a variant of Makinson's canonical model construction. Furthermore we prove that the theoremhood problem for LK is co-NP-complete, using techniques similar to those used to prove that the satisfiability problem for propositional S5 is NP-complete.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A note on the complexity of S4.2.Aggeliki Chalki, Costas D. Koutras & Yorgos Zikos - 2021 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 31 (2):108-129.
    S4.2 is the modal logic of directed partial pre-orders and/or the modal logic of reflexive and transitive relational frames with a final cluster. It holds a distinguished position in philosophical...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation