Switch to: References

Citations of:

Set Theory

Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):876-877 (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Pointwise definable models of set theory.Joel David Hamkins, David Linetsky & Jonas Reitz - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):139-156.
    A pointwise definable model is one in which every object is \loos definable without parameters. In a model of set theory, this property strengthens $V=\HOD$, but is not first-order expressible. Nevertheless, if \ZFC\ is consistent, then there are continuum many pointwise definable models of \ZFC. If there is a transitive model of \ZFC, then there are continuum many pointwise definable transitive models of \ZFC. What is more, every countable model of \ZFC\ has a class forcing extension that is pointwise definable. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Generalizations of the Kunen inconsistency.Joel David Hamkins, Greg Kirmayer & Norman Lewis Perlmutter - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1872-1890.
    We present several generalizations of the well-known Kunen inconsistency that there is no nontrivial elementary embedding from the set-theoretic universe V to itself. For example, there is no elementary embedding from the universe V to a set-forcing extension V[G], or conversely from V[G] to V, or more generally from one set-forcing ground model of the universe to another, or between any two models that are eventually stationary correct, or from V to HOD, or conversely from HOD to V, or indeed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Relations between some cardinals in the absence of the axiom of choice.Lorenz Halbeisen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):237-261.
    If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable, In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On Shattering, Splitting and Reaping Partitions.Lorenz Halbeisen - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (1):123-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Determinacy in third order arithmetic.Sherwood Hachtman - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (11):2008-2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The monadic theory of ω2.Yuri Gurevich, Menachem Magidor & Saharon Shelah - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):387-398.
    Assume ZFC + "There is a weakly compact cardinal" is consistent. Then: (i) For every $S \subseteq \omega, \mathrm{ZFC} +$ "S and the monadic theory of ω 2 are recursive each in the other" is consistent; and (ii) ZFC + "The full second-order theory of ω 2 is interpretable in the monadic theory of ω 2 " is consistent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem for infinitary theories which have the unsuperstability property.Rami Grossberg - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):231-242.
    We present a downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem which transfers downward formulas from L ∞,ω to L κ +, ω . The simplest instance is: Theorem 1. Let $\lambda > \kappa$ be infinite cardinals, and let L be a similarity type of cardinality κ at most. For every L-structure M of cardinality λ and every $X \subseteq M$ there exists a model $N \prec M$ containing the set X of power |X| · κ such that for every pair of finite sequences a, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A basis theorem for perfect sets.Marcia J. Groszek & Theodore A. Slaman - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):204-209.
    We show that if there is a nonconstructible real, then every perfect set has a nonconstructible element, answering a question of K. Prikry. This is a specific instance of a more general theorem giving a sufficient condition on a pair $M\subset N$ of models of set theory implying that every perfect set in N has an element in N which is not in M.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Flat sets.Arthur D. Grainger - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):1012-1021.
    Let X be a set, and let $\hat{X} = \bigcup^\infty_{n = 0} X_n$ be the superstructure of X, where X 0 = X and X n + 1 = X n ∪ P(X n ) (P(X) is the power set of X) for n ∈ ω. The set X is called a flat set if and only if $X \neq \varnothing.\varnothing \not\in X.x \cap \hat X = \varnothing$ for each x ∈ X, and $x \cap \hat{y} = \varnothing$ for x.y (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rank-initial embeddings of non-standard models of set theory.Paul Kindvall Gorbow - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (5-6):517-563.
    A theoretical development is carried to establish fundamental results about rank-initial embeddings and automorphisms of countable non-standard models of set theory, with a keen eye for their sets of fixed points. These results are then combined into a “geometric technique” used to prove several results about countable non-standard models of set theory. In particular, back-and-forth constructions are carried out to establish various generalizations and refinements of Friedman’s theorem on the existence of rank-initial embeddings between countable non-standard models of the fragment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The entire NS ideal on pγ μ can be precipitous.Noa Goldring - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (4):1161 - 1172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two weak consequences of 0#. [REVIEW]M. Gitik, M. Magidor & H. Woodin - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (3):597 - 603.
    It is proven that the following statement: "there exists a club $C \subseteq \kappa$ such that every α ∈ C is an inaccessible cardinal in L and, for every δ a limit point of C, C ∩ δ is almost contained in every club of δ of L" is equiconsistent with a weakly compact cardinal if κ = ℵ 1 , and with a weakly compact cardinal of order 1 if κ = ℵ 2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonsplitting subset of κ.Moti Gitik - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):881-894.
    Assuming the existence of a supercompact cardinal, we construct a model of ZFC + ). Answering a question of Uri Abraham [A], [A-S], we prove that adding a real to the world always makes P ℵ 1 - V stationary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Ramsey-like cardinals.Victoria Gitman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):519 - 540.
    One of the numerous characterizations of a Ramsey cardinal κ involves the existence of certain types of elementary embeddings for transitive sets of size κ satisfying a large fragment of ZFC. We introduce new large cardinal axioms generalizing the Ramsey elementary embeddings characterization and show that they form a natural hierarchy between weakly compact cardinals and measurable cardinals. These new axioms serve to further our knowledge about the elementary embedding properties of smaller large cardinals, in particular those still consistent with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Foundations of nominal techniques: logic and semantics of variables in abstract syntax.Murdoch J. Gabbay - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):161-229.
    We are used to the idea that computers operate on numbers, yet another kind of data is equally important: the syntax of formal languages, with variables, binding, and alpha-equivalence. The original application of nominal techniques, and the one with greatest prominence in this paper, is to reasoning on formal syntax with variables and binding. Variables can be modelled in many ways: for instance as numbers (since we usually take countably many of them); as links (since they may `point' to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Fusion and large cardinal preservation.Sy-David Friedman, Radek Honzik & Lyubomyr Zdomskyy - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (12):1247-1273.
    In this paper we introduce some fusion properties of forcing notions which guarantee that an iteration with supports of size ⩽κ not only does not collapse κ+ but also preserves the strength of κ. This provides a general theory covering the known cases of tree iterations which preserve large cardinals [3], Friedman and Halilović [5], Friedman and Honzik [6], Friedman and Magidor [8], Friedman and Zdomskyy [10], Honzik [12]).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The consistency of the axiom of universality for the ordering of cardinalities.Marco Forti & Furio Honsell - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):502-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparison of the axioms of local and global universality.Marco Forti & Furio Honsell - 1984 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 30 (13‐16):193-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 0♯ and some forcing principles.Matthew Foreman, Menachem Magidor & Saharon Shelah - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (1):39 - 46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ordinals and graph decompositions.Stephen Flood - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (4):824-839.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locally finite ω‐languages and effective analytic sets have the same topological complexity.Olivier Finkel - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (4-5):303-318.
    Local sentences and the formal languages they define were introduced by Ressayre in. We prove that locally finite ω‐languages and effective analytic sets have the same topological complexity: the Borel and Wadge hierarchies of the class of locally finite ω‐languages are equal to the Borel and Wadge hierarchies of the class of effective analytic sets. In particular, for each non‐null recursive ordinal there exist some ‐complete and some ‐complete locally finite ω‐languages, and the supremum of the set of Borel ranks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A hierarchy of tree-automatic structures.Olivier Finkel & Stevo Todorčević - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):350-368.
    We consider ω n -automatic structures which are relational structures whose domain and relations are accepted by automata reading ordinal words of length ω n for some integer n ≥ 1. We show that all these structures are ω-tree-automatic structures presentable by Muller or Rabin tree automata. We prove that the isomorphism relation for ω 2 -automatic (resp. ω n -automatic for n > 2) boolean algebras (respectively, partial orders, rings, commutative rings, non commutative rings, non commutative groups) is not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rado's conjecture and presaturation of the nonstationary ideal on ω1.Qi Feng - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1):38-44.
    We prove that Rado's Conjecture implies that the nonstationary ideal on ω 1 is presaturated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the Rowbottom m-ultrafilters.Qi Feng - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):990-993.
    We show that $M \models \kappa$ is a completely Ramsey cardinal iff there is a Rowbottom M-ultrafilter on κ.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An ideal characterization of mahlo cardinals.Qi Feng - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):467-473.
    We show that a cardinal κ is a (strongly) Mahlo cardinal if and only if there exists a nontrivial κ-complete κ-normal ideal on κ. Also we show that if κ is Mahlo and λ ≥ κ and $\lambda^{ then there is a nontrivial κ-complete κ-normal fine ideal on P κ (λ). If κ is the successor of a cardinal, we consider weak κ-normality and prove that if κ = μ + and μ is a regular cardinal then (1) $\mu^{ if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Models of weak theories of truth.Mateusz Łełyk & Bartosz Wcisło - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (5-6):453-474.
    In the following paper we propose a model-theoretical way of comparing the “strength” of various truth theories which are conservative over PA\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$ PA $$\end{document}. Let Th\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathfrak {Th}}$$\end{document} denote the class of models of PA\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$ PA $$\end{document} which admit an expansion to a model of theory Th\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • PCF structures of height less than ω 3.Karim Er-Rhaimini & Boban Veličković - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (4):1231-1248.
    We show that it is relatively consistent with ZFC to have PCF structures of heightδ, for all ordinalsδ<ω3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The equivalence of determinacy and iterated sharps.Derrick Albert Dubose - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):502-525.
    We characterize, in terms of determinacy, the existence of 0 ♯♯ as well as the existence of each of the following: 0 ♯♯♯ , 0 ♯♯♯♯ ,0 ♯♯♯♯♯ , .... For k ∈ ω, we define two classes of sets, (k * Σ 0 1 ) * and (k * Σ 0 1 ) * + , which lie strictly between $\bigcup_{\beta and Δ(ω 2 -Π 1 1 ). We also define 0 1♯ as 0 ♯ and in general, 0 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Sequential discreteness and clopen-I-Boolean classes.Randall Dougherty - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):232-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A model in which the base-matrix tree cannot have cofinal branches.Peter Lars Dordal - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):651-664.
    A model of ZFC is constructed in which the distributivity cardinal h is 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 2 , and in which there are no ω 2 -towers in [ω] ω . As an immediate corollary, it follows that any base-matrix tree in this model has no cofinal branches. The model is constructed via a form of iterated Mathias forcing, in which a mixture of finite and countable supports is used.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Core models.A. J. Dodd - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):78-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Woodin for strong compactness cardinals.Stamatis Dimopoulos - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):301-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some results on higher suslin trees.R. David - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):526-536.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Axiom of Infinity and Transformations j: V → V.Paul Corazza - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (1):37-84.
    We suggest a new approach for addressing the problem of establishing an axiomatic foundation for large cardinals. An axiom asserting the existence of a large cardinal can naturally be viewed as a strong Axiom of Infinity. However, it has not been clear on the basis of our knowledge of ω itself, or of generally agreed upon intuitions about the true nature of the mathematical universe, what the right strengthening of the Axiom of Infinity is—which large cardinals ought to be derivable? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ramsey sets, the Ramsey ideal, and other classes over R.Paul Corazza - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (4):1441 - 1468.
    We improve results of Marczewski, Frankiewicz, Brown, and others comparing the σ-ideals of measure zero, meager, Marczewski measure zero, and completely Ramsey null sets; in particular, we remove CH from the hypothesis of many of Brown's constructions of sets lying in some of these ideals but not in others. We improve upon work of Marczewski by constructing, without CH, a nonmeasurable Marczewski measure zero set lacking the property of Baire. We extend our analysis of σ-ideals to include the completely Ramsey (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Woodin's axiom , bounded forcing axioms, and precipitous ideals on ω 1.Benjamin Claverie & Ralf Schindler - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):475-498.
    If the Bounded Proper Forcing Axiom BPFA holds, then Mouse Reflection holds at N₂ with respect to all mouse operators up to the level of Woodin cardinals in the next ZFC-model. This yields that if Woodin's ℙ max axiom (*) holds, then BPFA implies that V is closed under the "Woodin-in-the-next-ZFC-model" operator. We also discuss stronger Mouse Reflection principles which we show to follow from strengthenings of BPFA, and we discuss the theory BPFA plus "NS ω1 is precipitous" and strengthenings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Basis theorems for -sets.Chi Tat Chong, Liuzhen Wu & Liang Yu - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):376-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recognizable sets and Woodin cardinals: computation beyond the constructible universe.Merlin Carl, Philipp Schlicht & Philip Welch - 2018 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 169 (4):312-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Small Filter forcing.R. Michael Canjar - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):526-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complete Boolean ultraproducts.R. Michael Canjar - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (2):530-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A microscopic approach to Souslin-tree constructions, Part I.Ari Meir Brodsky & Assaf Rinot - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (11):1949-2007.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Infinitary combinatorics and modal logic.Andreas Blass - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):761-778.
    We show that the modal propositional logic G, originally introduced to describe the modality "it is provable that", is also sound for various interpretations using filters on ordinal numbers, for example the end-segment filters, the club filters, or the ineffable filters. We also prove that G is complete for the interpretation using end-segment filters. In the case of club filters, we show that G is complete if Jensen's principle □ κ holds for all $\kappa ; on the other hand, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (Probably) Not companions in guilt.Sharon Berry - 2018 - Philosophical Studies 175 (9):2285-2308.
    In this paper, I will attempt to develop and defend a common form of intuitive resistance to the companions in guilt argument. I will argue that one can reasonably believe there are promising solutions to the access problem for mathematical realism that don’t translate to moral realism. In particular, I will suggest that the structuralist project of accounting for mathematical knowledge in terms of some form of logical knowledge offers significant hope of success while no analogous approach offers such hope (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The topological Vaught's conjecture and minimal counterexamples.Howard Becker - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):757-784.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Determinacy of Banach games.Howard Becker - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):110-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A characterization of jump operators.Howard Becker - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):708-728.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Adjoining dominating functions.James E. Baumgartner & Peter Dordal - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):94-101.
    If dominating functions in ω ω are adjoined repeatedly over a model of GCH via a finite-support c.c.c. iteration, then in the resulting generic extension there are no long towers, every well-ordered unbounded family of increasing functions is a scale, and the splitting number s (and hence the distributivity number h) remains at ω 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Richness and Reflection.Neil Barton - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (3):330-359.
    A pervasive thought in contemporary philosophy of mathematics is that in order to justify reflection principles, one must hold universism: the view that there is a single universe of pure sets. I challenge this kind of reasoning by contrasting universism with a Zermelian form of multiversism. I argue that if extant justifications of reflection principles using notions of richness are acceptable for the universist, then the Zermelian can use similar justifications. However, I note that for some forms of richness argument, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Standard foundations for nonstandard analysis.David Ballard & Karel Hrbacek - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):741-748.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Ideals without CCC.Marek Balcerzak, Andrzej RosŁanowski & Saharon Shelah - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (1):128-148.
    Let I be an ideal of subsets of a Polish space X, containing all singletons and possessing a Borel basis. Assuming that I does not satisfy ccc, we consider the following conditions (B), (M) and (D). Condition (B) states that there is a disjoint family F $\subseteq$ P(X) of size c, consisting of Borel sets which are not in I. Condition (M) states that there is a Borel function f: X → X with $f^{-1}[\{x\}] \not\in$ I for each x ∈ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations