Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The essential opacity of modular systems: Why even connectionism cannot give complete formal accounts of cognition.Marten J. den Uyl - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):56-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The psychological appeal of connectionism.Denise Dellarosa - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):28-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Conflict adaptation is predicted by the cognitive, but not the affective alexithymia dimension.Michiel de Galan, Roberta Sellaro, Lorenza S. Colzato & Bernhard Hommel - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On individual risk.Philip Dawid - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3445-3474.
    We survey a variety of possible explications of the term “Individual Risk.” These in turn are based on a variety of interpretations of “Probability,” including classical, enumerative, frequency, formal, metaphysical, personal, propensity, chance and logical conceptions of probability, which we review and compare. We distinguish between “groupist” and “individualist” understandings of probability, and explore both “group to individual” and “individual to group” approaches to characterising individual risk. Although in the end that concept remains subtle and elusive, some pragmatic suggestions for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Jeffreys–Lindley paradox and discovery criteria in high energy physics.Robert D. Cousins - 2017 - Synthese 194 (2):395-432.
    The Jeffreys–Lindley paradox displays how the use of a \ value ) in a frequentist hypothesis test can lead to an inference that is radically different from that of a Bayesian hypothesis test in the form advocated by Harold Jeffreys in the 1930s and common today. The setting is the test of a well-specified null hypothesis versus a composite alternative. The \ value, as well as the ratio of the likelihood under the null hypothesis to the maximized likelihood under the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is Smolensky's treatment of connectionism on the level?Carol E. Cleland - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information processing abstractions: The message still counts more than the medium.B. Chandrasekaran, Ashok Goel & Dean Allemang - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Functional Dissociation of Latency-Variable, Stimulus- and Response-Locked Target P3 Sub-components in Task-Switching.Christopher R. Brydges & Francisco Barceló - 2018 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Neyman-Pearson theory as decision theory, and as inference theory; with a criticism of the Lindley-Savage argument for bayesian theory.Allan Birnbaum - 1977 - Synthese 36 (1):19 - 49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On Probabilities in Biology and Physics.Joseph Berkovitz & Philippe Huneman - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (S3):433-456.
    This volume focuses on various questions concerning the interpretation of probability and probabilistic reasoning in biology and physics. It is inspired by the idea that philosophers of biology and philosophers of physics who work on the foundations of their disciplines encounter similar questions and problems concerning the role and application of probability, and that interaction between the two communities will be both interesting and fruitful. In this introduction we present the background to the main questions that the volume focuses on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two constructive themes.Richard K. Belew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):25-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism and interlevel relations.William Bechtel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):24-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Two dogmas of strong objective bayesianism.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay & Gordon Brittan - 2010 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 24 (1):45 – 65.
    We introduce a distinction, unnoticed in the literature, between four varieties of objective Bayesianism. What we call ' strong objective Bayesianism' is characterized by two claims, that all scientific inference is 'logical' and that, given the same background information two agents will ascribe a unique probability to their priors. We think that neither of these claims can be sustained; in this sense, they are 'dogmatic'. The first fails to recognize that some scientific inference, in particular that concerning evidential relations, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of the connection between connectionism and symbolism.Louise Antony & Joseph Levine - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):23-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • We are All Bayesian, Everyone is Not a Bayesian.Mattia Andreoletti & Andrea Oldofredi - 2019 - Topoi 38 (2):477-485.
    Medical research makes intensive use of statistics in order to support its claims. In this paper we make explicit an epistemological tension between the conduct of clinical trials and their interpretation: statistical evidence is sometimes discarded on the basis of an underlined Bayesian reasoning. We suggest that acknowledging the potentiality of Bayesian statistics might contribute to clarify and improve comprehension of medical research. Nevertheless, despite Bayesianism may provide a better account for scientific inference with respect to the standard frequentist approach, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probabilist antirealism.Igor Douven, Leon Horsten & Jan-Willem Romeijn - 2010 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (1):38-63.
    Until now, antirealists have offered sketches of a theory of truth, at best. In this paper, we present a probabilist account of antirealist truth in some formal detail, and we assess its ability to deal with the problems that are standardly taken to beset antirealism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Putting together connectionism – again.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):59-74.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Regular probability comparisons imply the Banach–Tarski Paradox.Alexander R. Pruss - 2014 - Synthese 191 (15):3525-3540.
    Consider the regularity thesis that each possible event has non-zero probability. Hájek challenges this in two ways: there can be nonmeasurable events that have no probability at all and on a large enough sample space, some probabilities will have to be zero. But arguments for the existence of nonmeasurable events depend on the axiom of choice. We shall show that the existence of anything like regular probabilities is by itself enough to imply a weak version of AC sufficient to prove (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Inferring probabilities from symmetries.Michael Strevens - 1998 - Noûs 32 (2):231-246.
    This paper justifies the inference of probabilities from symmetries. I supply some examples of important and correct inferences of this variety. Two explanations of such inferences -- an explanation based on the Principle of Indifference and a proposal due to Poincaré and Reichenbach -- are considered and rejected. I conclude with my own account, in which the inferences in question are shown to be warranted a posteriori, provided that they are based on symmetries in the mechanisms of chance setups.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Ignorance and Indifference.John D. Norton - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (1):45-68.
    The epistemic state of complete ignorance is not a probability distribution. In it, we assign the same, unique, ignorance degree of belief to any contingent outcome and each of its contingent, disjunctive parts. That this is the appropriate way to represent complete ignorance is established by two instruments, each individually strong enough to identify this state. They are the principle of indifference (PI) and the notion that ignorance is invariant under certain redescriptions of the outcome space, here developed into the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • A note on scale invariance.Peter Milne - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1):49-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Some random observations.Edwin T. Jaynes - 1985 - Synthese 63 (1):115 - 138.
    Of course, the rationale of PME is so different from what has been taught in “orthodox” statistics courses for fifty years, that it causes conceptual hangups for many with conventional training. But beginning students have no difficulty with it, for it is just a mathematical model of the natural, common sense way in which anybody does conduct his inferences in problems of everyday life.The difficulties that seem so prominent in the literature today are, therefore, only transient phenomena that will disappear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The reality of the symbolic and subsymbolic systems.Andrew Woodfield & Adam Morton - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):58-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On objectivity and subjectivity in statistical inference: A response to Mayo.Peffrey A. Witmer & Murray K. Clayton - 1986 - Synthese 67 (2):369 - 379.
    In this paper we respond to the article An Objective Theory of Statistical Testing by D. G. Mayo (1983). We argue that the theory of testing developed by Mayo, NPT*, is neither novel nor objective. We also respond to the claims made by Mayo against Bayesian theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decision theory and cognitive choice.John R. Welch - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (2):147-172.
    The focus of this study is cognitive choice: the selection of one cognitive option (a hypothesis, a theory, or an axiom, for instance) rather than another. The study proposes that cognitive choice should be based on the plausibilities of states posited by rival cognitive options and the utilities of these options' information outcomes. The proposal introduces a form of decision theory that is novel because comparative; it permits many choices among cognitive options to be based on merely comparative plausibilities and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Indifference, neutrality and informativeness: generalizing the three prisoners paradox.Sergio Wechsler, L. G. Esteves, A. Simonis & C. Peixoto - 2005 - Synthese 143 (3):255-272.
    . The uniform prior distribution is often seen as a mathematical description of noninformativeness. This paper uses the well-known Three Prisoners Paradox to examine the impossibility of maintaining noninformativeness throughout hierarchization. The Paradox has been solved by Bayesian conditioning over the choice made by the Warder when asked to name a prisoner who will be shot. We generalize the paradox to situations of N prisoners, k executions and m announcements made by the Warder. We then extend the consequences of hierarchically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • No evidence amalgamation without evidence measurement.Veronica J. Vieland & Hasok Chang - 2019 - Synthese 196 (8):3139-3161.
    In this paper we consider the problem of how to measure the strength of statistical evidence from the perspective of evidence amalgamation operations. We begin with a fundamental measurement amalgamation principle : for any measurement, the inputs and outputs of an amalgamation procedure must be on the same scale, and this scale must have a meaningful interpretation vis a vis the object of measurement. Using the p value as a candidate evidence measure, we examine various commonly used approaches to amalgamation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Has the case been made against the ecumenical view of connectionism?Robert Van Gulick - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):57-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Hierarchical Bayesian Modeling Approach to Searching and Stopping in Multi-Attribute Judgment.Don van Ravenzwaaij, Chris P. Moore, Michael D. Lee & Ben R. Newell - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (7):1384-1405.
    In most decision-making situations, there is a plethora of information potentially available to people. Deciding what information to gather and what to ignore is no small feat. How do decision makers determine in what sequence to collect information and when to stop? In two experiments, we administered a version of the German cities task developed by Gigerenzer and Goldstein (1996), in which participants had to decide which of two cities had the larger population. Decision makers were not provided with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the proper treatment of thermostats.David S. Touretzky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):55-56.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decision Theory Without “Independence” or Without “Ordering”.Teddy Seidenfeld - 1988 - Economics and Philosophy 4 (2):267.
    It is a familiar argument that advocates accommodating the so-called paradoxes of decision theory by abandoning the “independence” postulate. After all, if we grant that choice reveals preference, the anomalous choice patterns of the Allais and Ellsberg problems violate postulate P2 of Savage's system. The strategy of making room for new preference patterns by relaxing independence is adopted in each of the following works: Samuelson, Kahneman and Tversky's “Prospect Theory”, Allais and Hagen, Fishburn, Chew and MacCrimmon, McClennen, and in closely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The nature of probability.Patrick Suppes - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (1):89 - 102.
    The thesis of this article is that the nature of probability is centered on its formal properties, not on any of its standard interpretations. Section 2 is a survey of Bayesian applications. Section 3 focuses on two examples from physics that seem as completely objective as other physical concepts. Section 4 compares the conflict between subjective Bayesians and objectivists about probability to the earlier strident conflict in physics about the nature of force. Section 5 outlines a pragmatic approach to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From data to dynamics: The use of multiple levels of analysis.Gregory O. Stone - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):54-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • From connectionism to eliminativism.Stephen P. Stich - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Some aspects of Carnap's theory of inductive inference.Carl-Erik Särndal - 1968 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 19 (3):225-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The objectivity of Subjective Bayesianism.Jan Sprenger - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 8 (3):539-558.
    Subjective Bayesianism is a major school of uncertain reasoning and statistical inference. It is often criticized for a lack of objectivity: it opens the door to the influence of values and biases, evidence judgments can vary substantially between scientists, it is not suited for informing policy decisions. My paper rebuts these concerns by connecting the debates on scientific objectivity and statistical method. First, I show that the above concerns arise equally for standard frequentist inference with null hypothesis significance tests. Second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Simpler without a simplest: Ockham's Razor implies epistemic dilemmas.R. Sorensen - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):260-264.
    William of Ockham wrote, ‘It is futile to do with more things that which can be done with fewer .’ But what if each option uses less than its predecessor but no option uses the least? A scale perfectly balanced between a pair of kilogram weights can be tipped by adding half a kilogram to one side, or a quarter of a kilogram, or an eighth of a kilogram, or … For any choice, there is an option that gets the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Issues and advances in research methods on video games and cognitive abilities.Bart Sobczyk, Paweł Dobrowolski, Maciek Skorko, Jakub Michalak & Aneta Brzezicka - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the proper treatment of connectionism.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):1-23.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • Prior probabilities.John Skilling - 1985 - Synthese 63 (1):1 - 34.
    The theoretical construction and practical use of prior probabilities, in particular for systems having many degrees of freedom, are investigated. It becomes clear that it is operationally unsound to use mutually consistent priors if one wishes to draw sensible conclusions from practical experiments. The prior cannot usefully be identified with a state of knowledge, and indeed it is not so identified in common scientific practice. Rather, it can be identified with the question one asks. Accordingly, priors are free constructions. Their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why explanation and thus coherence cannot be reduced to probability.M. Siebel - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):264-266.
    Some philosophers, most notably Hempel and Salmon, have tried to reduce explanation to probability by proposing analyses of explanation in probabilistic terms. Hempel claims, roughly, that a hypothesis H explains a datum D if and only if the conditional probability P is close to 1. It is well known that such an account fails in cases where H is irrelevant for D. Even though it is highly likely that Tom will not become pregnant, given that he regularly takes his wife’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On Carnap: Reflections of a metaphysical student. [REVIEW]Abner Shimony - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):261 - 274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How fully should connectionism be activated? Two sources of excitation and one of inhibition.Roger N. Shepard - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):52-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Testing adaptive toolbox models: A Bayesian hierarchical approach.Benjamin Scheibehenne, Jörg Rieskamp & Eric-Jan Wagenmakers - 2013 - Psychological Review 120 (1):39-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Structure and controlling subsymbolic processing.Walter Schneider - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):51-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Making the connections.Jay G. Rueckl - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):50-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the automatic link between affect and tendencies to approach and avoid: Chen and Bargh (1999) revisited.Mark Rotteveel, Alexander Gierholz, Gijs Koch, Cherelle van Aalst, Yair Pinto, Dora Matzke, Helen Steingroever, Josine Verhagen, Titia F. Beek, Ravi Selker, Adam Sasiadek & Eric-Jan Wagenmakers - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:57614.
    Within the literature on emotion and behavioral action, studies on approach-avoidance take up a prominent place. Several experimental paradigms feature successful conceptual replications but many original studies have not yet been replicated directly. We present such a direct replication attempt of two seminal experiments originally conducted by Chen and Bargh (1999). In their first experiment, participants affectively evaluated attitude objects by pulling or pushing a lever. Participants who had to pull the lever with positively valenced attitude objects and push the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Inductivism and probabilism.Roger Rosenkrantz - 1971 - Synthese 23 (2-3):167 - 205.
    I I set out my view that all inference is essentially deductive and pinpoint what I take to be the major shortcomings of the induction rule.II The import of data depends on the probability model of the experiment, a dependence ignored by the induction rule. Inductivists admit background knowledge must be taken into account but never spell out how this is to be done. As I see it, that is the problem of induction.III The induction rule, far from providing a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the correct interpretation of p values and the importance of random variables.Guillaume Rochefort-Maranda - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1777-1793.
    The p value is the probability under the null hypothesis of obtaining an experimental result that is at least as extreme as the one that we have actually obtained. That probability plays a crucial role in frequentist statistical inferences. But if we take the word ‘extreme’ to mean ‘improbable’, then we can show that this type of inference can be very problematic. In this paper, I argue that it is a mistake to make such an interpretation. Under minimal assumptions about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information and Inaccuracy.William Roche & Tomoji Shogenji - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (2):577-604.
    This article proposes a new interpretation of mutual information. We examine three extant interpretations of MI by reduction in doubt, by reduction in uncertainty, and by divergence. We argue that the first two are inconsistent with the epistemic value of information assumed in many applications of MI: the greater is the amount of information we acquire, the better is our epistemic position, other things being equal. The third interpretation is consistent with EVI, but it is faced with the problem of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations