Switch to: References

Citations of:

Critique of pure reason

In Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Late modern philosophy: essential readings with commentary. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 449-451 (2007)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The strange belief of Alexis de Tocqueville: Christianity as philosophy.Luk Sanders - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 74 (1):33-53.
    Alexis de Tocqueville is known for his strange liberalism. One of the reasons therefore has to be found in his lesser known strange religious belief. The three main elements that determined his belief were his aristocratic and profoundly religious education, the dramatic loss of his faith after reading eighteenth century French philosophers and his conviction that the stability of the American democracy was mainly due to religious mores. These elements explain why Tocqueville appeared in his publications as an obvious believer, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the transcendental deduction in Kant’s Groundwork III.Marilia Espirito Santo - 2011 - Disputatio 4 (30):1 - 19.
    The purpose of the third section of Kant’s Groundwork is to prove the possibility of the categorical imperative. In the end of the second section, Kant establishes that a proof like this is necessary to show that morality is ‘something’ and ‘not a chimerical idea without any truth’ or a ‘phantom’. Since the categorical imperative was established as a synthetic a priori practical proposition, in order to prove its possibility it is necessary ‘to go beyond cognition of objects to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflective Judgment's Potentials in the Formation of Juridical Nature in Kant.Ali Salmani & Saeed Hajrashidian - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 15 (35):134-158.
    Perhaps one of the most pivotal ideas of Kant which connects all of the periods of his continuous intellectual work is the idea of the nature as the whole. According to Kant the nature as the whole is equivalent to totality and universality. This is the rule of the fundamental idea: the particulars finally must be under the general in order to be explicable. But it is interesting to note that this general rule which remains unchanged in Kant’s three periods (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The acknowledgement of transcendence: Anti-theodicy in Adorno and Levinas.Carl B. Sachs - 2011 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 37 (3):273-294.
    It is generally recognized that Adorno and Levinas should both be read as urging a rethinking of ethics in light of Auschwitz. This demand should be understood in terms of the acknowledgement of transcendence. A phenomenological account of the event of Auschwitz developed by Todes motivates my use of Cavell’s distinction between acknowledgement and knowledge. Both Levinas and Adorno argue that an ethically adequate acknowledgement of transcendence requires that the traditional concept of transcendence as represented in theodicy must be rejected. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Editorial for the Topical Issue “Imagination and Potentiality: The Quest for the Real”.Kristupas Sabolius & Graham Harman - 2020 - Open Philosophy 3 (1):694-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situating representational redescriptionin infants' pragmatic knowledge.Julie C. Rutkowska - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):726-727.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tillich's implicit ontological argument.John M. Russell - 1993 - Sophia 32 (2):1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The analytic/synthetic distinction.Gillian Russell - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (5):712–729.
    Once a standard tool in the epistemologist’s kit, the analytic/synthetic distinction was challenged by Quine and others in the mid-twentieth century and remains controversial today. But although the work of a lot contemporary philosophers touches on this distinction – in the sense that it either has consequences for it, or it assumes results about it – few have really focussed on it recently. This has the consequence that a lot has happened that should affect our view of the analytic/synthetic distinction, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Metaphysical analyticity and the epistemology of logic.Gillian K. Russell - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 171 (1):161-175.
    Recent work on analyticity distinguishes two kinds, metaphysical and epistemic. This paper argues that the distinction allows for a new view in the philosophy of logic according to which the claims of logic are metaphysically analytic and have distinctive modal profiles, even though their epistemology is holist and in many ways rather Quinean. It is argued that such a view combines some of the more attractive aspects of the Carnapian and Quinean approaches to logic, whilst avoiding some famous problems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kantian Self-Conceit and the Two Guises of Authority.Francey Russell - 2020 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (2):268-283.
    There is a debate in the literature as to whether Kantian self-conceit is intrapsychic or interpersonal. I argue that self-conceit is both. I argue that, for Kant, self-conceit is fundamentally an illusion about authority, one’s own and any authority one stands in relation to. Self-conceit refuses to recognize the authority of the law. But the law “shows up” for us in two guises: one’s own reason and other persons. Thus, self-conceit refuses to recognize both guises of the law. Hence self-conceit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Minimalist Approach to the Development of Episodic Memory.James Russell & Robert Hanna - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (1):29-54.
    Episodic memory is usually regarded in a Conceptualist light, in the sense of its being dependent upon the grasp of concepts directly relevant to the act of episodic recollection itself, such as a concept of past times and of the self as an experiencer. Given this view, its development is typically timed as being in the early school-age years. We present a minimalist, Non-Conceptualist approach in opposition to this view, but one that also exists in clear contrast to the kind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • There is more to psychological meaningfulness than computation and representation.Sverker Runeson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):399-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Imaginings, Narratives and Otherness: On the Critical Hermeneutics of Richard Kearney.John Rundell - 2003 - Thesis Eleven 73 (1):97-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Epistemic Import of Affectivity: A Husserlian Account.Jacob Martin Rump - 2017 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41 (1):82-104.
    I argue that, on Husserl's account, affectivity, along with the closely related phenomenon of association, follows a form of sui generis lawfulness belonging to the domain of what Husserl calls motivation, which must be distinguished both (1) from the causal structures through which we understand the body third-personally, as a material thing; and also (2) from the rational or inferential structures at the level of deliberative judgment traditionally understood to be the domain of epistemic import. In effect, in addition to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Making the connections.Jay G. Rueckl - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):50-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rethinking Kant on Individuation.Eric M. Rubenstein - 2001 - Kantian Review 5:73-89.
    In the section of the Critique of Pure Reason entitled The Amphiboly of Concepts of Reflection Kant writes:Suppose that an object is exhibited to us repeatedly but always with the same intrinsic determinations . In that case, if the object counts as object of pure understanding then it is always the same object, and is not many but only one thing . But if the object is appearance, then comparison of concepts does not matter at all; rather, however much everything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mills Can't Think: Leibniz's Approach to the Mind-Body Problem.Marleen Rozemond - 2014 - Res Philosophica 91 (1):1-28.
    In the Monadology Leibniz has us imagine a thinking machine the size of a mill in order to show that matter can’t think. The argument is often thought to rely on the unity of consciousness and the notion of simplicity. Leibniz himself did not see matters this way. For him the argument relies on the view that the qualities of a substance must be intimately connected to its nature by being modifications, limitations of its nature. Leibniz thinks perception is not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • II—Self-Awareness and Korsgaard’s Naturalistic Explanation of the Good.Mark Rowlands - 2018 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 92 (1):133-149.
    This paper explores certain facets of Christine Korsgaard’s paper, ‘Prospects for a Naturalistic Explanation of the Good’. Korsgaard’s account requires that an animal be able to experience ‘herself trying to get or avoid something’. The claim that animals possess such self-awareness is regarded by many as problematic and, if this is correct, it would jeopardize Korsgaard’s account. This paper argues that animals can, in fact, be aware of themselves in the way required by Korsgaard’s account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The choice of logical foundations: Non-classical choices and the ultralogical choice.Richard Routley - 1980 - Studia Logica 39 (1):77 - 98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Articulating the World: Experimental Systems and Conceptual Understanding.Joseph Rouse - 2011 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (3):243 - 254.
    Attention to scientific practice offers a novel response to philosophical queries about how conceptual understanding is empirically accountable. The locus of the issue is thereby shifted, from perceptual experience to experimental and fieldwork interactions. More important, conceptual articulation is shown to be not merely ?spontaneous? and intralinguistic, but instead involves a establishing a systematic domain of experimental operations. The importance of experimental practice for conceptual understanding is especially clearly illustrated by cases in which entire domains of scientific investigation were first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Toward a Noninferentialist, Nonreliabilist Account of Perceptual Justification.Martin Roth - 2019 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 57 (1):80-102.
    While it may be a datum of common sense that perceptual experiences can justify beliefs, there is no clear consensus about how they can do so. According to what I call “inferentialism,” perceptual experiences can justify beliefs because perceptual experiences have propositional contents and thus can serve as reasons for belief. A critical commitment of inferentialism is that justification requires the obtaining of a nonarbitrary or nonaccidental semantic relation between justifier and justified, a requirement that I call semantic appropriateness (SA). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Good Will: Cosmopolitan education as a site for deliberation.Klas Roth - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (3):298-312.
    Why should we deliberate? I discuss a Kantian response to this query and argue that we cannot as rational beings avoid deliberation in principle; and that we have good reasons to consider the value and strength of Kant's philosophical investigations concerning fundamental moral issues and their relevance for the question of why we ought to deliberate. I also argue that deliberation is a wide duty. This means that it has to be set as an end, that it is meritorious, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The transcendent function of the bilateral brain.Virginia Ross - 1986 - Zygon 21 (2):233-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • New Perspectives on the Tractatus.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1966 - Dialogue 4 (4):506-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction to Monique David-Ménard on Kant and madness.Alison Ross - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):77-81.
    : Ross examines the relation between thought and madness within the practical and theoretical wings of Kant's critical philosophy. She argues that the notion of critique is formulated as a guard against the tendency of thought to madness. She locates the significance of David-Ménard's essay on Kant's pre-critical works in the idea that Kant's own tendency to madness functions in these early works as a motivational principle for the mature, critical system.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Following his own path: Li Zehou and contemporary Chinese philosophy.Jana Rošker - 2019 - Albany: SUNY Press.
    In this book, Jana S. Ros̆ker offers the first comprehensive overview and exegesis of the work of Li Zehou, who is one of the most significant and influential Chinese philosophers of our time. Ros̆ker shows us how Li's complex system of thought seeks to revive various Chinese traditions, and at the same time attempts to harmonize or reconcile this cultural heritage with the demands of the dominant economic, political, and axiological structures of our globalized world. Variously characterized as 'neo-traditional,' 'neo-Kantian,' (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thinking as a subversive activity: doing philosophy in the corporate university.Gary Rolfe - 2013 - Nursing Philosophy 14 (1):28-37.
    The academy is in a mess. The cultural theorist Bill Readings claimed that it is in ruins, while the political scientist Michael Oakeshott suggested that it has all but ceased to exist. At the very least, we might argue that the current financial squeeze has distorted the University into a shape that would be all but unrecognizable to Oakeshott and others writing in the 1950s and 1960s. I will begin this paper by tracing the development of the modern Enlightenment University (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hauerwas's "With the Grain of the Universe" and the Barthian Outlook: A Few Observations.Roger Gustavsson - 2007 - Journal of Religious Ethics 35 (1):25 - 86.
    This article has two main divisions, the first consisting in parts 1-3, the second in parts 4-8. The purpose of the first division is to assess Hauerwas's contentions regarding what he takes to be serious debilities in modern theological culture. The objects of Hauerwas's criticism are: (1) natural theology; (2) reason as it is represented in the structure of the modern university and in the "Enlightenment Project"; and (3) liberal Protestantism--the latter particularly as it turns up, by his account, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Allais on Transcendental Idealism.Andrew F. Roche - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (3):351-374.
    Lucy Allais argues that we can better understand Kant's transcendental idealism by taking seriously the analogy of appearances to secondary qualities that Kant offers in theProlegomena. A proper appreciation of this analogy, Allais claims, yields a reading of transcendental idealism according to which all properties that can appear to us in experience are mind-dependent relational properties that inhere in mind-independent objects. In section 1 of my paper, I articulate Allais's position and its benefits, not least of which is its elegant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Faculties, modules, and computers.Daniel N. Robinson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):28-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Postmodern Education and the Concept of Power.Thomas Aastrup Rømer - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (7):755-772.
    This article presents a discussion of how postmodernist, poststructuralist and critical educational thinking relate to different theories of power. I argue that both Critical Theory and some poststructuralist ideas base themselves on a concept of power borrowed from a modernist tradition. I argue as well that we are better off combining a postmodern idea of education with a postmodern idea of power. To this end the concept of power presented by the works of Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe is introduced. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Imagination and Judgment in John Dewey's Philosophy: Intelligent transactions in a democratic context.Thomas Aastrup Rømer - 2012 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 44 (2):133-150.
    In this essay, I attempt to interpret the educational philosophy of John Dewey in a way that accomplishes two goals. The first of these is to avoid any reference to Dewey as a propagator of a particular scientific method or to any of the individualist and cognitivist ideas that is sometimes associated with him. Secondly, I want to overcome the tendency to interpret Dewey as a naturalist by looking at his concept of intelligence. It is argued that ‘intelligent experience’ is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Generation, interiority and the phenomenology of Christianity in Michel Henry.Joseph M. Rivera - 2011 - Continental Philosophy Review 44 (2):205-235.
    In this paper I focus on a central phenomenological concept in Michel Henry’s work that has often been neglected: generation. Generation becomes an especially important conceptual key to understanding not only the relationship between God and human self but also Henry’s adoption of radical interiority and his critical standpoint with respect to much of the phenomenological tradition in which he is working. Thus in pursuing the theme of generation, I shall introduce many phenomenological-theological terms in Henry’s trilogy on Christianity as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Seeing empty space.Louise Richardson - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):227-243.
    Abstract: In this paper I offer an account of a particular variety of perception of absence, namely, visual perception of empty space. In so doing, I aim to make explicit the role that seeing empty space has, implicitly, in Mike Martin's account of the visual field. I suggest we should make sense of the claim that vision has a field—in Martin's sense—in terms of our being aware of its limitations or boundaries. I argue that the limits of the visual field (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Explaining the relationship between art and nature in Schelling's philosophy.Roxana Riahi, Ali Moradkhani & Mohammad Shokri - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 15 (35):97-114.
    To achieve the common origin of "I" and nature, Schelling takes a new approach to the philosophy of nature; demonstrating the falsity of dualism between "I" and nature and showing how nature cannot be reduced to a mechanistic series of causes and effects. By integrating Leibniz's principle of inner purposiveness, Spinoza's monism, and the Kantian concept of teleology, he interprets an organic idea of nature as a totality and founds "I" on the ground of this organic nature. Schelling turns to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sanity surrounded by madness.Georges Rey - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):48-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Quinity, isotropy, and Wagnerian rapture.Georges Rey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Death as the Limit to Life and Thought; A Thanatological Outline.Matthias Remenyi - 2014 - Heythrop Journal 55 (1):94-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Priori Justification in Nietzsche.Justin Remhof - 2021 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 38 (3):261-276.
    This paper argues there are crucial points in Nietzsche’s texts where he offers a priori epistemic justification for views he believes are correct. My reading contrasts with the dominant view that Nietzsche’s philosophical naturalism is incompatible with a priori justification. My aim is to develop Nietzsche’s brand of a priori justification, show that he employs this account of justification in the texts, and suggest how it might be compatible with naturalism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experience, Seemings, and Evidence.Indrek Reiland - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (4):510-534.
    Many people have recently argued that we need to distinguish between experiences and seemings and that this has consequences for views about how perception provides evidence. In this article I spell out my take on these issues by doing three things. First, I distinguish between mere sensations like seeing pitch black all around you and perceptual experiences like seeing a red apple. Both have sensory phenomenology in presenting us with sensory qualities like colors, being analog in Dretske's sense, and being (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Measuring the plausibility of explanatory hypotheses.James A. Reggia - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):486-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Exploding the Limits of Law’: Judgment and Freedom in Arendt and Adorno.Craig Reeves - 2009 - Res Publica 15 (2):137-164.
    In Eichmann in Jerusalem , Hannah Arendt struggled to defend the possibility of judgment against the obvious problems encountered in attempts to offer legally valid and morally meaningful judgments of those who had committed crimes in morally bankrupt communities. Following Norrie, this article argues that Arendt’s conclusions in Eichmann are equivocal and incoherent. Exploring her perspectival theory of judgment, the article suggests that Arendt remains trapped within certain Kantian assumptions in her philosophy of history, and as such sees the question (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Areas of ignorance and confusion in color science.Adam Reeves - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hegel and Peircean abduction.Paul Redding - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):295–313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pragmatism and the unlikely influence of German idealism on the academy in the united states.Todd C. Ream - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (2):150–167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanatory coherence in understanding persons, interactions, and relationships.Stephen J. Read & Lynn C. Miller - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):485-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Judgment as synthesis.Sebastian Rödl - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 17 (3):435-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Second Step of the B‐Deduction.Frederick Rauscher - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 22 (3):396-419.
    This paper offers a new interpretation of Kant's puzzling claim that the B-Deduction in the Critique of Pure Reason should be considered as having two main steps. Previous commentators have tended to agree in general on the first step as arguing for the necessity of the categories for possible experience, but disagree on what the second step is and whether Kant even needs a second step. I argue that the two parts of the B-Deduction correspond to the two aspects of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations