Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Depressive symptoms and use of perspective taking within a communicative context.Elizabeth S. Nilsen & David Duong - 2013 - Cognition and Emotion 27 (2):335-344.
    Our language system is ambiguous in that the same utterance can be interpreted in different ways depending on the intention of the speaker. For example, the phrase, “Nice job!” can be interpreted a...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generation of Referring Expressions: Assessing the Incremental Algorithm.Kees van Deemter, Albert Gatt, Ielka van der Sluis & Richard Power - 2012 - Cognitive Science 36 (5):799-836.
    A substantial amount of recent work in natural language generation has focused on the generation of ‘‘one‐shot’’ referring expressions whose only aim is to identify a target referent. Dale and Reiter's Incremental Algorithm (IA) is often thought to be the best algorithm for maximizing the similarity to referring expressions produced by people. We test this hypothesis by eliciting referring expressions from human subjects and computing the similarity between the expressions elicited and the ones generated by algorithms. It turns out that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • ‘Putting Ourselves in the Other Fellow’ s Shoes’ : The Role of ‘Theory of Mind’ in Solving Coordination Problems.Oliver Curry & Matthew Jones Chesters - 2012 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 12 (1-2):147-159.
    How do people solve coordination problems? One possibility is that they use ‘ Theory of Mind’ to generate expectations about others’ behaviour. To test this, we investigate whether the ability to solve interpersonal coordination problems is associated with individual differences in ‘ Theory of Mind’, as measured by a questionnaire addressing autistic-spectrum personality traits. The results suggest that successful coordination is associated with Theory-of-Mind function, but not with the non-social components of autistic personality (e.g., pattern detection, imagination). We discuss the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Will the Real Empathy Please Stand Up? A Case for a Narrow Conceptualization.Amy Coplan - 2011 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (s1):40-65.
    A longstanding problem with the study of empathy is the lack of a clear and agreed upon definition. A trend in the recent literature is to respond to this problem by advancing a broad and all-encompassing view of empathy that applies to myriad processes ranging from mimicry and imitation to high-level perspective taking. I argue that this response takes us in the wrong direction and that what we need in order to better understand empathy is a narrower conceptualization, not a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Anchoring Utterances.Herbert H. Clark - 2021 - Topics in Cognitive Science 13 (2):329-350.
    Clark highlights a neglected issue in research on language use: the process by which speakers and addressees anchor utterances with respect to individual entities in their common ground. In his review, he identifies the challenges linked to investigations of anchoring, but also displays the pitfalls of evading it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Under Pressure: Processing Representational Decoupling in False-Belief Tasks.Anna Ciaunica - 2014 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 (4):527-542.
    Several studies demonstrated that children younger than 3 years of age, who consistently fail the standard verbal false-belief task, can anticipate others’ actions based on their attributed false beliefs. This gave rise to the so-called “Developmental Paradox”. De Bruin and Kästner recently suggested that the Developmental Paradox is best addressed in terms of the relation between coupled and decoupled processes and argued that if enactivism is to be a genuine alternative to classic cognitivism, it should be able to bridge the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mindreading underlies metacognition.Peter Carruthers - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):164-182.
    This response defends the view that human metacognition results from us turning our mindreading capacities upon ourselves, and that our access to our own propositional attitudes is through interpretation rather than introspection. Relevant evidence is considered, including that deriving from studies of childhood development and other animal species. Also discussed are data suggesting dissociations between metacognitive and mindreading capacities, especially in autism and schizophrenia.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Mindreading in adults: evaluating two-systems views.Peter Carruthers - 2017 - Synthese 194 (3):673-688.
    A number of convergent recent findings with adults have been interpreted as evidence of the existence of two distinct systems for mindreading that draw on separate conceptual resources: one that is fast, automatic, and inflexible; and one that is slower, controlled, and flexible. The present article argues that these findings admit of a more parsimonious explanation. This is that there is a single set of concepts made available by a mindreading system that operates automatically where it can, but which frequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On-line false belief understanding qua folk psychology?Martin Capstick - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (1):27-40.
    In this paper, I address Mitchell Herschbach’s arguments against the phenomenological critics of folk psychology. Central to Herschbach’s arguments is the introduction of Michael Wheeler’s distinction between ‘on-line’ and ‘off-line’ intelligence to the debate on social understanding. Herschbach uses this distinction to describe two arguments made by the phenomenological critics. The first is that folk psychology is exclusively off-line and mentalistic. The second is that social understanding is on-line and non-mentalistic. To counter the phenomenological critics, Herschbach argues for the existence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to Construct a Minimal Theory of Mind.Stephen A. Butterfill & Ian A. Apperly - 2013 - Mind and Language 28 (5):606-637.
    What could someone represent that would enable her to track, at least within limits, others' perceptions, knowledge states and beliefs including false beliefs? An obvious possibility is that she might represent these very attitudes as such. It is sometimes tacitly or explicitly assumed that this is the only possible answer. However, we argue that several recent discoveries in developmental, cognitive, and comparative psychology indicate the need for other, less obvious possibilities. Our aim is to meet this need by describing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states?Stephen Andrew Butterfill & Ian A. Apperly - 2009 - Psychological Review 116 (4):953-970.
    The lack of consensus on how to characterize humans’ capacity for belief reasoning has been brought into sharp focus by recent research. Children fail critical tests of belief reasoning before 3 to 4 years (Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001; Wimmer & Perner, 1983), yet infants apparently pass false belief tasks at 13 or 15 months (Onishi & Baillargeon, 2005; Surian, Caldi, & Sperber, 2007). Non-human animals also fail critical tests of belief reasoning but can show very complex social behaviour (e.g., (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • Memory and Common Ground Processes in Language Use.Sarah Brown-Schmidt & Melissa C. Duff - 2016 - Topics in Cognitive Science 8 (4):722-736.
    During communication, we form assumptions about what our communication partners know and believe. Information that is mutually known between the discourse partners—their common ground—serves as a backdrop for successful communication. Here we present an introduction to the focus of this topic, which is the role of memory in common ground and language use. Two types of questions emerge as central to understanding the relationship between memory and common ground, specifically questions having to do with the representation of common ground in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Addressees distinguish shared from private information when interpreting questions during interactive conversation.Sarah Brown-Schmidt, Christine Gunlogson & Michael K. Tanenhaus - 2008 - Cognition 107 (3):1122-1134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Understanding children's and adults' limitations in mental state reasoning.Paul Bloom - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (6):255-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A ‘curse of knowledge’ in the absence of knowledge? People misattribute fluency when judging how common knowledge is among their peers.Susan A. J. Birch, Patricia E. Brosseau-Liard, Taeh Haddock & Siba E. Ghrear - 2017 - Cognition 166 (C):447-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • When the theory of mind would be very useful.Piergiorgio Battistelli & Alessandra Farneti - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Pragmatic expectations and linguistic evidence: Listeners anticipate but do not integrate common ground.Dale J. Barr - 2008 - Cognition 109 (1):18-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Establishing conventional communication systems: Is common knowledge necessary?Dale J. Barr - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (6):937-962.
    How do communities establish shared communication systems? The Common Knowledge view assumes that symbolic conventions develop through the accumulation of common knowledge regarding communication practices among the members of a community. In contrast with this view, it is proposed that coordinated communication emerges a by‐product of local interactions among dyads. A set of multi‐agent computer simulations show that a population of “egocentric” agents can establish and maintain symbolic conventions without common knowledge. In the simulations, convergence to a single conventional system (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Enhancing “theory of mind” through behavioral synchrony.Adam Baimel, Rachel L. Severson, Andrew S. Baron & Susan A. J. Birch - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Two sources of evidence on the non-automaticity of true and false belief ascription.Elisa Back & Ian A. Apperly - 2010 - Cognition 115 (1):54-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Mindreading and Psycholinguistic Approaches to Perspective Taking: Establishing Common Ground.Ian Apperly - 2018 - Topics in Cognitive Science 10 (1):133-139.
    In this commentary on “Memory and Common Ground Processes in Language Use,” I draw attention to relevant work on mindreading. The concerns of research on common ground and mindreading have significant overlap, but these literatures have worked in relative isolation of each other. I attempt an assimilation, pointing out shared and distinctive concerns and mutually informative results.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Comprehension Processes of Verbal Irony: The Effects of Salience, Egocentric Context, and Allocentric Theory of Mind.Yoritaka Akimoto, Shiho Miyazawa & Toshiaki Muramoto - 2012 - Metaphor and Symbol 27 (3):217-242.
    The present study investigated the comprehension processes of verbal irony by clarifying the temporally distinct contributions of three information sources, namely, salience-based lexical meaning, egocentric context, and allocentric Theory of Mind. We predicted that salience-based lexical meaning initially activates the literal representation of an ironic utterance. This is immediately followed by the activation of the ironic representation supported by the automatic interaction between salience-based lexical meaning and egocentric context. Finally, overall interpretation is achieved by incorporating the information from Theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic Focal Bias.Mikkel Gerken - 2013 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (1):41-61.
    This paper defends strict invariantism against some philosophical and empirical data that have been taken to compromise it. The defence involves a combination of a priori philosophical arguments and empirically informed theorizing. The positive account of the data is an epistemic focal bias account that draws on cognitive psychology. It involves the assumption that, owing to limitations of the involved cognitive resources, intuitive judgments about knowledge ascriptions are generated by processing only a limited part of the available information—the part that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Mindreading in the balance : adults' mediolateral leaning and anticipatory looking foretell others' action preparation in a false-belief interactive task.Giovanni Zani, Stephen Andrew Butterfill & Jason Low - 2020 - Royal Society Open Science 7.
    Anticipatory looking on mindreading tasks can indicate our expectation of an agent's action. The challenge is that social situations are often more complex, involving instances where we need to track an agent's false belief to successfully identify the outcome to which an action is directed. If motor processes can guide how action goals are understood, it is conceivable— where that kind of goal ascription occurs in false-belief tasks— for motor representations to account for someone's belief-like state. Testing adults (N = (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic and social cognition the facts matter, and so do computational models.Rineke Verbrugge - 2009 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (6):649-680.
    This article takes off from Johan van Benthem’s ruminations on the interface between logic and cognitive science in his position paper “Logic and reasoning: Do the facts matter?”. When trying to answer Van Benthem’s question whether logic can be fruitfully combined with psychological experiments, this article focuses on a specific domain of reasoning, namely higher-order social cognition, including attributions such as “Bob knows that Alice knows that he wrote a novel under pseudonym”. For intelligent interaction, it is important that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Logic and Social Cognition: The Facts Matter, and So Do Computational Models.Rineke Verbrugge - 2009 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (6):649-680.
    This article takes off from Johan van Benthem’s ruminations on the interface between logic and cognitive science in his position paper “Logic and reasoning: Do the facts matter?”. When trying to answer Van Benthem’s question whether logic can be fruitfully combined with psychological experiments, this article focuses on a specific domain of reasoning, namely higher-order social cognition, including attributions such as “Bob knows that Alice knows that he wrote a novel under pseudonym”. For intelligent interaction, it is important that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Dissociation of posture remapping and cognitive load in level-2 perspective-taking.Yei-Yu Yeh, Chi-Chin Wang, Shih-Kuen Cheng & Chui-De Chiu - 2021 - Cognition 214 (C):104733.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Belief–desire reasoning in the explanation of behavior: Do actions speak louder than words?Annie E. Wertz & Tamsin C. German - 2007 - Cognition 105 (1):184-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Minimal coherence among varied theory of mind measures in childhood and adulthood.Katherine Rice Warnell & Elizabeth Redcay - 2019 - Cognition 191 (C):103997.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is egocentric bias evidence for simulation theory.Annika Wallin - 2011 - Synthese 178 (3):503-514.
    Revised simulation theory allows mental state attributions containing some or all of the attributor's genuine, non-simulated mental states. It is thought that this gives the revised theory an empirical advantage, because unlike theory theory and rationality theory, it can explain egocentric bias. I challenge this view, arguing that theory theory and rationality theory can explain egocentricity by appealing to heuristic mindreading and the diagnosticity of attributors' own beliefs, and that these explanations are as simple and consistent as those provided by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Learning to apply theory of mind.Rineke Verbrugge & Lisette Mol - 2008 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 17 (4):489-511.
    In everyday life it is often important to have a mental model of the knowledge, beliefs, desires, and intentions of other people. Sometimes it is even useful to to have a correct model of their model of our own mental states: a second-order Theory of Mind. In order to investigate to what extent adults use and acquire complex skills and strategies in the domains of Theory of Mind and the related skill of natural language use, we conducted an experiment. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Toward a Computational Psycholinguistics of Reference Production.Kees van Deemter, Albert Gatt, Roger P. G. van Gompel & Emiel Krahmer - 2012 - Topics in Cognitive Science 4 (2):166-183.
    This article introduces the topic ‘‘Production of Referring Expressions: Bridging the Gap between Computational and Empirical Approaches to Reference’’ of the journal Topics in Cognitive Science. We argue that computational and psycholinguistic approaches to reference production can benefit from closer interaction, and that this is likely to result in the construction of algorithms that differ markedly from the ones currently known in the computational literature. We focus particularly on determinism, the feature of existing algorithms that is perhaps most clearly at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Generation of Referring Expressions: Assessing the Incremental Algorithm.Kees van Deemter, Albert Gatt, Ielka van der Sluis & Richard Power - 2012 - Cognitive Science 36 (5):799-836.
    A substantial amount of recent work in natural language generation has focused on the generation of ‘‘one-shot’’ referring expressions whose only aim is to identify a target referent. Dale and Reiter's Incremental Algorithm (IA) is often thought to be the best algorithm for maximizing the similarity to referring expressions produced by people. We test this hypothesis by eliciting referring expressions from human subjects and computing the similarity between the expressions elicited and the ones generated by algorithms. It turns out that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Editorial: Models of Reference.Kees van Deemter, Emiel Krahmer, Albert Gatt & Roger P. G. van Gompel - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dissociating processes underlying level-1 visual perspective taking in adults.Andrew R. Todd, C. Daryl Cameron & Austin J. Simpson - 2017 - Cognition 159 (C):97-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Anxiety impairs spontaneous perspective calculation: Evidence from a level-1 visual perspective-taking task.Andrew R. Todd & Austin J. Simpson - 2016 - Cognition 156 (C):88-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Unintentional perspective-taking calculates whether something is seen, but not how it is seen.Andrew Surtees, Dana Samson & Ian Apperly - 2016 - Cognition 148 (C):97-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Similarities and differences in visual and spatial perspective-taking processes.Andrew Surtees, Ian Apperly & Dana Samson - 2013 - Cognition 129 (2):426-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • I’ve got your number: Spontaneous perspective-taking in an interactive task.Andrew Surtees, Ian Apperly & Dana Samson - 2016 - Cognition 150 (C):43-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • How to Construct a Minimal Theory of Mind.Ian A. Apperly Stephen A. Butterfill - 2013 - Mind and Language 28 (5):606-637.
    What could someone represent that would enable her to track, at least within limits, others' perceptions, knowledge states and beliefs including false beliefs? An obvious possibility is that she might represent these very attitudes as such. It is sometimes tacitly or explicitly assumed that this is the only possible answer. However, we argue that several recent discoveries in developmental, cognitive, and comparative psychology indicate the need for other, less obvious possibilities. Our aim is to meet this need by describing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Intergroup visual perspective-taking: Shared group membership impairs self-perspective inhibition but may facilitate perspective calculation.Austin J. Simpson & Andrew R. Todd - 2017 - Cognition 166 (C):371-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What do you know? ERP evidence for immediate use of common ground during online reference resolution.Les Sikos, Samuel B. Tomlinson, Conor Heins & Daniel J. Grodner - 2019 - Cognition 182 (C):275-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Addressees distinguish shared from private information when interpreting questions during interactive conversation.Michael K. Tanenhaus Sarah Brown-Schmidt, Christine Gunlogson - 2008 - Cognition 107 (3):1122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • How do you know that? Automatic belief inferences in passing conversation.Paula Rubio-Fernández, Francis Mollica, Michelle Oraa Ali & Edward Gibson - 2019 - Cognition 193 (C):104011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Development of Shared Liking of Representational but not Abstract Art in Primary School Children and Their Justifications for Liking.Paul Rodway, Julie Kirkham, Astrid Schepman, Jordana Lambert & Anastasia Locke - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pooling the ground: understanding and coordination in collective sense making.Joanna Rä…Czaszek-Leonardi, Agnieszka Dä™Bska & Adam Sochanowicz - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • In defense of a developmental dogma: children acquire propositional attitude folk psychology around age 4.Hannes Rakoczy - 2017 - Synthese 194 (3):689-707.
    When do children acquire a propositional attitude folk psychology or theory of mind? The orthodox answer to this central question of developmental ToM research had long been that around age 4 children begin to apply “belief” and other propositional attitude concepts. This orthodoxy has recently come under serious attack, though, from two sides: Scoffers complain that it over-estimates children’s early competence and claim that a proper understanding of propositional attitudes emerges only much later. Boosters criticize the orthodoxy for underestimating early (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • An Audience Effect in Sooty Mangabey Alarm Calling.Fredy Quintero, Sonia Touitou, Martina Magris & Klaus Zuberbühler - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    How does intentional communication evolve? Comparative studies can shed light on the evolutionary history of this relevant feature of human language and its distribution before modern humans. The current animal literature on intentional signaling consists mostly of ape gestural studies with evidence of subjects persisting and elaborating with sometimes arbitrary signals toward a desired outcome. Although vocalizations can also have such imperative qualities, they are typically produced in a functionally fixed manner, as if evolved for a specific purpose. Yet, intentionality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What can metacognition teach us about the evolution of communication?Joëlle Proust - 2023 - Evolutionary Linguistic Theory 5 (1):1-10.
    Procedural metacognition is the set of affect-based mechanisms allowing agents to regulate cognitive actions like perceptual discrimination, memory retrieval or problem solving. This article proposes that procedural metacognition has had a major role in the evolution of communication. A plausible hypothesis is that, under pressure for maximizing signalling efficiency, the metacognitive abilities used by nonhumans to regulate their perception and their memory have been re-used to regulate their communication. On this view, detecting one’s production errors in signalling, or solving species-specific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue.Martin J. Pickering & Simon Garrod - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):169-190.
    Traditional mechanistic accounts of language processing derive almost entirely from the study of monologue. Yet, the most natural and basic form of language use is dialogue. As a result, these accounts may only offer limited theories of the mechanisms that underlie language processing in general. We propose a mechanistic account of dialogue, the interactive alignment account, and use it to derive a number of predictions about basic language processes. The account assumes that, in dialogue, the linguistic representations employed by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations