Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Proofs and pictures.James Robert Brown - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2):161-180.
    Everyone appreciates a clever mathematical picture, but the prevailing attitude is one of scepticism: diagrams, illustrations, and pictures prove nothing; they are psychologically important and heuristically useful, but only a traditional verbal/symbolic proof provides genuine evidence for a purported theorem. Like some other recent writers (Barwise and Etchemendy [1991]; Shin [1994]; and Giaquinto [1994]) I take a different view and argue, from historical considerations and some striking examples, for a positive evidential role for pictures in mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Incomplete understanding of complex numbers Girolamo Cardano: a case study in the acquisition of mathematical concepts.Denis Buehler - 2014 - Synthese 191 (17):4231-4252.
    In this paper, I present the case of the discovery of complex numbers by Girolamo Cardano. Cardano acquires the concepts of (specific) complex numbers, complex addition, and complex multiplication. His understanding of these concepts is incomplete. I show that his acquisition of these concepts cannot be explained on the basis of Christopher Peacocke’s Conceptual Role Theory of concept possession. I argue that Strong Conceptual Role Theories that are committed to specifying a set of transitions that is both necessary and sufficient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historical development of the foundations of mathematics: Course description.Robert L. Brabenec - 1994 - Science & Education 3 (3):295-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Concept Formation and Concept Grounding.Jörgen Sjögren & Christian Bennet - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):827-839.
    Recently Carrie S. Jenkins formulated an epistemology of mathematics, or rather arithmetic, respecting apriorism, empiricism, and realism. Central is an idea of concept grounding. The adequacy of this idea has been questioned e.g. concerning the grounding of the mathematically central concept of set (or class), and of composite concepts. In this paper we present a view of concept formation in mathematics, based on ideas from Carnap, leading to modifications of Jenkins’s epistemology that may solve some problematic issues with her ideas. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Logical and Philosophical Foundations for the Possibility of True Contradictions.Ben Martin - 2014 - Dissertation, University College London
    The view that contradictions cannot be true has been part of accepted philosophical theory since at least the time of Aristotle. In this regard, it is almost unique in the history of philosophy. Only in the last forty years has the view been systematically challenged with the advent of dialetheism. Since Graham Priest introduced dialetheism as a solution to certain self-referential paradoxes, the possibility of true contradictions has been a live issue in the philosophy of logic. Yet, despite the arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Mathematical Roots of Semantic Analysis.Axel Arturo Barcelo Aspeitia - manuscript
    Semantic analysis in early analytic philosophy belongs to a long tradition of adopting geometrical methodologies to the solution of philosophical problems. In particular, it adapts Descartes’ development of formalization as a mechanism of analytic representation, for its application in natural language semantics. This article aims to trace the mathematical roots of Frege, Russel and Carnap’s analytic method. Special attention is paid to the formal character of modern analysis introduced by Descartes. The goal is to identify the particular conception of “form” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conventionalism in Reid’s ‘Geometry of Visibles’.Edward Slowik - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 34:467-489.
    The role of conventions in the formulation of Thomas Reid’s theory of the geometry of vision, which he calls the “geometry of visibles”, is the subject of this investigation. In particular, we will examine the work of N. Daniels and R. Angell who have alleged that, respectively, Reid’s “geometry of visibles” and the geometry of the visual field are non-Euclidean. As will be demonstrated, however, the construction of any geometry of vision is subject to a choice of conventions regarding the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Poncelet’s porism: a long story of renewed discoveries, I.Andrea Del Centina - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (1):1-122.
    In 1813, J.-V. Poncelet discovered that if there exists a polygon of n-sides, which is inscribed in a given conic and circumscribed about another conic, then infinitely many such polygons exist. This theorem became known as Poncelet’s porism, and the related polygons were called Poncelet’s polygons. In this article, we trace the history of the research about the existence of such polygons, from the “prehistorical” work of W. Chapple, of the middle of the eighteenth century, to the modern approach of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Kepler’s system of conics in Astronomiae pars optica.Andrea Del Centina - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (6):567-589.
    This is an attempt to explain Kepler’s invention of the first “non-cone-based” system of conics, and to put it into a historical perspective.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Analyse et géométrie, histoire des courbes gauches De Clairaut à Darboux.Jean Delcourt - 2011 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 65 (3):229-293.
    RésuméCet article est consacré à l’histoire de la théorie locale des courbes “à double courbure”. Initiée par Clairaut en 1731, cette théorie se développe en parallèle à la théorie des surfaces et trouve son achèvement avec les formules de Serret et Frenet et leur interprétation par Darboux, en 1887. Au delà de l’analyse des contributions de nombreux mathématiciens, parmi lesquels Monge bien sûr mais aussi Fourier, Lagrange et Cauchy, notre étude donne un regard particulier sur l’évolution conjointe de l’Analyse et (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beyond the methodology of mathematics research programmes.Corfield David - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3):272-301.
    In this paper I assess the obstacles to a transfer of Lakatos's methodology of scientific research programmes to mathematics. I argue that, if we are to use something akin to this methodology to discuss modern mathematics with its interweaving theoretical development, we shall require a more intricate construction and we shall have to move still further away from seeing mathematical knowledge as a collection of statements. I also examine the notion of rivalry within mathematics and claim that this appears to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Whittaker’s analytical dynamics: a biography.S. C. Coutinho - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (3):355-407.
    Originally published in 1904, Whittaker’s A Treatise on the Analytical Dynamics of Particles and Rigid Bodies soon became a classic of the subject and has remained in print for most of these 108 years. In this paper, we follow the book as it develops from a report that Whittaker wrote for the British Society for the Advancement of Science to its influence on Dirac’s version of quantum mechanics in the 1920s and beyond.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Categoricity.John Corcoran - 1980 - History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1):187-207.
    After a short preface, the first of the three sections of this paper is devoted to historical and philosophic aspects of categoricity. The second section is a self-contained exposition, including detailed definitions, of a proof that every mathematical system whose domain is the closure of its set of distinguished individuals under its distinguished functions is categorically characterized by its induction principle together with its true atoms (atomic sentences and negations of atomic sentences). The third section deals with applications especially those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Assaying lakatos's philosophy of mathematics.David Corfield - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (1):99-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The ontological commitments of inconsistent theories.Mark Colyvan - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 141 (1):115 - 123.
    In this paper I present an argument for belief in inconsistent objects. The argument relies on a particular, plausible version of scientific realism, and the fact that often our best scientific theories are inconsistent. It is not clear what to make of this argument. Is it a reductio of the version of scientific realism under consideration? If it is, what are the alternatives? Should we just accept the conclusion? I will argue (rather tentatively and suitably qualified) for a positive answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • In defence of indispensability.Mark Colyvan - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (1):39-62.
    Indispensability arguments for realism about mathematical entities have come under serious attack in recent years. To my mind the most profound attack has come from Penelope Maddy, who argues that scientific/mathematical practice doesn't support the key premise of the indispensability argument, that is, that we ought to have ontological commitment to those entities that are indispensable to our best scientific theories. In this paper I defend the Quine/Putnam indispensability argument against Maddy's objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Abstraction in computer science.Timothy Colburn & Gary Shute - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):169-184.
    We characterize abstraction in computer science by first comparing the fundamental nature of computer science with that of its cousin mathematics. We consider their primary products, use of formalism, and abstraction objectives, and find that the two disciplines are sharply distinguished. Mathematics, being primarily concerned with developing inference structures, has information neglect as its abstraction objective. Computer science, being primarily concerned with developing interaction patterns, has information hiding as its abstraction objective. We show that abstraction through information hiding is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Paradigm transitions in mathematics.Claire L. Parkinson - 1987 - Philosophia Mathematica (2):127-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Search of Intuition.Elijah Chudnoff - 2020 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98 (3):465-480.
    What are intuitions? Stereotypical examples may suggest that they are the results of common intellectual reflexes. But some intuitions defy the stereotype: there are hard-won intuitions that take d...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ambiguities of Fundamental Concepts in Mathematical Analysis During the Mid-nineteenth Century.Kajsa Bråting - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (4):301-320.
    In this paper we consider the major development of mathematical analysis during the mid-nineteenth century. On the basis of Jahnke’s (Hist Math 20(3):265–284, 1993 ) distinction between considering mathematics as an empirical science based on time and space and considering mathematics as a purely conceptual science we discuss the Swedish nineteenth century mathematician E.G. Björling’s general view of real- and complexvalued functions. We argue that Björling had a tendency to sometimes consider mathematical objects in a naturalistic way. One example is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pānini and Euclid: Reflections on Indian Geometry. [REVIEW]Johannes Bronkhorst - 2001 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 29 (1/2):43-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Le funzioni a periodi multipli nella corrispondenza tra Hermite e Casorati.Umberto Bottazzini - 1977 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 18 (1):39-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The transzendenz of mathematical 'experience'.William Boos - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):49-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Operationalism: An Interpretation of the Philosophy of Ancient Greek Geometry.Viktor Blåsjö - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (2):587-708.
    I present a systematic interpretation of the foundational purpose of constructions in ancient Greek geometry. I argue that Greek geometers were committed to an operationalist foundational program, according to which all of mathematics—including its entire ontology and epistemology—is based entirely on concrete physical constructions. On this reading, key foundational aspects of Greek geometry are analogous to core tenets of 20th-century operationalist/positivist/constructivist/intuitionist philosophy of science and mathematics. Operationalism provides coherent answers to a range of traditional philosophical problems regarding classical mathematics, such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Energy: Learning from the Past.Fabio Bevilacqua - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (6):1231-1243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematical Arguments in Context.Jean Bendegem & Bart Kerkhove - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (1-2):45-57.
    Except in very poor mathematical contexts, mathematical arguments do not stand in isolation of other mathematical arguments. Rather, they form trains of formal and informal arguments, adding up to interconnected theorems, theories and eventually entire fields. This paper critically comments on some common views on the relation between formal and informal mathematical arguments, most particularly applications of Toulmin’s argumentation model, and launches a number of alternative ideas of presentation inviting the contextualization of pieces of mathematical reasoning within encompassing bodies of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wigner’s Puzzle for Mathematical Naturalism.Sorin Bangu - 2009 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 23 (3):245-263.
    I argue that a recent version of the doctrine of mathematical naturalism faces difficulties arising in connection with Wigner's old puzzle about the applicability of mathematics to natural science. I discuss the strategies to solve the puzzle and I show that they may not be available to the naturalist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ‘Miracle’ of Applicability? The Curious Case of the Simple Harmonic Oscillator.Sorin Bangu & Robert H. C. Moir - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (5):507-525.
    The paper discusses to what extent the conceptual issues involved in solving the simple harmonic oscillator model fit Wigner’s famous point that the applicability of mathematics borders on the miraculous. We argue that although there is ultimately nothing mysterious here, as is to be expected, a careful demonstration that this is so involves unexpected difficulties. Consequently, through the lens of this simple case we derive some insight into what is responsible for the appearance of mystery in more sophisticated examples of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leibniz on Continuity.Richard T. W. Arthur - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):105-115.
    Leibniz never tired of stressing the fundamental importance of the concept of continuity for philosophy, nor was he shy of attributing major importance to his own struggle through “the labyrinth of the continuum” for the subsequent development of his whole system of thought. Unfortunately, however, his own thought on the subject is something of a labyrinth itself, and from a modern point of view many of his pronouncements are apt to seem blatantly contradictory.Certain quotations seem to commit him unambiguously to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Riemann and the theory of electrical phenomena: Nobili’s rings.Thomas Archibald - 1991 - Centaurus 34 (3):247--271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Desargues' Method of Perspective Its Mathematical Content, Its Connection to Other Perspective Methods and Its Relation to Desargues' Ideas on Projective Geometry.Kirsti Andersen - 1991 - Centaurus 34 (1):44-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Development of Mathematics. [REVIEW]Donald Gillies - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):68-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Charles L. Dodgson’s Work on Trigonometry.Francine F. Abeles - 2019 - Acta Baltica Historiae Et Philosophiae Scientiarum 7 (1):27-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semiotic Scaffolding in Mathematics.Mikkel Willum Johansen & Morten Misfeldt - 2015 - Biosemiotics 8 (2):325-340.
    This paper investigates the notion of semiotic scaffolding in relation to mathematics by considering its influence on mathematical activities, and on the evolution of mathematics as a research field. We will do this by analyzing the role different representational forms play in mathematical cognition, and more broadly on mathematical activities. In the main part of the paper, we will present and analyze three different cases. For the first case, we investigate the semiotic scaffolding involved in pencil and paper multiplication. For (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logic and philosophy of mathematics in the early Husserl.Stefania Centrone - 2010 - New York: Springer.
    This volume will be of particular interest to researchers working in the history, and in the philosophy, of logic and mathematics, and more generally, to ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The foundations of mathematics from a historical viewpoint.Antonino Drago - 2015 - Epistemologia 38 (1):133-151.
    A new hypothesis on the basic features characterising the Foundations of Mathematics is suggested. By means of them the entire historical development of Mathematics before the 20th Century is summarised through a table. Also the several programs, launched around the year 1900, on the Foundations of Mathematics are characterised by a corresponding table. The major difficulty that these programs met was to recognize an alternative to the basic feature of the deductive organization of a theory - more precisely, to Hilbert’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Merleau-Ponty and the transcendental problem of bodily agency.Rasmus Thybo Jensen - 2013 - In Rasmus Thybo Jensen & Dermot Moran (eds.), The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity, Contributions to Phenomenology 71. Springer. pp. 43-61.
    I argue that we find the articulation of a problem concerning bodily agency in the early works of the Merleau-Ponty which he explicates as analogous to what he explicitly calls the problem of perception. The problem of perception is the problem of seeing how we can have the object given in person through it perspectival appearances. The problem concerning bodily agency is the problem of seeing how our bodily movements can be the direct manifestation of a person’s intentions in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pasch's empiricism as methodological structuralism.Dirk Schlimm - 2020 - In Erich H. Reck & Georg Schiemer (eds.), The Pre-History of Mathematical Structuralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 80-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematical Monsters.Andrew Aberdein - 2019 - In Diego Compagna & Stefanie Steinhart (eds.), Monsters, Monstrosities, and the Monstrous in Culture and Society. Vernon Press. pp. 391-412.
    Monsters lurk within mathematical as well as literary haunts. I propose to trace some pathways between these two monstrous habitats. I start from Jeffrey Jerome Cohen’s influential account of monster culture and explore how well mathematical monsters fit each of his seven theses. The mathematical monsters I discuss are drawn primarily from three distinct but overlapping domains. Firstly, late nineteenth-century mathematicians made numerous unsettling discoveries that threatened their understanding of their own discipline and challenged their intuitions. The great French mathematician (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological Practice and Complementary Concepts of Logical Consequence: Tarski's Model-Theoretic Consequence and Corcoran's Information-Theoretic Consequence.José M. Sagüillo - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (1):21-48.
    This article discusses two coextensive concepts of logical consequence that are implicit in the two fundamental logical practices of establishing validity and invalidity for premise-conclusion arguments. The premises and conclusion of an argument have information content (they ?say? something), and they have subject matter (they are ?about? something). The asymmetry between establishing validity and establishing invalidity has long been noted: validity is established through an information-processing procedure exhibiting a step-by-step deduction of the conclusion from the premise-set. Invalidity is established by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mathematical Logic: On Numbers, Sets, Structures, and Symmetry.Roman Kossak - 2018 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    This book, presented in two parts, offers a slow introduction to mathematical logic, and several basic concepts of model theory, such as first-order definability, types, symmetries, and elementary extensions. Its first part, Logic Sets, and Numbers, shows how mathematical logic is used to develop the number structures of classical mathematics. The exposition does not assume any prerequisites; it is rigorous, but as informal as possible. All necessary concepts are introduced exactly as they would be in a course in mathematical logic; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The meaning of the wave function: in search of the ontology of quantum mechanics.Shan Gao - 2017 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    The meaning of the wave function has been a hot topic of debate since the early days of quantum mechanics. Recent years have witnessed a growing interest in this long-standing question. Is the wave function ontic, directly representing a state of reality, or epistemic, merely representing a state of knowledge, or something else? If the wave function is not ontic, then what, if any, is the underlying state of reality? If the wave function is indeed ontic, then exactly what physical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Kirchhoff’s theory for optical diffraction, its predecessor and subsequent development: the resilience of an inconsistent theory.Chen-Pang Yeang & Jed Z. Buchwald - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (5):463-511.
    Kirchhoff’s 1882 theory of optical diffraction forms the centerpiece in the long-term development of wave optics, one that commenced in the 1820s when Fresnel produced an empirically successful theory based on a reinterpretation of Huygens’ principle, but without working from a wave equation. Then, in 1856, Stokes demonstrated that the principle was derivable from such an equation albeit without consideration of boundary conditions. Kirchhoff’s work a quarter century later marked a crucial, and widely influential, point for he produced Fresnel’s results (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychological foundations of number: numerical competence in human infants.Karen Wynn - 1998 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2 (8):296-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Book reviews: David Papineau,thinking about consciousness, clarendon press (oxford university press), 2002, XIV + 266 pp., $35.00 (hardcover), ISBN 0-19924-382-. [REVIEW]Richard Wyatt - 2005 - Minds and Machines 15 (1):113-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nested realities and human consciousness: The paradoxical expression of evolutionary process.Paul C. Wohlmuth - 1988 - World Futures 25 (3):199-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Idealization and external symbolic storage: the epistemic and technical dimensions of theoretic cognition.Peter Woelert - 2012 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11 (3):335-366.
    This paper explores some of the constructive dimensions and specifics of human theoretic cognition, combining perspectives from (Husserlian) genetic phenomenology and distributed cognition approaches. I further consult recent psychological research concerning spatial and numerical cognition. The focus is on the nexus between the theoretic development of abstract, idealized geometrical and mathematical notions of space and the development and effective use of environmental cognitive support systems. In my discussion, I show that the evolution of the theoretic cognition of space apparently follows (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Pure and the Applied: Bourbakism Comes to Mathematical Economics.E. Roy Weintraub & Philip Mirowski - 1994 - Science in Context 7 (2):245-272.
    The ArgumentIn the minds of many, the Bourbakist trend in mathematics was characterized by pursuit of rigor to the detriment of concern for applications or didactic concessions to the nonmathematician, which would seem to render the concept of a Bourbakist incursion into a field of applied mathematices an oxymoron. We argue that such a conjuncture did in fact happen in postwar mathematical economics, and describe the career of Gérard Debreu to illustrate how it happened. Using the work of Leo Corry (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Axiomatization of the Symbols System of Classic of Changes: The Marriage of Oriental Mysticism and Western Scientific Tradition.Xijia Wang - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (2):315-325.
    Classic of Changes is a Chinese cultural classic born more than 3000 years ago. Its profound philosophical thoughts and the use of divination have brought Classic of Changes to a strong oriental mysticism. The view of the heaven and man of yin and yang and the five elements states of Classic of Changes are completely different from the Western elemental theory of ancient Greece. The latter gave birth to classical and modern scientific theories, and the yin and yang and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Deleuze's Third Synthesis of Time.Daniela Voss - 2013 - Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 7 (2):194-216.
    Deleuze's theory of time set out in Difference and Repetition is a complex structure of three different syntheses of time – the passive synthesis of the living present, the passive synthesis of the pure past and the static synthesis of the future. This article focuses on Deleuze's third synthesis of time, which seems to be the most obscure part of his tripartite theory, as Deleuze mixes different theoretical concepts drawn from philosophy, Greek drama theory and mathematics. Of central importance is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations