Switch to: References

Citations of:

History of science and its rational reconstructions

In R. C. Buck & R. S. Cohen (eds.), Psa 1970. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Viii. D. Reidel. pp. 91-108 (1971)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Theory-assessment in the historiography of science.James W. McAllister - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (3):315-333.
    This paper argues that evaluation of the truth and rationality of past scientific theories is both possible and profitable. The motivation for this enterprise is traced to recent discussions by I. Lakatos, L. Laudan and others on the import of history for the philosophy of science; several objections to it are considered and T. S. Kuhn is found to advance the most substantive. An argument for establishing judgements of rationality and truth in the face of scientific revolutions is presented; finally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lakatos as historian of mathematics.Brendan P. Larvor - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (1):42-64.
    This paper discusses the connection between the actual history of mathematics and Lakatos's philosophy of mathematics, in three parts. The first points to studies by Lakatos and others which support his conception of mathematics and its history. In the second I suggest that the apparent poverty of Lakatosian examples may be due to the way in which the history of mathematics is usually written. The third part argues that Lakatos is right to hold philosophy accountable to history, even if Lakatos's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • From Marginal Utility to Revealed Preference.Marek Hudík - 2013 - E-Logos 20 (1):1-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Brownian Motion in Finance: An Epistemological Puzzle.Christian Walter - 2019 - Topoi 40 (4):1-17.
    While in medicine, comparison of the data supplied by a clinical syndrome with the data supplied by the biological system is used to arrive at the most accurate diagnosis, the same cannot be said of financial economics: the accumulation of statistical results that contradict the Brownian hypothesis used in risk modelling, combined with serious empirical problems in the practical implementation of the Black-Scholes-Merton model, the benchmark theory of mathematical finance founded on the Brownian hypothesis, has failed to change the Brownian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Underconsideration in Space-time and Particle Physics.J. Brian Pitts - unknown
    The idea that a serious threat to scientific realism comes from unconceived alternatives has been proposed by van Fraassen, Sklar, Stanford and Wray among others. Peter Lipton's critique of this threat from underconsideration is examined briefly in terms of its logic and its applicability to the case of space-time and particle physics. The example of space-time and particle physics indicates a generic heuristic for quantitative sciences for constructing potentially serious cases of underdetermination, involving one-parameter family of rivals T_m that work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rationality in inquiry : on the revisability of cognitive standards.Jonas Nilsson - 2000 - Umeå Studies in Philosophy 1:154.
    The topic of this study is to what extent standards of rational inquiry can be rationally criticized and revised. It is argued that it is rational to treat all such standards as open to criticism and revision. Arguments to the effect that we are fallible with regard to all standards of rational inquiry are presented. Standards cannot be ultimately justified and with certainty established either as adequate or as inescapable presuppositions. Apel's attempt to give ultimate justifications of certain moral and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How important are the laws of definite and multiple proportions in chemistry and teaching chemistry?–A history and philosophy of science perspective.Mansoor Niaz - 2001 - Science & Education 10 (3):243-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Theory Choice, Good Sense and Social Consensus.Milena Ivanova & Cedric Paternotte - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (5):1109-1132.
    There has been a significant interest in the recent literature in developing a solution to the problem of theory choice which is both normative and descriptive, but agent-based rather than rule-based, originating from Pierre Duhem’s notion of ‘good sense’. In this paper we present the properties Duhem attributes to good sense in different contexts, before examining its current reconstructions advanced in the literature and their limitations. We propose an alternative account of good sense, seen as promoting social consensus in science, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Content of Science Debate in the Historiography of the Scientific Revolution.John Nnaji & José Luis Luján - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):99-109.
    The issue of internalism and externalism in historiography of science was intensely debated two decades ago. The conclusions of such debate on the ‘context of science’ appear to be a reinstatement of the positivist view of the ‘content of science’ as comprising only ideas and concepts uninfluenced by extra-scientific factors. The description of the roles of politics, economy, and socio-cultural factors in science was limited only within the ‘context of science’. This article seeks to resituate the ‘content of science’ debate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kitcher's compromise: A critical examination of the compromise model of scientific closure, and its implications for the relationship between history and philosophy of science.Timothy Shanahan - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (2):319-338.
    In The Advancement of Science (1993) Philip Kitcher develops what he calls the 'Compromise Model' of the closure of scientific debates. The model is designed to acknowledge significant elements from 'Rationalist' and 'Antirationalist' accounts of science, without succumbing to the one-sidedness of either. As part of an ambitious naturalistic account of scientific progress, Kitcher's model succeeds to the extent that transitions in the history of science satisfy its several conditions. I critically evaluate the Compromise Model by identifying its crucial assumptions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Realism, relativism, and constructivism.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1991 - Synthese 89 (1):135 - 162.
    This paper gives a critical evaluation of the philosophical presuppositions and implications of two current schools in the sociology of knowledge: the Strong Programme of Bloor and Barnes; and the Constructivism of Latour and Knorr-Cetina. Bloor's arguments for his externalist symmetry thesis (i.e., scientific beliefs must always be explained by social factors) are found to be incoherent or inconclusive. At best, they suggest a Weak Programme of the sociology of science: when theoretical preferences in a scientific community, SC, are first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Genetic epistemology, equilibration and the rationality of scientific change.Richard F. Kitchener - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (3):339-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kuhn's second thoughts. [REVIEW]Alan E. Musgrave - 1971 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (3):287-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The State, Democracy, and Class Rule: Remarks on the Hoppean Approach.Norbert Slenzok - 2021 - Civitas. Studia Z Filozofii Polityki 28:103-136.
    The subject-matter of the paper is the theory of class struggle proposed by Hans-Hermann Hoppe, one of the leading representatives of libertarian political philosophy in the radical tradition of Murray N. Rothbard. The author reconstructs and critically comments on the theory at hand. The author's remarks focus on the ethical and methodological background of Hoppe's approach, the main question being whether the latter theory is consonant with the thinker's positions on ethics and methodology, as well as with his political standpoint. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy of science and history of science: A troubling interaction.Cassandra Pinnick & George Gale - 2000 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 31 (1):109-125.
    History and philosophy complement and overlap each other in subject matter, but the two disciplines exhibit conflict over methodology. Since Hempel's challenge to historians that they should adopt the covering law model of explanation, the methodological conflict has revolved around the respective roles of the general and the particular in each discipline. In recent years, the revival of narrativism in history, coupled with the trend in philosophy of science to rely upon case studies, joins the methodological conflict anew. So long (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Kant, Schlick and Friedman on Space, Time and Gravity in Light of Three Lessons from Particle Physics.J. Brian Pitts - 2018 - Erkenntnis 83 (2):135-161.
    Kantian philosophy of space, time and gravity is significantly affected in three ways by particle physics. First, particle physics deflects Schlick’s General Relativity-based critique of synthetic a priori knowledge. Schlick argued that since geometry was not synthetic a priori, nothing was—a key step toward logical empiricism. Particle physics suggests a Kant-friendlier theory of space-time and gravity presumably approximating General Relativity arbitrarily well, massive spin-2 gravity, while retaining a flat space-time geometry that is indirectly observable at large distances. The theory’s roots (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Methodology and finance.Reinhard H. Schmidt - 1982 - Theory and Decision 14 (4):391-413.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • History of Physics as a Tool to Detect the Conceptual Difficulties Experienced by Students: The Case of Simple Electric Circuits in Primary Education.Matteo Leone - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (4):923-953.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Idealizations, intertheory explanations and conditionals.Hans Rott - 2011 - In Erik J. Olson Sebastian Enqvist (ed.), Belief Revision meets Philosophy of Science. Springer. pp. 59–75.
    Drawing inspiration from Lakatos’s philosophy of science, the paper presents a notion of intertheory explanation that is suitable to explain, from the point of view of a successor theory, its predecessor theory’s success (where it is successful) as well as the latter’s failure (where it fails) at the same time. A variation of the Ramsey-test is used, together with a standard AGM belief revision model, to give a semantics for open and counterfactual conditionals and ’because’-sentences featuring in such intertheory explanations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alternative Models of Scientific Rationality: Theorisation in Classical Indian Sciences.Virendra Shekhawat - 1988 - Diogenes 36 (144):32-51.
    The roots of scientific epistemology have generally been recognized in the Greeks, Aristotle and Euclid,—the former representing an empiricist trend whereas the latter representing a rationalist trend. Very little is known about classical Indian scientific epistemologies which are generally considered at least two centuries earlier than Aristotle. Inspired by the Aristotelian and Euclidean models of scientific rationality, various new models have flourished in contemporary Western thought, the prominent ones being the logical-empiricist-inductivist model (Reichenbach), the hypothet-ico-deductivist-falsificationist model (Popper), conventionalist-rationalist model (Pioncaré, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Towards a system philosophy of scientific research.Gerard Radnitzky - 1974 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4 (3):369-398.
    Can research be studied in a way that is neither logical reconstruction nor empirical psychology or sociology of science? In contemporary philosophy of science this is usually denied—in spite of the recent 'paradigm shift' there. A system-philosophy approach in theory of research is outlined by means of some models : a research enterprise is viewed as a productive, innovative system, the research process as a transformation of complexes of knowledge-problems-instruments (software and hard ware). The direction this development takes is guided (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)History of Science and the Material Theory of Induction: Einstein’s Quanta, Mercury’s Perihelion.John Norton - 2011
    The use of the material theory of induction to vindicate a scientist’s claims of evidential warrant is illustrated with the cases of Einstein’s thermodynamic argument for light quanta of 1905 and his recovery of the anomalous motion of Mercury from general relativity in 1915. In a survey of other accounts of inductive inference applied to these examples, I show that, if it is to succeed, each account must presume the same material facts as the material theory and, in addition, some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An evolutionary account of science: A response to Rosenberg's critical notice. [REVIEW]David L. Hull - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (2):229-236.
    In his critical notice, Rosenberg (1991) raises three objections to my evolutionary account of science: whether it is more than a week metaphor, the compatibility of my past objections to reduction and my current advocacy of viewing selection in terms of replication and interaction, and finally, the feasibility of identifying appropriate replicators and interactors in biological evolution, let alone conceptual evolution. I discuss each of these objections in turn.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy of chemistry and the image of science.Rein Vihalemm - 2007 - Foundations of Science 12 (3):223-234.
    The philosophical analysis of chemistry has advanced at such a pace during the last dozen years that the existence of philosophy of chemistry as an autonomous discipline cannot be doubted any more. The present paper will attempt to analyse the experience of philosophy of chemistry at the, so to say, meta-level. Philosophers of chemistry have especially stressed that all sciences need not be similar to physics. They have tried to argue for chemistry as its own type of science and for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Filozofia dramatu jako filozoficzna tradycja badawcza.Tadeusz Sierotowicz - 2018 - Philosophical Problems in Science 64:59-92.
    This paper presents an attempt to describe Józef Tischner’s philosophy of drama from the point of view of Larry Laudan’s philosophy of science. That is achieved with the help of the concept of Philosophical Research Traditions developed in the paper. A~certain conceptual problem of Tischner’s philosophy, and some future research topics are also presented.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Exploring students’ epistemological knowledge of models and modelling in science:results from a teaching/learning experience on climate change.Giulia Tasquier, Olivia Levrini & Justin Dillon - 2016 - International Journal of Science Education 38 (4):539-563.
    The scientific community has been debating climate change for over two decades. In the light of certain arguments put forward by the aforesaid community, the EU has recommended a set of innovative reforms to science teaching such as incorporating environmental issues into the scientific curriculum, thereby helping to make schools a place of civic education. However, despite these European recommendations, relatively little emphasis is still given to climate change within science curricula. Climate change, although potentially engaging for students, is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy of science: From justification to explanation.Aharon Kantorovich - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4):469-494.
    The paper investigates the implications of a nonaprioristic philosophy of science. It starts by developing a scheme of justification which draws its norms from the prevailing paradigm of rationality, which need not be universal or external. If the requirement for normativity is then abandoned we do not end up with a descriptive philosophy of science. The alternative to a prescriptive philosophy of science is a theoretical explanation of scientific decisions and acts. Explanation, rather than mere description, replaces justification; and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Epicyclic popperism.Errol E. Harris - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (1):55-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Reviews. [REVIEW]David Papineau - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (1):98-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causal V. Positivist Theories of Scientific Explanation: A Defense of the Causal Theory.Douglas Hans Rice - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    Three fundamental claims are defended in this dissertation. First, the influence of Hume's epistemological program and his skepticism with respect to causal knowledge have hindered the development of an adequate theory of scientific explanation. Second, Hume's conception of causal knowledge is outdated, and knowledge of causation should be relieved of the special epistemological burden placed on it by Hume's followers. Finally, once relieved of this Humean epistemological burden, the causal theory of scientific explanation is superior to alternatives lying in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Reviews. [REVIEW]Ronald Rubin - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (1):104-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Neopositivism, marxism, and idealization: Some comments on professor Nowak's paper.Peter P. Kirschenmann - 1985 - Studies in East European Thought 30 (3):219-235.
    The paper is a discussion of the idealizational interpretation of the dialectical Marxist methodology of science which has been worked out and applied in a diversity of ways by L. Nowak and the other members of the so-called Pozna school. I examine the sense in which, and the extent to which, this methodology is or can be said to be dialectical. Subsequently, I discuss and criticize Nowak's claim that this methodology can function at the same time as a meta-methodology; I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why the Realism Debate Matters for Science Policy: The Case of the Human Brain Project.Jamie Craig Owen Shaw - 2018 - Spontaneous Generations 9 (1):82-98.
    There has been a great deal of skepticism towards the value of the realism/anti-realism debate. More specifically, many have argued that plausible formulations of realism and anti-realism do not differ substantially in any way. In this paper, I argue against this trend by demonstrating how a hypothetical resolution of the debate, through deeper engagement with the historical record, has important implications for our criterion of theory pursuit and science policy. I do this by revisiting Arthur Fine’s ‘small handful’ argument for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A combined approach to the dynamics of theories.Wolfgang Stegmüller - 1978 - Theory and Decision 9 (1):39-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Duhem and the origins of statics: Ramifications of the crisis of 1903–04.R. N. D. Martin - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):337 - 355.
    Much speculation on the sources of Duhem's historical interests fails to account for the major shifts in these interests: neither his belief in the continuous development of physics nor his Catholicism, when his Church was encouraging the study of generally Aristotelian scholastic thought, led to any interest in mediaeval science before 1904. Equally, his own claim that he was merely testing his views on the nature of physical theory is easily squared only with earlier work with no trace of mediaeval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Critical Appraisal of Scientific Inquiries with Policy Implications.Giandomenico Majone & William C. Clark - 1985 - Science, Technology and Human Values 10 (3):6-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plurality of science and rational integration of knowledge.Catherine Laurent - 2012 - In Torres Juan, Pombo Olga, Symons John & Rahman Shahid (eds.), Special sciences and the Unity of Science. Springer. pp. 219--231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contemporary state of philosophy of science in Britain.Colin Howson & John Worrall - 1974 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 5 (2):363-374.
    Some of the problem areas in which British philosophers of science have recently been engaged are described and some of the major contributions noted. Two sets of problems are given special attention: one concerned with the analysis of probability statements and one concerned with the appraisal of scientific theories. Three traditions in the approach to this second set of problems are distinguished. These might be called the Carnapian, the Popperian and the Wittgensteinian traditions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science and Rationality.Ron Johnston & Julie Sheppard - 1982 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 2 (3):205-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Definite values of infinite sums: Aspects of the foundations of infinitesimal analysis around 1820.Detlef Laugwitz - 1989 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 (3):195-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations