Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Language, Truth, and Logic and the Anglophone reception of the Vienna Circle.Andreas Vrahimis - 2021 - In Adam Tamas Tuboly (ed.), The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave. pp. 41-68.
    A. J. Ayer’s Language, Truth, and Logic had been responsible for introducing the Vienna Circle’s ideas, developed within a Germanophone framework, to an Anglophone readership. Inevitably, this migration from one context to another resulted in the alteration of some of the concepts being transmitted. Such alterations have served to facilitate a number of false impressions of Logical Empiricism from which recent scholarship still tries to recover. In this paper, I will attempt to point to the ways in which LTL has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Perspectival Realist features of Ernst Mach’s critical epistemology.Pietro Gori - 2023 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 54 (1):99-124.
    This paper has a twofold aim. On the one hand, it explores the extent to which Mach was inspired by Kant’s approach to philosophical inquiry and tried to further elaborate it through his historico-critical method for enlightening scientific knowledge claims. On the other hand, it argues that the focus on the situated character of these claims that is implied in Mach’s epistemology makes it possible to compare his view to recent attempts to defend a perspectival realist account of scientific knowledge, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ernst Mach’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Science in Light of Mary B. Hesse’s Postempiricism.Pietro Gori - 2021 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 11 (2):383-411.
    Ernst Mach’s definition of the relationship between thoughts and facts is well known, but the question of how Mach conceived of their actual relationship has received much less attention. This paper aims to address this gap in light of Mary B. Hesse’s view of a postempiricist approach to natural science. As this paper will show, this view is characterized by a constructivist conception of the relationship between theory and facts that seems to be consistent with Mach’s observations on scientific knowledge. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What are the contributions of the direct perception approach?Carl B. Zuckerman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):407-408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The computational/representational paradigm as normal science: further support.Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):406-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mach, Einstein, and the rise of modern science.Elie Zahar - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (3):195-213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The material memory of history: Edgar Zilsel’s epistemology of historiography. [REVIEW]Monika Wulz - 2012 - Studies in East European Thought 64 (1-2):91-105.
    The paper focuses on the concept of matter and the material in Edgar Zilsel’s considerations about historiographical methods in the context of the Marxist debates on the materialist conception of history in the 1920s and 1930s (György Lukács, Max Adler). It sheds light on Zilsel’s understanding of matter as fluctuating, interfering processes in the lapse of time and the related concept of irreversible laws and relates it to Ernst Mach’s philosophy and to Richard Semon’s theory of mneme . Finally, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Radical Empiricism, Neutral Monism, and the Elements of Mind.Donovan Wishon - 2021 - The Monist 104 (1):125-151.
    Neutral monism is the view that both ‘mind’ and ‘matter’ are grounded in a more fundamental form of reality that is intrinsically neither mental nor material. It has often been treated as an odd fringe theory deserving of at most a footnote in the broader philosophical debates. Yet such attitudes do a grave disservice to its sophistications and significance for late nineteenth and early twentieth-century philosophy of mind and psychology. This paper sheds light on this neglected view by situating it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Percepts, intervening variables, and neural mechanisms.Wally Welker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical atomism and computation do not refute Gibson.Walter B. Welmer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of invariances and higher-order stimuli.K. von Fieandt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):404-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Musil’s Imaginary Bridge.Achille C. Varzi - 2014 - The Monist 97 (1):30-46.
    In a calculation involving imaginary numbers, we begin with real numbers that represent concrete measures and we end up with numbers that are equally real, but in the course of the operation we find ourselves walking “as if on a bridge that stands on no piles”. How is that possible? How does that work? And what is involved in the as-if stance that this metaphor introduces so beautifully? These are questions that bother Törless deeply. And that Törless is bothered by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception, information, and computation.S. Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):408-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Modern Theories of Gestalt Perception.Stephen E. Palmer - 1990 - Mind and Language 5 (4):289-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What kind of indirect process is visual perception?Aaron Sloman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):401-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mach's Denial of Absolute Time.Matias Slavov - 2023 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 40 (1):85-104.
    Mach repudiated Newton's argument for absolute time. He denied there is such a thing as time itself that exists independently of any external change. In doing so, Mach failed to appreciate Newton's scientific practice. Absolute time is intrinsically related to Newton's laws of motion and the method of fluxions. Commentators have noted similarities between Mach's rejection of Newtonian time and his rejection of the independent existence of atoms. In this article, it shall be argued that the juxtaposition of absolute time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Abstract machine theory and direct perception.Robert Shaw & James Todd - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):400-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • There is more to psychological meaningfulness than computation and representation.Sverker Runeson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):399-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Perceptual Categories Derived from Reid’s “Common Sense” Philosophy.Adam Reeves & Birgitta Dresp-Langley - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    The 18th-century Scottish ‘common sense’ philosopher Thomas Reid argued that perception can be distinguished on several dimensions from other categories of experience, such as sensation, illusion, hallucination, mental images, and what he called ‘fancy.’ We extend his approach to eleven mental categories, and discuss how these distinctions, often ignored in the empirical literature, bear on current research. We also score each category on five properties (ones abstracted from Reid) to form a 5 × 11 matrix, and thus can generate statistical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ecological Psychology and Enactivism: Perceptually-Guided Action vs. Sensation-Based Enaction1.Catherine Read & Agnes Szokolszky - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:532803.
    Ecological Psychology and Enactivism both challenge representationist cognitive science, but the two approaches have only begun to engage in dialogue. Further conceptual clarification is required in which differences are as important as common ground. This paper enters the dialogue by focusing on important differences. After a brief account of the parallel histories of Ecological Psychology and Enactivism, we cover incompatibility between them regarding their theories of sensation and perception. First, we show how and why in ecological theory perception is, crucially, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Animal-environment mutuality and direct perception.Sandra S. Prindle, Claudia Carello & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):395-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How wrong is Gibson?K. Prazdny - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):394-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Singularité et perception visuelle1.André Porto - 2012 - Philosophiques 39 (1):75-100.
    Cet article poursuit un double but : d’une part, situer dans le parcours philosophique de Wittgenstein une partie de l’histoire du « problème du champ visuel », thème clé de sa période intermédiaire ; d’autre part, mettre en lumière sa critique de l’idée d’un champ visuel (et celle de l’idée d’un objet interne). Nous croyons que ses arguments sont nouveaux, pénétrants, et ainsi leur intérêt dépasse les limites d’un exposé purement exégétique.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From Grouping to Coupling: A New Perceptual Organization in Vision, Psychology, and Biology.Baingio Pinna, Daniele Porcheddu & Katia Deiana - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Directional organization and shape formation: new illusions and Helmholtz's Square.Baingio Pinna - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Identification of Disoriented Objects: A Dual-systems Theory.Pierre Jolicoeur - 1990 - Mind and Language 5 (4):387-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Identity and Self-Knowledge.John Perry - 2017 - Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 9 (5).
    Self, person, and identity are among the concepts most central to the way humans think about themselves and others. It is often natural in biology to use such concepts; it seems sensible to say, for example, that the job of the immune system is to attack the non-self, but sometimes it attacks the self. But does it make sense to borrow these concepts? Don’t they only pertain to persons, beings with sophisticated minds, and perhaps even souls? I argue that if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ambiguous figures and representationalism.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2011 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10 (3):307-323.
    Ambiguous figures pose a problem for representationalists, particularly for representationalists who believe that the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual (MacPherson in Nous 40(1):82–117, 2006). This is because, in viewing ambiguous figures, subjects have perceptual experiences that differ in phenomenal properties without differing in non-conceptual content. In this paper, I argue that ambiguous figures pose no problem for non-conceptual representationalists. I argue that aspect shifts do not presuppose or require the possession of sophisticated conceptual resources and that, although viewing ambiguous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Philosophical objections to the kinetic theory.John Nyhof - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (1):81-109.
    Towards the end of the 19th century there were those who wished to see the kinetic theory abandoned. This paper attempts to show that this reaction was primarily due to philosophical objections rather than the result of scientific difficulties encountered by the kinetic theory. First the relevant philosophical background is examined as well as the relation between the kinetic theory and thermodynamics. Next the scientific difficulty known as the specific heats ratio anomaly is discussed and finally Boltzmann's philosophy of science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Panqualityism, Awareness and the Explanatory Gap.Jakub Mihálik - 2022 - Erkenntnis 87 (3):1423-1445.
    According to panqualityism, a form of Russellian monism defended by Sam Coleman and others, consciousness is grounded in fundamental qualities, i.e. unexperienced qualia. Despite panqualityism’s significant promise, according to David Chalmers panqualityism fails as a theory of consciousness since the reductive approach to awareness of qualities it proposes fails to account for the specific phenomenology associated with awareness. I investigate Coleman’s reasoning against this kind of phenomenology and conclude that he successfully shows that its existence is controversial, and so Chalmers’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Naturalistic methodology in an emerging scientific psychology: Lotze and fechner in the balance.Patrick McDonald - 2008 - Zygon 43 (3):605-625.
    The development of a methodologically naturalistic approach to physiological and experimental psychology in the nineteenth century was not primarily driven by a naturalistic agenda. The work of R. Hermann Lotze and G. T. Fechner help to illustrate this claim. I examine a selected set of central commitments in each thinkers philosophical outlook, particularly regarding the human soul and the nature of God, that departed strongly from a reductionist materialism. Yet, each contributed significantly to the formation of experimental and physiological psychology. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory Of Knowledge In Britain From 1860 To 1950.Mathieu Marion - 2008 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4:5.
    In 1956, a series of BBC radio talks was published in London under the title The Revolution in Philosophy . This short book included papers by prominent British philosophers of the day, such as Sir Alfred Ayer and Sir Peter Strawson, with an introduction by Gilbert Ryle. Although there is precious little in it concerning the precise nature of the ‘revolution’ alluded to in the title, it is quite clear that these lectures were meant to celebrate in an insular manner (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When analytic thought is challenged by a misunderstanding.L. Macchi & M. Bagassi - 2015 - Thinking and Reasoning 21 (1):147-164.
    In our view, the way of thinking involved in insight problem solving is very close to the process involved in the understanding of an utterance, when a misunderstanding occurs. In this case, a more appropriate meaning has to be selected to resolve the misunderstanding , the default interpretation has to be dropped in order to “restructure”, to grasp another meaning which appears more relevant to the context and the speaker's intention. A new conception of unconscious, implicit thought emerges, informed by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Perceptual activity and direct perception.William M. Mace - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):392-393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are mediating representations the ghosts in the machine?Alan K. Mackworth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ambiguous Figures and the Content of Experience.Fiona Macpherson - 2006 - Noûs 40 (1):82-117.
    Representationalism is the position that the phenomenal character of an experience is either identical with, or supervenes on, the content of that experience. Many representationalists hold that the relevant content of experience is nonconceptual. I propose a counterexample to this form of representationalism that arises from the phenomenon of Gestalt switching, which occurs when viewing ambiguous figures. First, I argue that one does not need to appeal to the conceptual content of experience or to judgements to account for Gestalt switching. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Visual perception: the shifting domain of discourse.Geoffrey R. Loftus & Elizabeth F. Loftus - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):391-392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pre-Reflective Self-Consciousness.Dorothée Legrand - 2007 - Janus Head 9 (2):493-519.
    Empirical and experiential investigations allow the distinction between observational and non-observational forms of subjective bodily experiences. From a first-person perspective, the biological body can be (1) an "opaque body" taken as an intentional object of observational consciousness, (2) a "performative body" pre-reflectively experienced as a subject/agent, (3) a "transparent body" pre-reflectively experienced as the bodily mode of givenness of objects in the external world, or (4) an "invisible body" absent from experience. It is proposed that pre-reflective bodily experiences rely on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Why argue about direct perception?J. J. Koenderink - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Direct vs. representational views of cognition: A parallel between vision and phonology.Samuel Jay Keyser & Steven Pinker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):389-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • On the nature of information in behalf of direct perception.Rebecca K. Jones & Anne D. Pick - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):388-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tachistoscopic construction of four orientations of a square.Richard M. Johnson & John Uhlarik - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 9 (5):333-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct perception and perceptual processes.Gunnar Johansson, Claes von Hofsten & Gunnar Jansson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):388-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three Kinds of Arguments for Panpsychism.Jacek Jarocki - forthcoming - Acta Analytica:1-20.
    Panpsychism may be roughly defined as a view that at least some of the properties constituting the fundamental level of reality are mental or proto-mental. Despite its long history, it has been revived in recent discussions as a solution to the problems raised by the mind, especially to the so-called hard problem of consciousness. Contemporary panpsychism differs significantly from incarnations known from the history of philosophy mainly due to the fact that the former is often combined with so-called Russellian monism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nietzsche's Positivism.Nadeem J. Z. Hussain - 2004 - European Journal of Philosophy 12 (3):326–368.
    Nietzsche’s favourable comments about science and the senses have recently been taken as evidence of naturalism. Others focus on his falsification thesis: our beliefs are falsifying interpretations of reality. Clark argues that Nietzsche eventually rejects this thesis. This article utilizes the multiple ways of being science friendly in Nietzsche’s context by focussing on Mach’s neutral monism. Mach’s positivism is a natural development of neo-Kantian positions Nietzsche was reacting to. Section 15 of Beyond Good and Evil is crucial to Clark’s interpretation. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Inferring the meaning of direct perception.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):387-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mediating the so-called immediate processes of perception.Frederick Hayes-Roth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):386-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark