Switch to: References

Citations of:

Natural deduction: a proof-theoretical study

Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications (1965)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Assumption Classes in Natural Deduction.Daniel Leivant - 1979 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 25 (1-2):1-4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Burali-Forti as a Purely Logical Paradox.Graham Leach-Krouse - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (5):885-908.
    Russell’s paradox is purely logical in the following sense: a contradiction can be formally deduced from the proposition that there is a set of all non-self-membered sets, in pure first-order logic—the first-order logical form of this proposition is inconsistent. This explains why Russell’s paradox is portable—why versions of the paradox arise in contexts unrelated to set theory, from propositions with the same logical form as the claim that there is a set of all non-self-membered sets. Burali-Forti’s paradox, like Russell’s paradox, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionist type theory and foundations.J. Lambek & P. J. Scott - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (1):101 - 115.
    A version of intuitionistic type theory is presented here in which all logical symbols are defined in terms of equality. This language is used to construct the so-called free topos with natural number object. It is argued that the free topos may be regarded as the universe of mathematics from an intuitionist's point of view.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What is wrong with classical negation?Nils Kürbis - 2015 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 92 (1):51-86.
    The focus of this paper are Dummett's meaning-theoretical arguments against classical logic based on consideration about the meaning of negation. Using Dummettian principles, I shall outline three such arguments, of increasing strength, and show that they are unsuccessful by giving responses to each argument on behalf of the classical logician. What is crucial is that in responding to these arguments a classicist need not challenge any of the basic assumptions of Dummett's outlook on the theory of meaning. In particular, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A negationless interpretation of intuitionistic theories. I.Victor N. Krivtsov - 2000 - Studia Logica 64 (1-2):323-344.
    The present work contains an axiomatic treatment of some parts of the restricted version of intuitionistic mathematics advocated by G. F. C. Griss, also known as negationless intuitionistic mathematics.Formal systems NPC, NA, and FIMN for negationless predicate logic, arithmetic, and analysis are proposed. Our Theorem 4 in Section 2 asserts the translatability of Heyting's arithmetic HAinto NA. The result can in fact be extended to a large class of intuitionistic theories based on HAand their negationless counterparts. For instance, in Section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A negationless interpretation of intuitionistic theories.Victor N. Krivtsov - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):155-179.
    In a seriesof papers beginning in 1944, the Dutch mathematician and philosopherGeorge Francois Cornelis Griss proposed that constructivemathematics should be developedwithout the use of the intuitionistic negation1 and,moreover, without any use of a nullpredicate.In the present work, we give formalized versions of intuitionisticarithmetic, analysis,and higher-order arithmetic in the spirit ofGriss' ``negationless intuitionistic mathematics''and then consider their relation to thecurrent formalizations of thesetheories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proof-Theoretic Semantics, a Problem with Negation and Prospects for Modality.Nils Kürbis - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (6):713-727.
    This paper discusses proof-theoretic semantics, the project of specifying the meanings of the logical constants in terms of rules of inference governing them. I concentrate on Michael Dummett’s and Dag Prawitz’ philosophical motivations and give precise characterisations of the crucial notions of harmony and stability, placed in the context of proving normalisation results in systems of natural deduction. I point out a problem for defining the meaning of negation in this framework and prospects for an account of the meanings of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Definite Descriptions in Intuitionist Positive Free Logic.Nils Kürbis - 2020 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 30:1.
    This paper presents rules of inference for a binary quantifier I for the formalisation of sentences containing definite descriptions within intuitionist positive free logic. I binds one variable and forms a formula from two formulas. Ix[F, G] means ‘The F is G’. The system is shown to have desirable proof-theoretic properties: it is proved that deductions in it can be brought into normal form. The discussion is rounded up by comparisons between the approach to the formalisation of definite descriptions recommended (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Normalisation and subformula property for a system of classical logic with Tarski’s rule.Nils Kürbis - 2021 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (1):105-129.
    This paper considers a formalisation of classical logic using general introduction rules and general elimination rules. It proposes a definition of ‘maximal formula’, ‘segment’ and ‘maximal segment’ suitable to the system, and gives reduction procedures for them. It is then shown that deductions in the system convert into normal form, i.e. deductions that contain neither maximal formulas nor maximal segments, and that deductions in normal form satisfy the subformula property. Tarski’s Rule is treated as a general introduction rule for implication. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Normalisation and subformula property for a system of intuitionistic logic with general introduction and elimination rules.Nils Kürbis - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):14223-14248.
    This paper studies a formalisation of intuitionistic logic by Negri and von Plato which has general introduction and elimination rules. The philosophical importance of the system is expounded. Definitions of ‘maximal formula’, ‘segment’ and ‘maximal segment’ suitable to the system are formulated and corresponding reduction procedures for maximal formulas and permutative reduction procedures for maximal segments given. Alternatives to the main method used are also considered. It is shown that deductions in the system convert into normal form and that deductions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Justification of Identity Elimination in Martin-Löf’s Type Theory.Ansten Klev - 2019 - Topoi 38 (3):577-590.
    On the basis of Martin-Löf’s meaning explanations for his type theory a detailed justification is offered of the rule of identity elimination. Brief discussions are thereafter offered of how the univalence axiom fares with respect to these meaning explanations and of some recent work on identity in type theory by Ladyman and Presnell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Harmony of Identity.Ansten Klev - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (5):867-884.
    The standard natural deduction rules for the identity predicate have seemed to some not to be harmonious. Stephen Read has suggested an alternative introduction rule that restores harmony but presupposes second-order logic. Here it will be shown that the standard rules are in fact harmonious. To this end, natural deduction will be enriched with a theory of definitional identity. This leads to a novel conception of canonical derivation, on the basis of which the identity elimination rule can be justified in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logic as instrument: the millian view on the role of logic.Ken Akiba - 1996 - History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1-2):73-83.
    I interpret Mill?s view on logic as the instrumentalist view that logical inferences, complex statements, and logical operators are not necessary for reasoning itself, but are useful only for our remembering and communicating the results of the reasoning. To defend this view, I first show that we can transform all the complex statements in the language of classical first-order logic into what I call material inference rules and reduce logical inferences to inferences which involve only atomic statements and the material (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Second-order abstract categorial grammars as hyperedge replacement grammars.Makoto Kanazawa - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (2):137-161.
    Second-order abstract categorial grammars (de Groote in Association for computational linguistics, 39th annual meeting and 10th conference of the European chapter, proceedings of the conference, pp. 148–155, 2001) and hyperedge replacement grammars (Bauderon and Courcelle in Math Syst Theory 20:83–127, 1987; Habel and Kreowski in STACS 87: 4th Annual symposium on theoretical aspects of computer science. Lecture notes in computer science, vol 247, Springer, Berlin, pp 207–219, 1987) are two natural ways of generalizing “context-free” grammar formalisms for string and tree (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computing interpolants in implicational logics.Makoto Kanazawa - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 142 (1):125-201.
    I present a new syntactical method for proving the Interpolation Theorem for the implicational fragment of intuitionistic logic and its substructural subsystems. This method, like Prawitz’s, works on natural deductions rather than sequent derivations, and, unlike existing methods, always finds a ‘strongest’ interpolant under a certain restricted but reasonable notion of what counts as an ‘interpolant’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural deduction systems for Nelson's paraconsistent logic and its neighbors.Norihiro Kamide - 2005 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 15 (4):405-435.
    Firstly, a natural deduction system in standard style is introduced for Nelson's para-consistent logic N4, and a normalization theorem is shown for this system. Secondly, a natural deduction system in sequent calculus style is introduced for N4, and a normalization theorem is shown for this system. Thirdly, a comparison between various natural deduction systems for N4 is given. Fourthly, a strong normalization theorem is shown for a natural deduction system for a sublogic of N4. Fifthly, a strong normalization theorem is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Completeness and Herbrand Theorems for Nominal Logic.James Cheney - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):299 - 320.
    Nominal logic is a variant of first-order logic in which abstract syntax with names and binding is formalized in terms of two basic operations: name-swapping and freshness. It relies on two important principles: equivariance (validity is preserved by name-swapping), and fresh name generation ("new" or fresh names can always be chosen). It is inspired by a particular class of models for abstract syntax trees involving names and binding, drawing on ideas from Fraenkel-Mostowski set theory: finite-support models in which each value (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Artificial Intelligence as a Possible Tool for Discovering Laws of Logic.David Isles - 1978 - Cognitive Science 2 (4):329-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Weak Assertion.Luca Incurvati & Julian J. Schlöder - 2019 - Philosophical Quarterly 69 (277):741-770.
    We present an inferentialist account of the epistemic modal operator might. Our starting point is the bilateralist programme. A bilateralist explains the operator not in terms of the speech act of rejection ; we explain the operator might in terms of weak assertion, a speech act whose existence we argue for on the basis of linguistic evidence. We show that our account of might provides a solution to certain well-known puzzles about the semantics of modal vocabulary whilst retaining classical logic. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A labelled natural deduction system for linear temporal logic.Andrzej Indrzejczak - 2003 - Studia Logica 75 (3):345 - 376.
    The paper is devoted to the concise description of some Natural Deduction System (ND for short) for Linear Temporal Logic. The system's distinctive feature is that it is labelled and analytical. Labels convey necessary semantic information connected with the rules for temporal functors while the analytical character of the rules lets the system work as a decision procedure. It makes it more similar to Labelled Tableau Systems than to standard Natural Deduction. In fact, our solution of linearity representation is rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Full intuitionistic linear logic.Martin Hyland & Valeria de Paiva - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 64 (3):273-291.
    In this paper we give a brief treatment of a theory of proofs for a system of Full Intuitionistic Linear Logic. This system is distinct from Classical Linear Logic, but unlike the standard Intuitionistic Linear Logic of Girard and Lafont includes the multiplicative disjunction par. This connective does have an entirely natural interpretation in a variety of categorical models of Intuitionistic Linear Logic. The main proof-theoretic problem arises from the observation of Schellinx that cut elimination fails outright for an intuitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Idempotent Variations on the Theme of Exclusive Disjunction.L. Humberstone - 2021 - Studia Logica 110 (1):121-163.
    An exclusive disjunction is true when exactly one of the disjuncts is true. In the case of the familiar binary exclusive disjunction, we have a formula occurring as the first disjunct and a formula occurring as the second disjunct, so, if what we have is two formula-tokens of the same formula-type—one formula occurring twice over, that is—the question arises as to whether, when that formula is true, to count the case as one in which exactly one of the disjuncts is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intuitionistic Logic and Elementary Rules.Lloyd Humberstone & David Makinson - 2011 - Mind 120 (480):1035-1051.
    The interplay of introduction and elimination rules for propositional connectives is often seen as suggesting a distinguished role for intuitionistic logic. We prove three formal results concerning intuitionistic propositional logic that bear on that perspective, and discuss their significance. First, for a range of connectives including both negation and the falsum, there are no classically or intuitionistically correct introduction rules. Second, irrespective of the choice of negation or the falsum as a primitive connective, classical and intuitionistic consequence satisfy exactly the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A reduction rule for Peirce formula.Sachio Hirokawa, Yuichi Komori & Izumi Takeuti - 1996 - Studia Logica 56 (3):419 - 426.
    A reduction rule is introduced as a transformation of proof figures in implicational classical logic. Proof figures are represented as typed terms in a -calculus with a new constant P (()). It is shown that all terms with the same type are equivalent with respect to -reduction augmented by this P-reduction rule. Hence all the proofs of the same implicational formula are equivalent. It is also shown that strong normalization fails for P-reduction. Weak normalization is shown for P-reduction with another (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the form of witness terms.Stefan Hetzl - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (5):529-554.
    We investigate the development of terms during cut-elimination in first-order logic and Peano arithmetic for proofs of existential formulas. The form of witness terms in cut-free proofs is characterized in terms of structured combinations of basic substitutions. Based on this result, a regular tree grammar computing witness terms is given and a class of proofs is shown to have only elementary cut-elimination.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gentzen and Jaśkowski Natural Deduction: Fundamentally Similar but Importantly Different.Allen P. Hazen & Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (6):1103-1142.
    Gentzen’s and Jaśkowski’s formulations of natural deduction are logically equivalent in the normal sense of those words. However, Gentzen’s formulation more straightforwardly lends itself both to a normalization theorem and to a theory of “meaning” for connectives . The present paper investigates cases where Jaskowski’s formulation seems better suited. These cases range from the phenomenology and epistemology of proof construction to the ways to incorporate novel logical connectives into the language. We close with a demonstration of this latter aspect by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Postponement of Reduction ad Absurdum and Glivenko’s Theorem, Revisited.Giulio Guerrieri & Alberto Naibo - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (1):109-144.
    We study how to postpone the application of the reductio ad absurdum rule (RAA) in classical natural deduction. This technique is connected with two normalization strategies for classical logic, due to Prawitz and Seldin, respectively. We introduce a variant of Seldin’s strategy for the postponement of RAA, which induces a negative translation from classical to intuitionistic and minimal logic. Through this translation, Glivenko’s theorem from classical to intuitionistic and minimal logic is proven.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Natural deduction calculi for classical and intuitionistic S5.S. Guerrini, A. Masini & M. Zorzi - 2023 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 33 (2):165-205.
    1. It is a fact that developing a good proof theory for modal logics is a difficult task. The problem is not in having deductive systems. In fact, all the main modal logics enjoy an axiomatic prese...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making Logical Form type-logical: Glue semantics for Minimalist syntax.Matthew Gotham - 2018 - Linguistics and Philosophy 41 (5):511-556.
    Glue semantics is a theory of the syntax–semantics interface according to which the syntactic structure of a sentence produces premises in a fragment of linear logic, and the semantic interpretation of the sentence correspond to the proof derivable from those premises. This paper describes how Glue can be connected to a Minimalist syntactic theory and compares the result with the more mainstream approach to the syntax–semantics interface in Minimalism, according to which the input to semantic interpretation is a syntactic structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Proof-theoretical analysis: weak systems of functions and classes.L. Gordeev - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 38 (1):1-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Proof Compression and NP Versus PSPACE.L. Gordeev & E. H. Haeusler - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (1):53-83.
    We show that arbitrary tautologies of Johansson’s minimal propositional logic are provable by “small” polynomial-size dag-like natural deductions in Prawitz’s system for minimal propositional logic. These “small” deductions arise from standard “large” tree-like inputs by horizontal dag-like compression that is obtained by merging distinct nodes labeled with identical formulas occurring in horizontal sections of deductions involved. The underlying geometric idea: if the height, h(∂), and the total number of distinct formulas, ϕ(∂), of a given tree-like deduction ∂ of a minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Axiomatic and dual systems for constructive necessity, a formally verified equivalence.Lourdes del Carmen González-Huesca, Favio E. Miranda-Perea & P. Selene Linares-Arévalo - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (3):255-287.
    We present a proof of the equivalence between two deductive systems for constructive necessity, namely an axiomatic characterisation inspired by Hakli and Negri's system of derivations from assumptions for modal logic , a Hilbert-style formalism designed to ensure the validity of the deduction theorem, and the judgmental reconstruction given by Pfenning and Davies by means of a natural deduction approach that makes a distinction between valid and true formulae, constructively. Both systems and the proof of their equivalence are formally verified (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A refutation of global scepticism.Ken Gemes - 2009 - Analysis 69 (2):218-219.
    Various possibilities, that one is dreaming, that one is being deceived by a deceitful demon, that one is a brain in the vat being stimulated to think one has a body and is in a regular world, have been invoked to show that all one's experience-based beliefs might be false. Descartes in Meditation I advises that in order not to lapse into his careless everyday view of things he, or at least his meditator, should pretend that all his experience-based beliefs, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Calculus of Natural Calculation.René Gazzari - 2021 - Studia Logica 109 (6):1375-1411.
    The calculus of Natural Calculation is introduced as an extension of Natural Deduction by proper term rules. Such term rules provide the capacity of dealing directly with terms in the calculus instead of the usual reasoning based on equations, and therefore the capacity of a natural representation of informal mathematical calculations. Basic proof theoretic results are communicated, in particular completeness and soundness of the calculus; normalisation is briefly investigated. The philosophical impact on a proof theoretic account of the notion of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Label-free natural deduction systems for intuitionistic and classical modal logics.Didier Galmiche & Yakoub Salhi - 2010 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 20 (4):373-421.
    In this paper we study natural deduction for the intuitionistic and classical (normal) modal logics obtained from the combinations of the axioms T, B, 4 and 5. In this context we introduce a new multi-contextual structure, called T-sequent, that allows to design simple labelfree natural deduction systems for these logics. After proving that they are sound and complete we show that they satisfy the normalization property and consequently the subformula property in the intuitionistic case.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pluralism in Mathematics: A New Position in Philosophy of Mathematics.Michèle Friend - 2013 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The pluralist sheds the more traditional ideas of truth and ontology. This is dangerous, because it threatens instability of the theory. To lend stability to his philosophy, the pluralist trades truth and ontology for rigour and other ‘fixtures’. Fixtures are the steady goal posts. They are the parts of a theory that stay fixed across a pair of theories, and allow us to make translations and comparisons. They can ultimately be moved, but we tend to keep them fixed temporarily. Apart (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A dialogical route to logical pluralism.Rohan French - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 20):4969-4989.
    This paper argues that adopting a particular dialogical account of logical consequence quite directly gives rise to an interesting form of logical pluralism, the form of pluralism in question arising out of the requirement that deductive proofs be explanatory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proof-theoretic semantics for a natural language fragment.Nissim Francez & Roy Dyckhoff - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (6):447-477.
    The paper presents a proof-theoretic semantics (PTS) for a fragment of natural language, providing an alternative to the traditional model-theoretic (Montagovian) semantics (MTS), whereby meanings are truth-condition (in arbitrary models). Instead, meanings are taken as derivability-conditions in a dedicated natural-deduction (ND) proof-system. This semantics is effective (algorithmically decidable), adhering to the meaning as use paradigm, not suffering from several of the criticisms formulated by philosophers of language against MTS as a theory of meaning. In particular, Dummett’s manifestation argument does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Bilateralism in Proof-Theoretic Semantics.Nissim Francez - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic (2-3):1-21.
    The paper suggests a revision of the notion of harmony, a major necessary condition in proof-theoretic semantics for a natural-deduction proof-system to qualify as meaning conferring, when moving to a bilateral proof-system. The latter considers both forces of assertion and denial as primitive, and is applied here to positive logics, lacking negation altogether. It is suggested that in addition to the balance between (positive) introduction and elimination rules traditionally imposed by harmony, a balance should be imposed also on: (i) negative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Bilateralism in Proof-Theoretic Semantics.Nissim Francez - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (2-3):239-259.
    The paper suggests a revision of the notion of harmony, a major necessary condition in proof-theoretic semantics for a natural-deduction proof-system to qualify as meaning conferring, when moving to a bilateral proof-system. The latter considers both forces of assertion and denial as primitive, and is applied here to positive logics, lacking negation altogether. It is suggested that in addition to the balance between introduction and elimination rules traditionally imposed by harmony, a balance should be imposed also on: negative introduction and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • A Logic Inspired by Natural Language: Quantifiers As Subnectors.Nissim Francez - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (6):1153-1172.
    Inspired by the grammar of natural language, the paper presents a variant of first-order logic, in which quantifiers are not sentential operators, but are used as subnectors . A quantified term formed by a subnector is an argument of a predicate. The logic is defined by means of a meaning-conferring natural-deduction proof-system, according to the proof-theoretic semantics program. The harmony of the I/E-rules is shown. The paper then presents a translation, called the Frege translation, from the defined logic to standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Brief History of Natural Deduction.Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (1):1-31.
    Natural deduction is the type of logic most familiar to current philosophers, and indeed is all that many modern philosophers know about logic. Yet natural deduction is a fairly recent innovation in logic, dating from Gentzen and Jaśkowski in 1934. This article traces the development of natural deduction from the view that these founders embraced to the widespread acceptance of the method in the 1960s. I focus especially on the different choices made by writers of elementary textbooks—the standard conduits of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Natural deduction and arbitrary objects.Kit Fine - 1985 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 14 (1):57 - 107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On the Notion of Object. A Logical Genealogy.Fernando Ferreira - 2012 - Disputatio 4 (34):609-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comments on Predicative Logic.Fernando Ferreira - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (1):1-8.
    We show how to interpret intuitionistic propositional logic into a predicative second-order intuitionistic propositional system having only the conditional and the universal second-order quantifier. We comment on this fact. We argue that it supports the legitimacy of using classical logic in a predicative setting, even though the philosophical cast of predicativism is nonrealistic. We also note that the absence of disjunction and existential quantifications allows one to have a process of normalization of proofs that avoids the use of "commuting conversions.".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A Refined Interpretation of Intuitionistic Logic by Means of Atomic Polymorphism.José Espírito Santo & Gilda Ferreira - 2020 - Studia Logica 108 (3):477-507.
    We study an alternative embedding of IPC into atomic system F whose translation of proofs is based, not on instantiation overflow, but instead on the admissibility of the elimination rules for disjunction and absurdity. As compared to the embedding based on instantiation overflow, the alternative embedding works equally well at the levels of provability and preservation of proof identity, but it produces shorter derivations and shorter simulations of reduction sequences. Lambda-terms are employed in the technical development so that the algorithmic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Inversion Principles.Enrico Moriconi & Laura Tesconi - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (2):103-113.
    The idea of an ?inversion principle?, and the name itself, originated in the work of Paul Lorenzen in the 1950s, as a method to generate new admissible rules within a certain syntactic context. Some fifteen years later, the idea was taken up by Dag Prawitz to devise a strategy of normalization for natural deduction calculi (this being an analogue of Gentzen's cut-elimination theorem for sequent calculi). Later, Prawitz used the inversion principle again, attributing it with a semantic role. Still working (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Propositions in Prepositional Logic Provable Only by Indirect Proofs.Jan Ekman - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (1):69-91.
    In this paper it is shown that addition of certain reductions to the standard cut removing reductions of deductions in prepositional logic makes prepositional logic non-normalizable. From this follows that some provable propositions in prepositional logic has no direct proof.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Cut-elimination and a permutation-free sequent calculus for intuitionistic logic.Roy Dyckhoff & Luis Pinto - 1998 - Studia Logica 60 (1):107-118.
    We describe a sequent calculus, based on work of Herbelin, of which the cut-free derivations are in 1-1 correspondence with the normal natural deduction proofs of intuitionistic logic. We present a simple proof of Herbelin's strong cut-elimination theorem for the calculus, using the recursive path ordering theorem of Dershowitz.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Feasibility In Logic.Jacques Dubucs - 2002 - Synthese 132 (3):213-237.
    The paper is a defense of a strict form of anti-realism, competing the "in principle" form defended by Michael Dummett. It proposes to ground anti-realism on the basis of two principles ("immanence" and "implicitness") and to develop the consequences of these principles in the light of sub-structural logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations