Switch to: References

Citations of:

Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity

New York: Cambridge University Press (1989)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. "El inmortal" de Jorge Luis Borges: El yo, aleph absolutos Y vocabularios finales.Jorge R. Sagastume - 2011 - Revista de filosofía (Chile) 67:269-289.
    Una obra frecuentemente consultada por Jorge Luis Borges fue Matemáticas e imaginación, de E. Kasner y J. Newman, en la que se discute la teoría de los conjuntos , propuesta por el matemático Georg Cantor , y mediante la cual se crea la aritmética transifinita y se establece un sistema epistémico para representar los diversos niveles del infinito. Así, Cantor le asigna a estas infinitudes la primera letra del alfabeto hebreo, el Aleph, seguido de un determinado número, dependiendo del nivel (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transcendental constraints and transcendental features.Mark Sacks - 1997 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (2):164 – 186.
    Transcendental idealism has been conceived of in philosophy as a position that aims to secure objectivity without traditional metaphysical underpinnings. This article contrasts two forms of transcendental idealism that have been identified: one in the work of Kant, the other in the later Wittgenstein. The distinction between these two positions is clarified by means of a distinction between transcendental constraints and transcendental features. It is argued that these conceptions provide the - fundamentally different - bases of the two positions under (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rorty’s Aversion to Normative Violence: The Myth of the Given and the Death of God.Carl B. Sachs - 2017 - Contemporary Pragmatism 14 (3):277-291.
    Among the deeper strata of Rorty’s philosophy is what I call his aversion to normative violence. Normative violence occurs when some specific group presents itself as having a privileged relation to reality. The alternative to normative violence is recognizing that cultural politics has priority over ontology. I trace this Rortyan idea to its origins in Nietzsche and Sellars. Rorty’s contribution is to combine Nietzsche on the death of God and Sellars on the Myth of the Given. However, I conclude with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rorty's Debt to Sellarsian Metaphysics.Carl B. Sachs - 2013 - Metaphilosophy 44 (5):682-707.
    Rorty regards himself as furthering the project of the Enlightenment by separating Enlightenment liberalism from Enlightenment rationalism. To do so, he rejects the very need for explicit metaphysical theorizing. Yet his commitments to naturalism, nominalism, and the irreducibility of the normative come from the metaphysics of Wilfrid Sellars. Rorty's debt to Sellars is concealed by his use of Davidsonian arguments against the scheme/content distinction and the nonsemantic concept of truth. The Davidsonian arguments are used for Deweyan ends: to advance secularization (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ethics of ambiguity and irony: Jacques Derrida and Richard Rorty.Honglim Ryu - 2001 - Human Studies 24 (1-2):5-28.
    This paper examines the relation or, more precisely, tension between postmodern deconstruction and ethics by elaborating upon the ethico-political dimensions of deconstructionism. It embarks on a critical assessment of postmodern discourse on ethics in view of its political implications by analyzing Jacques Derrida''s and Richard Rorty''s arguments with an assumption that their positions represent a certain logic in the postmodern discourse on ethics. Postmodern ethics is based on incredulity with regard to traditional metanarratives, and it defines ethics in terms of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Narrative and Rhetorical Approaches to Problems of Education. Jerome Bruner and Kenneth Burke Revisited.Kris Rutten & Ronald Soetaert - 2012 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 32 (4):327-343.
    Over the last few decades there has been a strong narrative turn within the humanities and social sciences in general and educational studies in particular. Especially Jerome Bruner’s theory of narrative as a specific ‘mode of knowing’ was very important for this growing body of work. To understand how the narrative mode works Bruner proposes to study narratives ‘at their far reach’—as an art form—and on several occasions he refers to the dramatistic pentad as an important method for ‘unpacking’ narratives. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Rhetoric of Turns: Signs and Symbols in Education.Kris Rutten & Ronald Soetaert - 2014 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 48 (4):604-620.
    In our research and teaching we explore the value and the place of rhetoric in education. From a theoretical perspective we situate our work in different disciplines, inspired by major ‘turns’: linguistic, cultural, anthropological/ethnographic, interpretive, semiotic, narrative, literary, rhetorical etc. In this article we engage in the discussion about what all these turns might entail for education by elaborating on what it implies to read the world as a ‘text'—as is central in a semiotic approach—and by introducing new rhetoric in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language games and natural reactions.David Rubinstein - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (1):55–71.
    Ludwig Wittgenstein imagines a variety of eccentric social practices—like a tribe trained “to give no expression of feeling of any kind”. But he also speaks of “the common behavior of mankind” that is rooted in “natural/primitive reactions”. This emphasis on the uniformities of human behavior raises questions about the plausibility of some of his imagined language games. Indeed, it suggests the claim of evolutionary psychologists that there are biologically based human universals that shape social practices. But in contrast to E.O. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Jörg Rössel, David Lambourn & Daniel Guinea - 2002 - European Journal of Social Theory 5 (3):367-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Signs, deixis, and the emergence of scientific explanation.Wolff-Michael Roth & Daniel V. Lawless - 2002 - Semiotica 2002 (138).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Quo Vadis? Quine’s Web, Kuhn’s Revolutions, and Baert’s “Way Forward”: Patrick Baert, Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Towards Pragmatism. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2005.Paul A. Roth - 2009 - Human Studies 32 (3):357-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific innovation and the limits of social scientific prediction.Alex Rosenberg - 1993 - Synthese 97 (2):161 - 181.
    Philosophers and historians of philosophy have come to recognize that at the core of logical positivism was an attachment to prediction as the necessary condition for scientific knowledge.1 The inheritors of their tradition, especially the Bayesians among us, continue to seek a theory of confirmation that reflects this epistemic commitment. The importance of prediction in the growth of scientific knowledge is a commitment I share with the positivists, so I do not blanch at that designation, much less employ it as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Richard Rorty on the American Left in the Era of Trump.David Rondel - 2018 - Contemporary Pragmatism 15 (2):194-210.
    This paper revisits some of the arguments in Richard Rorty’s Achieving Our Country, twenty years after the book first appeared. Not only are many of Rorty’s diagnoses and predictions eerily prescient in the wake of the rise of Donald Trump to the US presidency, but there is also perceptive political advice in Rorty’s book that I argue the contemporary American Left would do well to heed. While many post-election commentators have tended to read Achieving Our Country as an admonishment of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Rorty's Evangelical Metaphilosophy.David Rondel - 2011 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 44 (2):150-170.
    I have spent 40 years looking for a coherent and convincing way of formulating my worries about what, if anything, philosophy is good for. Richard Rorty had an unusually avid interest in metaphilosophy. Again and again he would return to questions about the practical uses (if any) to which philosophy might be put, about philosophy's role in intellectual culture, about what philosophy is or might become. His answers to these questions were famously negative: philosophy's practical uses are few, its cultural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pragmatist Egalitarianism Revisited: Some Replies to my Critics.David Rondel - 2019 - Contemporary Pragmatism 16 (4):337-347.
    In this article, I reply to some criticisms of my book, Pragmatist Egalitarianism, offered by professors Robert Talisse, Susan Dieleman, and Alexander Livingston. Some of the major themes and questions I address include the following: How are conflicts between different egalitarian ideals best understood and addressed? Does the quest for equality have a fundamental locus, or are the different egalitarian variables I identify in the book, conceptually speaking, on an equal footing? What is the relationship between justice and equality? How (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Appraising Justice as Larger Loyalty.David Rondel - 2015 - Contemporary Pragmatism 12 (2):302-316.
    This paper critically examines Richard Rorty’s “justice as larger loyalty” proposal. While Rorty is right, I argue, to reject the Kantian idea of a strict bifurcation between justice and loyalty, the former corresponding to reason the latter corresponding to sentiment, my argument is that it is nevertheless a mistake to follow Rorty in conceiving of justice as he recommends we should. This is not an endorsement of the rationalistic Kantian view Rorty rejects. Rather, I argue that there are compelling Rortyan (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The compassion deficit and what to do about it: a response to P aley.Gary Rolfe & Lyn D. Gardner - 2014 - Nursing Philosophy 15 (4):288-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Stranger Within: Dostoevsky’s underground.Peter Roberts - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (4):396-408.
    In Fyodor Dostoevsky’s influential novel Notes from underground, we find one of the most memorable characters in nineteenth century literature. The Underground Man, around whom everything else in this book revolves, is in some respects utterly repugnant: he is self-centred, obsessive and cruel. Yet he is also highly intelligent, honest and reflective, and he has suffered significantly at the hands of others. Reading Notes from underground can be a harrowing experience but also an educative one, for in an encounter with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Making and Remaking of Sport Actions.Terence J. Roberts - 1992 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 19 (1):15-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Sport and Strong Poetry.Terence J. Roberts - 1995 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 22 (1):94-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • On weak postpositivism: Ahistorical rejections of the view from nowhere.Robert C. Scharff - 2007 - Metaphilosophy 38 (4):509-534.
    Postpositivists have lately joined post‐Husserlians in arguing that the deepest problem with Descartes' legacy is that it fosters the objectivist illusion that philosophers might actually come to think “from Nowhere,” or at least that they can self‐consciously choose whatever presuppositions they do accept. Yet this argument is easier to express than to incorporate into one's own thinking. It is perfectly possible to oppose the View from Nowhere, and even to criticize others for failing to understand its impossibility, and still do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language, Truth, Justice, and Sporting Practice.Terence J. Roberts - 2001 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 28 (2):215-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “It's Just Not Cricket!” Rorty and Unfamiliar Movements: History of Metaphors In a Sporting Practice.Terence J. Roberts - 1997 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 24 (1):67-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • If our genes are for us, who can be against us? Thoughts of a pragmatist on science and morality.J. Wesley Robbins - 1995 - Zygon 30 (3):357-367.
    The philosopher Michael Ruse accounts for the difference between hypothetical and categorical imperatives, and thus the origin of distinctively moral obligations like that of altruism, in genetic terms. This is part of an attempt to develop a philosophy that takes Darwin seriously by substituting respectable scientific entities, specifically those of evolutionary biology, for suspect theological or philosophical ones, like God or the transcendental ego, as a basis for addressing philosophical questions. Pragmatists take Darwin seriously, but in a very different way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A neopragmatist perspective on religion and science.J. Wesley Robbins - 1993 - Zygon 28 (3):337-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Agnes Heller: Politics and Philosophy.Ángel Rivero - 1999 - Thesis Eleven 59 (1):17-28.
    The article tracks the development of Agnes Heller”s political philosophy as it evolves through the Marxism and reform communism of her years as a dissent Hungarian intellectual, followed by the period of her encounters with the Western Left and with the currents of postmodern liberalism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is historicism?Andrew Reynolds - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (3):275 – 287.
    “Historicism” has become a ubiquitous and equivocal term. A classification is given here of five separate uses of the term currently in vogue, each provided with a unique qualifying adjective to help keep them distinct. I then offer a few objections to some of the more radical conclusions which have been drawn by proponents of a specific version of historicism, one associated with “postmodernism “. The positions of Rorty and Putnam are contrasted as examples of strong and weak degrees of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liberal irony, rhetoric, and feminist thought: A unifying third wave feminist theory.Valerie R. Renegar & Stacey K. Sowards - 2003 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 36 (4):330-352.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Rhetoric 36.4 (2003) 330-352 [Access article in PDF] Liberal Irony, Rhetoric, and Feminist Thought: A Unifying Third Wave Feminist Theory Valerie R. Renegar School of Communication San Diego State University Stacey K. Sowards Department of Communication Studies California State University, San Bernardino The meanings of a feminist movement and feminism have changed significantly over the past hundred years. From the women's suffrage movement, to the Supreme Court (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contradiction as Agency: Self-Determination, Transcendence, and Counter-Imagination in Third Wave Feminism.Valerie R. Renegar & Stacey K. Sowards - 2009 - Hypatia 24 (2):1 - 20.
    This essay examines the contradictions often found in third wave feminist texts that function as strategic choices that may shape, foster, and enhance an individual's sense of agency. Many third wave feminists utilize contradiction as a way to understand emergent identities, to develop new ways of thinking, and to imagine new forms of social action. Agency, then, stems from the use of contradiction as a means of self-determination and identity, of transcendence of seemingly forced or dichotomous choices, and counter-imaginations of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of solidarity in social responsibility for health.Massimo Reichlin - 2011 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14 (4):365-370.
    The Article focuses on the concept of social solidarity, as it is used in the Report of the International Bioethics Committee On Social Responsibility and Health. It is argued that solidarity plays a major role in supporting the whole framework of social responsibility, as presented by the IBC. Moreover, solidarity is not limited to members of particular groups, but potentially extended to all human beings on the basis of their inherent dignity; this sense of human solidarity is a necessary presupposition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Ethical Imperative of Medical Humanities.Geoffrey Rees - 2010 - Journal of Medical Humanities 31 (4):267-277.
    Medical humanities purchases its presence on the medical side of university campuses by adopting as its own the ends of medicine and medical ethics. It even justifies its presence by asserting promotion of those ends as an ethical imperative, most of all to improve the caring in medical care. As unobjectionable, even praiseworthy, as this imperative appears, it actually constrains the possibilities for interpersonal relationship in the context of medical practice. Development of those possibilities requires openness of self to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Property rights, genes, and common good.Esther D. Reed - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (1):41-67.
    This paper applies aspects of Hugo Grotius's theologically informed theory of property to contemporary issues concerning access to the human DNA sequence and patenting practices. It argues that Christians who contribute to public debate in these areas might beneficially employ some of the concepts with which he worked--notably "common right," the "right of necessity," and "use right." In the seventeenth century, wars were fought over trading rights and access to the sea. In the twenty-first century, information and intellectual property are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a Theory of Social Practices: A Development in Culturalist Theorizing.Andreas Reckwitz - 2002 - European Journal of Social Theory 5 (2):243-263.
    This article works out the main characteristics of `practice theory', a type of social theory which has been sketched by such authors as Bourdieu, Giddens, Taylor, late Foucault and others. Practice theory is presented as a conceptual alternative to other forms of social and cultural theory, above all to culturalist mentalism, textualism and intersubjectivism. The article shows how practice theory and the three other cultural-theoretical vocabularies differ in their localization of the social and in their conceptualization of the body, mind, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The Naming of Evil: Sovereignty, Security and Unlawful Warfare.Walter Rech - 2022 - Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 54.
    Nombrar al mal: soberanía, seguridad y guerra ilegal Este artículo defiende la importancia fundamental del "nombrar al mal" como operación constitutiva del discurso político moderno. Para lograr este objetivo, el artículo llama primero la atención sobre cómo los discursos institucionales y públicos globales, y aparentemente consensuados, han definido al Estado Islámico de Irak y Siria como una forma contemporánea del "mal" y cómo la comunidad internacional ha concebido su posicionamiento de cara a esta entidad. Basándose en este análisis y en (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critique and social movements: Looking beyond contingency and normativity.Paola Rebughini - 2010 - European Journal of Social Theory 13 (4):459-479.
    This article aims to confront the principal arguments of the concept of critique in sociology and to demonstrate the emergence in recent years of a re-dimensioned conception of critique, on the one hand, of a pragmatic, pluralistic and contingent nature, and, on the other, show how the need for a strong and transcendental concept of critique that does not renounce the possibility of individual and collective emancipation is still present. This article argues that the analytic and empirical space in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ryle revisited: The dispositional model fifty years after.Grazia Melilli Ramoino - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (1):89 – 119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Obama’s Pragmatism in International Affairs.Shane J. Ralston - 2011 - Contemporary Pragmatism 8 (2):81-98.
    What is pragmatism's contribution, actual or potential, to contemporary International Relations theory and practice? Is there hope for constructing a pragmatist theory of International Relations? The author of this article takes up these questions by considering whether Barack Obama is a pragmatist in his handling of issues in international affairs. By examining a series of Obama speeches, the author teases out the raw material for a pragmatist theory of International Relations, demonstrating how the pragmatic practice of international diplomacy can inform (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conversations, conferences, and the practice of intellectual discussion.Gary Radford - 2000 - Human Studies 23 (3):211-225.
    This paper analyzes a conference panel discussion entitled "Identity in Crisis: The Issue of Agency in Social Constructionism and Postmodernism" in order to identify some limits to intellectual discussion. The panel participants made a deliberate attempt to engage in a self-reflexive language game about the language game of intellectual discussion in the conference format. This attempt revealed the highly sedimented nature of discursive practice in the conference setting, at least, and perhaps more generally. This analysis of the extent to which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Economism, pragmatism and pedagogy.J. Kevin Quinn & M. Neil Browne - 1998 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 30 (2):163–173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Literature, Ethics, and Richard Rorty’s Pragmatist Theory of Interpretation.Kalle Puolakka - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (1):29-41.
    This article considers the validity and strength of Richard Rorty’s pragmatist theory of interpretation in the light of two ethical issues related to literature and interpretation. Rorty’s theory is rejected on two grounds. First, it is argued that his unrestrained account of interpretation is incompatible with the distinctive moral concerns that have been seen to restrict the scope and nature of valid approaches to artworks. The second part of the paper claims that there is no indispensable relationship between supporting Rorty’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who wants to live forever? Immortality, authenticity, and living forever in the present.Ted M. Preston & Scott Dixon - 2007 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 61 (2):99-117.
    Death is a bad thing by virtue of its ability to frustrate the subjectively valuable projects that shape our identities and render our lives meaningful. While the presumption that immortality would necessarily result in boredom worse than death proves unwarranted, if the constraint of mortality is a necessary element for virtues, relationships, and motivation to pursue our life-projects, then death might nevertheless be a necessary evil. Mortal or immortal, it’s clear that the value of one’s life depends on its subjectively (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Quality and Legitimacy of Green Narratives in Business: A Framework for Evaluation.Lutz Preuss & David Dawson - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 84 (S1):135 - 149.
    Narrative is increasingly being recognised as an important tool both to manage and understand organisations. In particular, narrative is recognised to have an important influence on the perception of environmental issues in business, a particularly contested area of modern management. Management literature is, however, only beginning to develop a framework for evaluating the quality and legitimacy of narratives. Due to the highly fluid nature of narratives, the traditional notion of truth as reflecting ' objective reality' is not useful here. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Thinking ethical and regulatory frameworks in medicine from the perspective of solidarity on both sides of the Atlantic.Barbara Prainsack & Alena Buyx - 2016 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37 (6):489-501.
    This article provides a concise overview of the history of scholarship on solidarity in Europe and North America. While recent decades have seen an increase in conceptual and scholarly interest in solidarity in North America and other parts of the Anglo-Saxon world, the concept is much more strongly anchored in Europe. Continental European politics in particular have given rise to two of the most influential traditions of solidarity, namely, socialism and Christian ethics. Solidarity has also guided important public instruments and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Richard Rorty's politics.Richard A. Posner - 1993 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 7 (1):33-49.
    The training and experience of such academic philosophers as Richard Rorty and Hilary Putnam do not equip them with the economic and other social‐scientific tools necessary to make useful contributions to political discussion. In the case of Rorty, this has resulted in his being unable to make effective ripostes to left‐wing critics of his defense of “bourgeois liberalism,” his uncritical endorsement of simplistic arguments for social reform, and his embrace of false prophecies of doom, such as those found in Orwell's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ethical Room for Maneuver: Playground for the Food Business.Vincent Pompe & Michiel Korthals - 2010 - Business and Society Review 115 (3):367-391.
    In a world of glossy corporate social responsibility reports, the shallowness of the actual CSR results may well be its counterpart. We claim that the possible gaps between aspirations and implementations are due to the company's overrating abilities to deal with the irrational and complex moral world of business. Many academic approaches aim to lift business ethics up to a higher level by enhancing competences but will fail because they are too rationalistic and generalistic to match the pluralistic and situational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From Psychologism to Personhood: Honneth, Recognition, and the Making of Persons.Renante D. Pilapil - 2012 - Res Publica 18 (1):39-51.
    The paper explores the philosophical anthropology and the moral grammar of recognition. It does so by examining how the formation of the self is informed by social recognition, the result of which can motivate individuals and groups to engage in struggles for recognition. To pursue this task, the discussion focuses on the insights of Honneth, who grounds his theory of recognition in the intersubjective relations between persons. The idea that recognition impacts the formation of personal identity is regarded as susceptible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Neopragmatism and the Christian Desire for a Transcendent God.Hendrik R. Pieterse - 2002 - Essays in Philosophy 3 (2):177-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rhetoric of modern economics.Mirowski Philip - 1990 - History of the Human Sciences 3 (2):243-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and post‐analytic philosophy of education: Rorty or Lyotard?Michael Peters - 1997 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 29 (2):1–32.
    (1997). Wittgenstein and post‐analytic philosophy of education: Rorty or Lyotard? Educational Philosophy and Theory: Vol. 29, No. 2, pp. 1-32. doi: 10.1111/j.1469-5812.1997.tb00018.x.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Social philosophy: A reconstructive or deconstructive discipline?Jørgen Pedersen - 2012 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 38 (6):619-643.
    Social philosophy is a somewhat broad and imprecise term. In this article I discuss the social philosophy of Habermas, Foucault and Honneth, arguing that the latter’s work is an interesting, but not unproblematic, conception of the discipline. Following Habermas and Honneth, I argue that social philosophy should be reconstructive, but incorporate insights from Foucault. Specifically, reconstructive social philosophy can be both normative and descriptive, and at the same time establish a dialectical relationship between philosophy and the social sciences, thus fulfilling (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation