Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. O besouro na caixa de Skinner.Luiza Bacchi Dourado, Carlos Eduardo Lopes & Henrique Mesquita Pompermaier - 2021 - Psicologia: Teoria E Pesquisa 37:e37 221.
    The literature has indicated some approximations between Skinner’s and Wittgenstein’s proposals, such as a critical standpoint on traditional psychological language conceptions. For Wittgenstein, the critique refers to the impossibility of a private language. On the other hand, Skinner’s critique culminates in defense of the concept of private events. However, this concept seems inconsistent with Wittgenstein’s proposal. Based on this assumption, this paper aims to reevaluate the role of the concept of ‘private events’ in Skinnerian behaviorism in the light of Wittgenstein’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Intellectual Disability Poses a Challenge to the Received View of Capacity and a Potential Response.Abraham Graber & Andy Kreusel - 2022 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 47 (1):117-136.
    While copious quantities of ink have been spilled on the topic of autonomy in the context of health care, little has been written about autonomy in relation to intellectual disability. After presenting the received account of capacity, we argue that it cannot account for the moral permissibility of limiting an individual with intellectual disability’s access to diet soda. In cases of preventative medicine and intellectual disability, the philosophical motivation for the received account of capacity is incompatible with the actions it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitivismos y conductismos.Sergio Barrera Rodríguez & Gerardo Gabriel Primero - 2020 - Scientia in Verba Magazine 6 (1):17-46.
    En este texto se elabora un análisis historiográfico, filosófico y teórico en torno a diversas propuestas de caracterización, demarcación, y explicación de la conducta y la cognición. Asimismo, se construyen argumentos para favorecer una comprensión más integral y elaborada de los programas de investigación acerca de la conducta y la cognición. Con este fin, en la primera sección analizaremos y cuestionaremos tres mitos acerca de la historia de la psicología: la tesis de los paradigmas hegemónicos y los reemplazos revolucionarios, la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Rise and Fall of Behaviorism: The Narrative and the Numbers.Michiel Braat, Jan Engelen, Ties van Gemert & Sander Verhaegh - 2020 - History of Psychology 23 (3):1-29.
    The history of twentieth-century American psychology is often depicted as a history of the rise and fall of behaviorism. Although historians disagree about the theoretical and social factors that have contributed to the development of experimental psychology, there is widespread consensus about the growing and declining influence of behaviorism between approximately 1920 and 1970. Since such wide-scope claims about the development of American psychology are typically based on small and unrepresentative samples of historical data, however, the question rises to what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The intuitive mind.Geir Overskeid - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):414-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What manner of mind is this?Arthur S. Reber & Bill Winter - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):418-419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criteria for implicit learning: Deemphasize conscious access, emphasize amnesia.Carol Augart Seger - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):421-422.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mental States Are Like Diseases.Sander Verhaegh - 2019 - In Robert Sinclair (ed.), Science and Sensibilia by W. V. Quine: The 1980 Immanuel Kant Lectures. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.
    While Quine’s linguistic behaviorism is well-known, his Kant Lectures contain one of his most detailed discussions of behaviorism in psychology and the philosophy of mind. Quine clarifies the nature of his psychological commitments by arguing for a modest view that is against ‘excessively restrictive’ variants of behaviorism while maintaining ‘a good measure of behaviorist discipline…to keep [our mental] terms under control’. In this paper, I use Quine’s Kant Lectures to reconstruct his position. I distinguish three types of behaviorism in psychology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Towards a New Theory of Vision” Revisited.Jan Koenderink - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):571-581.
    I consider the geometrical structure of the apparent visual field. Although the optics of vision is well understood, the nature of visual awareness remains largely in the dark. A famous attempt at a formal description of the apparent visual field was by Helmholtz, in the late nineteenth century. It purportedly explains the phenomenon of the subjective curvatures often reported when viewing objectively straight lines of great extent. I consider the general problem, and suggest an alternative formal account. On phenomenological grounds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A step too far?Dianne C. Berry - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some thoughts on the proper foundations for the study of cognition in animals.Lynn Nadel - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):383-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • In the beginning was the word.J. E. R. Staddon - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difference without discontinuity.Max Hocutt - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):651-651.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The cost of an interrupted response pattern.Thomas R. Zentall - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Suspicion,” “fear,” “contamination,” “great dangers,” and behavioral fictions.Charles P. Shimp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):715-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is it behaviorism?B. F. Skinner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):716-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alternatives to radical behaviorism.Terry L. Smith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):143-144.
    Operant psychologists are looking for alternatives to radical behaviorism. Rachlin offers teleological behaviorism, but it may pose as many difficulties as radical behaviorism. There is, however, a less drastic way to defend Rachlin's thesis of It portrays operant principles as relating distal efficient causes to behavioral effects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • My behavior made me do it: The uncaused cause of teleological behaviorism.Jordan Hughes & Patricia S. Churchland - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):130-131.
    Toward a neurobiologically grounded approach to explaining self-control we discuss the case of a patient with a bilateral lesion in frontal ventromedial cortex. Patients with such lesions display a marked deficit in social decision making. Compared with an account that examines the causal antecedents of self-control, Rachlin's behaviorist approach seems lacking in explanatory strength.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-control: Acts of free will.James A. Schirillo - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):141-141.
    Rachlin overlooks that free will determines when and in what direction acts that appear impulsive will occur. Because behavioral patterns continuously evolve, animals are not guaranteed when they will, or how to, maximize larger-later reinforcements. An animal therefore uses self-control to emit free acts to vary behavioral patterns to optimize larger-later rewards.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there always a neurochemical link between pain and behavior?G. Pepeu - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):69-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why the Radical Behaviorist Conception of Private Events Is Interesting, Relevant, and Important.Jay Moore - 2009 - Behavior and Philosophy 37:21 - 37.
    For radical behaviorists, talk about "private events" could be about any of four things: (a) private behavioral events, (b) physiology, (c) dispositions, or (d) explanatory fictions. Talk about private events as behavioral engages the influence of feelings, sensations, and covert opérant behavior. Analyses based on private behavioral events allow radical behaviorists to understand how those events contribute to contingencies controlling subsequent operant behavior, whether verbal or nonverbal. Talk about private events in physiological terms risks confounding explanatory categories. Although physiology necessarily (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Feminist Philosophy of Science.Lynn Hankinson Nelson - 2002 - In Peter Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 312–331.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Highlights of Past Literature Current Work Future Work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Some Further Thoughts on the Pragmatic and Behavioral Conception of Private Events.J. Moore - 2003 - Behavior and Philosophy 31:151 - 157.
    For behavior analysis, ontological concerns are linked with pragmatism, rather than any stance on the inherent nature of the thing studied. Thus, behavior analysis regards as troublesome ontological commitments that formulate certain covert events as "mental" rather than behavioral because those commitments are antithetical to the effective prediction and control of natural phenomena. Moreover, a helpful recognition is that neither behavior nor environment need be publicly observable. Rather, they may be accessible to only one, but nevertheless in the behavioral dimension.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The unreliability of naive introspection.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2006 - Philosophical Review 117 (2):245-273.
    We are prone to gross error, even in favorable circumstances of extended reflection, about our own ongoing conscious experience, our current phenomenology. Even in this apparently privileged domain, our self-knowledge is faulty and untrustworthy. We are not simply fallible at the margins but broadly inept. Examples highlighted in this essay include: emotional experience (for example, is it entirely bodily; does joy have a common, distinctive phenomenological core?), peripheral vision (how broad and stable is the region of visual clarity?), and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   269 citations  
  • (1 other version)Characteristics of dissociable human learning systems.David R. Shanks & Mark F. St John - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):367-447.
    A number of ways of taxonomizing human learning have been proposed. We examine the evidence for one such proposal, namely, that there exist independent explicit and implicit learning systems. This combines two further distinctions, (1) between learning that takes place with versus without concurrent awareness, and (2) between learning that involves the encoding of instances (or fragments) versus the induction of abstract rules or hypotheses. Implicit learning is assumed to involve unconscious rule learning. We examine the evidence for implicit learning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • The brain's 'new' science: Psychology, neurophysiology, and constraint.Gary Hatfield - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):388-404.
    There is a strong philosophical intuition that direct study of the brain can and will constrain the development of psychological theory. When this intuition is tested against case studies on the neurophysiology and psychology of perception and memory, it turns out that psychology has led the way toward knowledge of neurophysiology. An abstract argument is developed to show that psychology can and must lead the way in neuroscientific study of mental function. The opposing intuition is based on mainly weak arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Dissociating multiple memory systems: Don't forsake the brain.Mark G. Packard - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):414-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A promissory note is paid, but has this bought into an illusion?Philip N. Hineline - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):650-651.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What defines a legitimate issue for Skinnerian psychology: Philosophy or technology?Hank Davis - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):137-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The intellectual origins of Rational Psychotherapy.Arthur Still & Windy Dryden - 1998 - History of the Human Sciences 11 (3):63-86.
    In this paper we attempt to understand the intellectual origins of Albert Ellis' Rational Psychotherapy (now known as Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy). In his therapeutic practice Ellis used a 'lumper' argument to replace the focus of change in psychoanalysis: not the lengthy uncovering and reworking of the individual's personal history, but the demands in self-talk through which the client is currently dis turbed. In constructing around this the persuasive (rhetorical) package that became his therapy, Ellis drew on a number of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Not “pain and behavior” but pain in behavior.Patrick D. Wall - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):73-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Skinner e uma crítica a Freud: apresentação e considerações.Marcos Rodrigues da Silva & Lucas Roberto Pedrão Paulino - 2011 - Natureza Humana 13 (2):144-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptualizing Self-Control.Alfred Mele - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):136-137.
    A pair of arguments suggests that self-control is not properly conceptualized on the pattern/act/preference model Rachlin proposes. The first concerns the irrational following of personal rules. The second concerns scenarios in which behavioral patterns an agent deems good come into conflict.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Facts, Concepts, and Theories: The Shape of Psychology's Epistemic Triangle.Armando Machado, Orlando Lourenço & Francisco J. Silva - 2000 - Behavior and Philosophy 28 (1/2):1 - 40.
    In this essay we introduce the idea of an epistemic triangle, with factual, theoretical, and conceptual investigations at its vertices, and argue that whereas scientific progress requires a balance among the three types of investigations, psychology's epistemic triangle is stretched disproportionately in the direction of factual investigations. Expressed by a variety of different problems, this unbalance may be created by a main operative theme—the obsession of psychology with a narrow and mechanical view of the scientific method and a misguided aversion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unificationism: Philosophy for the modern disunified science of psychology.Arthur W. Staats - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):143-164.
    Abstract Psychology's goal has been to become a science, taking the modern natural sciences as the model. It has not been understood that each science undergoes a transition from early disunification to later unification, that a fundmental dimension is involved that differentiates sciences. Psychology is a modern disunified science, distinguished by its chaotic knowledge and ways of operating. A philosophy of science based on modem unified science, as philosophies generally are, is inappropriate as a means of understanding psychology or of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pain and behavior.Howard Rachlin - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):43-83.
    There seem to be two kinds of pain: fundamental pain, the intensity of which is a direct function of the intensity of various pain stimuli, and pain, the intensity of which is highly modifiable by such factors as hypnotism, placebos, and the sociocultural setting in which the stimulus occurs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • Learning without awareness: What counts as an appropriate test of learning and of awareness.Sam S. Rakover - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):417-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning to modulate one's own brain activity: the effect of spontaneous mental strategies.Silvia E. Kober, Matthias Witte, Manuel Ninaus, Christa Neuper & Guilherme Wood - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Is implicit learning about consciousness?Richard A. Carlson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):400-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations and cognition.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):394-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind the brain.Martha Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive psychology's representation of behaviorism.A. W. Logue - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):381-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The reconstruction of a conceptual reconstruction.Leonard Krasner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):708-709.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The gentrification of behaviorism.Roger Schnaitter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):714-715.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Viewing behaviorism selectively.A. Charles Catania - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):701-702.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical principles of reinforcement.Peter R. Killeen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):105-135.
    Effective conditioning requires a correlation between the experimenter's definition of a response and an organism's, but an animal's perception of its behavior differs from ours. These experiments explore various definitions of the response, using the slopes of learning curves to infer which comes closest to the organism's definition. The resulting exponentially weighted moving average provides a model of memory that is used to ground a quantitative theory of reinforcement. The theory assumes that: incentives excite behavior and focus the excitement on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Persistence of Category Mistakes in Psychology.Per Holth - 2001 - Behavior and Philosophy 29:203 - 219.
    Gilbert Ryle's book The Concept of Mind was published in 1949. According to Ryle, his "destructive purpose" was to show that "a family of radical category mistakes" is the source of the "official doctrine," that is, a "double-life theory," according to which "with the doubtful exception of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind." By numerous examples, Ryle showed quite forcefully how psychology and philosophy at the time were misled into asking the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are Foxall's Intentions Good?Marc N. Branch - 2007 - Behavior and Philosophy 35:61 - 64.
    Foxall's argument that behavioristic and intentional approaches should be hybridized rests on his views about the inability of a behavioristic position to deal with several features of behavior, including its continuity through time. My commentary suggests that Foxall's reservations about the inadequacies of a behavioristic position are overstated. A behavioristic approach can incorporate many of the features of behavior said to embody intention. However, the radical-behavioristic approach to the continuity of behavior through time is highly unconventional, permitting provisional temporal gaps (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations