Switch to: Citations

References in:

Hume on External Existence: A Sceptical Predicament

Dissertation, University of Sydney (2018)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Stephen Buckle, Hume's Enlightenment Tract: The Unity and Purpose of 'An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding'. [REVIEW]Heiner F. Klemme - 2003 - Erkenntnis 58 (1):126-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hume’s Academic Scepticism.John P. Wright - 1986 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):407-435.
    A philosopher once wrote the following words:If I examine the PTOLOMAIC and COPERNICAN systems, I endeavour only, by my enquiries, to know the real situation of the planets; that is, in other words, I endeavour to give them, in my conception, the same relations, that they bear towards each other in the heavens. To this operation of the mind, therefore, there seems to be always a real, though often an unknown standard, in the nature of things; nor is truth or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hume's Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.Michael Williams & Robert J. Fogelin - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (2):263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The significance of philosophical scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1984 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   326 citations  
  • Hume’s Scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (1):271-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hume’s Scepticism.Barry Stroud - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (1):271-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Malebranche's indirect realism: A reply to Steven Nadler.David Scott - 1996 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 4 (1):53 – 78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Constancy, Coherence, and Causality.Ira M. Schnall - 2004 - Hume Studies 30 (1):33-50.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 30, Number 1, April 2004, pp. 33-50 Constancy, Coherence, and Causality IRA M. SCHNALL According to David Hume, we believe in the existence of an external world because of the phenomena of constancy and coherence (T 1.4.2.18-43; SBN 194-210).1 Hume delineated these two aspects of our sensory experience, and claimed that they influence the imagination in such a way as to generate belief in the existence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The problems of philosophy.Bertrand Russell - 1912 - New York: Barnes & Noble.
    Immensely intelligible, thought-provoking guide by Nobel prize-winner considers such topics as the distinction between appearance and reality, the existence and nature of matter, idealism, inductive logic, intuitive knowledge, many other subjects. For students and general readers, there is no finer introduction to philosophy than this informative, affordable and highly readable edition that is "concise, free from technical terms, and perfectly clear to the general reader with no prior knowledge of the subject."—The Booklist of the American Library Association.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   549 citations  
  • An Inquiry Into the Human Mind, on the Principles of Common Sense.Thomas Reid - 1997 - Cambridge University Press. Edited by Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya.
    Thomas Reid, the Scottish natural and moral philosopher, was one of the founding members of the Aberdeen Philosophical Society and a significant figure in the Scottish Enlightenment. Reid believed that common sense should form the foundation of all philosophical inquiry. He criticised the sceptical philosophy propagated by his fellow Scot David Hume and the Anglo-Irish bishop George Berkeley, who asserted that the external world did not exist outside the human mind. Reid was also critical of the theory of ideas propagated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • Hume's Internalist Epistemology in EHU 12.Hsueh Qu - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (3):517-539.
    Much has been written about Kemp Smith's famous problem regarding the tension between Hume's naturalism and his scepticism. However, most commentators have focused their attention on the Treatise; those who address the Enquiry often take it to express essentially the same message as the Treatise. When Hume's scepticism in the Enquiry has been investigated in its own right, commentators have tended to focus on Hume's inductive scepticism in Sections 4 and 5. All in all, it seems that Section 12 has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hume on Mental Transparency.Hsueh Qu - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (4):576-601.
    This article investigates Hume's account of mental transparency. In this article, I will endorse Qualitative Transparency – that is, the thesis that we cannot fail to apprehend the qualitative characters of our current perceptions, and these apprehensions cannot fail to be veridical – on the basis that, unlike its competitors, it is both weak enough to accommodate the introspective mistakes that Hume recognises, and yet strong enough to make sense of his positive employments of mental transparency. Moreover, Qualitative Transparency is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hume’s practically epistemic conclusions?Hsueh Qu - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (3):501-524.
    The inoffensive title of Section 1.4.7 of Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature, ‘Conclusion of this Book’, belies the convoluted treatment of scepticism contained within. It is notoriously difficult to decipher Hume’s considered response to scepticism in this section, or whether he even has one. In recent years, however, one line of interpretation has gained popularity in the literature. The ‘usefulness and agreeableness reading’ (henceforth U&A) interprets Hume as arguing in THN 1.4.7 that our beliefs and/or epistemic policies are justified via (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Hume's theory of the external world.Henry Habberley Price - 1943 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Hume's Intentions.Kingsley Price - 1954 - Philosophical Review 63 (1):113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • How To Avoid Mis‐Reiding Hume's Maxim Of Conceivability.Lewis Powell - 2013 - Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250):105-119.
    In his Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Thomas Reid offers a barrage of objections to the view, held by David Hume, that conceivability implies possibility. In this paper, I present Reid's first two objections to the ‘maxim of conceivability’ and defend Hume from them. The first objection concerns our ability to understand impossible claims, while the second concerns thoughts about impossible claims (such as, for instance, the thought that they are impossible). Reid's objections have special force against Hume (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • David Hume: His pyrrhonism and his critique of pyrrhonism.Richard H. Popkin - 1951 - Philosophical Quarterly 1 (5):385-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Hume. [REVIEW]Terence Penelhum - 1980 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (4):477-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Hume's System. [REVIEW]Annette C. Baier - 1994 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (2):475-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume's system: an examination of the first book of his Treatise.David Pears - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this compelling analysis David Pears examines the foundations of Hume's theory of the mind as presented in the first book of the Treatise. Past studies have tended to take one of two extreme views: that Hume relies exclusively on a theory of meaning, or that he relies exclusively on a theory of truth and evidence. Steering a middle course between these positions, Pears argues that Hume's theory of ideas serves both functions. He examines in detail its application to three (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The myth of ‘British empiricism’.David Fate Norton - 1981 - History of European Ideas 1 (4):331-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Hume's conclusion.William Edward Morris - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 99 (1):89-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • I—Peter Millican: Humes Old and New Four Fashionable Falsehoods, and One Unfashionable Truth.Peter Millican - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):163-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Humes old and new: Four fashionable falsehoods, and one unfashionable truth.Peter Millican - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):163-199.
    Hume has traditionally been understood as an inductive sceptic with positivist tendencies, reducing causation to regular succession and anticipating the modern distinctions between analytic and synthetic, deduction and induction. The dominant fashion in recent Hume scholarship is to reject all this, replacing the ‘Old Hume’ with various New alternatives. Here I aim to counter four of these revisionist readings, presenting instead a broadly traditional interpretation but with important nuances, based especially on Hume’s later works. He asked that we should treat (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • How to Become a Moderate Skeptic: Hume's Way Out of Pyrrhonism.Yves Michaud - 1985 - Hume Studies 11 (1):33-46.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:33 HOW TO BECOME A MODERATE SKEPTIC: HUME'S WAY OUT OF PYRRHONISM The nature and extent of Hume's skepticism have been assessed in various ways. He was viewed as a radical skeptic until the end of the XIXth century. Many contemporary interpretations, which can be traced back to Kemp Smith's book, have claimed since that a reassessment was indispensable if we are to take seriously either the very project (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How to Become a Moderate Skeptic: Hume's Way Out of Pyrrhonism.Yves Michaud - 1985 - Hume Studies 11 (1):33-46.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:33 HOW TO BECOME A MODERATE SKEPTIC: HUME'S WAY OUT OF PYRRHONISM The nature and extent of Hume's skepticism have been assessed in various ways. He was viewed as a radical skeptic until the end of the XIXth century. Many contemporary interpretations, which can be traced back to Kemp Smith's book, have claimed since that a reassessment was indispensable if we are to take seriously either the very project (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Skepticism by Michael Williams. [REVIEW]Marie McGinn - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):211-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes.Charles E. Marks - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Does Hume hold a dispositional account of belief?Jennifer Smalligan Marušić - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):155-183.
    Philosophical theories about the nature of belief can be roughly classified into two groups: those that treat beliefs as occurrent mental states or episodes and those that treat beliefs as dispositions. David Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature seems to contain a classic example of an occurrence theory of belief as he defines 'belief' as 'a lively idea related to or associated with a present impression' (Treatise 1.3.7.5 96). This definition suggests that believing is an occurrent mental state, such as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Phenomenal Character of Emotional Experience: A Look at Perception Theory.Anika Lutz - 2015 - Dialectica 69 (3):313-334.
    In this paper I examine whether different suggestions made in the philosophy of perception can help us to explain and understand the phenomenal character of emotional experience. After having introduced the range of possible positions, I consider qualia-theory, reductive pure intentionalism and reductive impure intentionalism. I argue that qualia-theory can easily explain why emotions are phenomenal states at all but that it cannot account for the “inextricable link thesis” which is quite prominent in the philosophy of emotion. Reductive pure and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What is Worth Preserving in the Kemp Smith Interpretation of Hume?Louis E. Loeb - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (4):769-797.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Stability, Justification, and Hume’s Propensity to Ascribe Identity to Related Objects.Louis E. Loeb - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (1):237-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Stability and justification in hume’s treatise.Louis Loeb - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1):233-235.
    Stability and Justification in Hume's Treatise. LOUIS LOEB. Knowledge by Agreement: The Programme of Communitarian Epistemology. MARTIN KUSCH. A Philosophy of Culture: The Scope of Holistic Pragmatism, MORTON WHITE. Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ‐PEREYRA.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • From Descartes to Hume.L. E. Loeb - 1981 - Ithaca & London.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Extreme Skepticism and Commitment in the Treatise.Karánn Durland - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (1):65-98.
    The extreme skepticism that Hume’s dangerous dilemma introduces at the end of the first Book of the Treatise is deeply unsettling, in part because it seems to undermine Hume’s commitments to common life and philosophy, but also because Hume seems not to take its sweeping doubts seriously. He refuses to abandon his daily activities and philosophical pursuits, and he offers no clear account of what entitles him to sustain them. This paper explores a variety of tactics for addressing these opposing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • God, Hume and Natural Belief.J. C. A. Gaskin - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (189):281 - 294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Perceptions and Objects: Hume’s Radical Empiricism.Yumiko Inukai - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (2):189-210.
    In Book One of the Treatise of Human Nature, Hume seems to acknowledge the existence of both internal and external worlds, in which perceptions, objects, and bodies, exist. In particular, Hume seems directly to affirm the existence of extra-mental bodies, when he says at the beginning of the section "Of scepticism with regard to the senses," "We may well ask, What causes induce us to believe in theexistence of body? but 'tis in vain to ask, whether there be body or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Perceptions and Objects: Hume's Radical Empiricism.Yumiko Inukai - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (2):189-210.
    In A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume seems to use the term "object" to refer to different things in different contexts, including impressions, ideas, perceptions, and bodies. Does he ever use the term "external bodies" to refer to things in the extra-mental world? I argue that what Hume means by external bodies when he affirms their existence is not externally existing, material objects that are somehow presented to the mind or presented in impressions. Rather, the bodies that Hume affirms are, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why Hume Cannot Be A Realist.Jani Hakkarainen - 2012 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 10 (2):143-161.
    In this paper, I argue that there is a sceptical argument against the senses advanced by Hume that forms a decisive objection to the Metaphysically Realist interpretations of his philosophy – such as the different naturalist and New Humean readings. Hume presents this argument, apparently starting with the primary/secondary qualities distinction, both in A Treatise of Human Nature, Book 1, Part 4, Section 4 (Of the modern philosophy) (1739) and An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Section 12 (Of the Academical or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume's Scepticism and Realism.Jani Hakkarainen - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2):283-309.
    In this article, a novel interpretation of one of the problems of Hume scholarship is defended: his view of Metaphysical Realism or the belief in an external world (that there are ontologically and causally perception-independent, absolutely external and continued, i.e. Real entities). According to this interpretation, Hume's attitude in the domain of philosophy should be distinguished from his view in the domain of everyday life: Hume the philosopher suspends his judgement on Realism, whereas Hume the common man firmly believes in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Objects of Hume's Treatise.Marjorie Grene - 1994 - Hume Studies 20 (2):163-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Introduction.John Greco & Eleonore Stump - 2016 - Res Philosophica 93 (3):507-507.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • God, Hume and Natural Belief.J. C. A. Gaskin - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (189):281-294.
    Hume's doctrine of natural belief allows that certain beliefs are justifiably held by all men without regard to the quality of the evidence which may be produced in their favour. Examples are belief in an external world and belief in the veracity of our senses. According to R. J. Butler, Hume argues in the Dialogues that belief in God is of this sort. More recently John Hick has argued that for some people it is as natural to believe in God (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hume's skepticism in the Treatise of human nature.Robert J. Fogelin - 1985 - Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
    Examines the skeptical arguments in David Hume's major work and analyzes the place of skepticism in his philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.Robert J. Fogelin - 1985 - Mind 95 (379):392-396.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Garrett on the Consistency of Hume's Philosophy.Robert J. Fogelin - 1998 - Hume Studies 24 (1):161-169.
    In *Cognition and Commitment in Hume's Philosophy*, Don Garrett argues for the coherence of Hume's philosophy when it is viewed as work in cognitive psychology. Without denying this, I argue that there is more to Hume's standpoint than cognitive psychology. Specifically, Hume's standpoint shifts as the level of inquiry changes. A descriptive cognitive psychology is one standpoint that he occupies. However, he occupies other standpoints as well: the commonsense standpoint of the vulgar is one; the radical doubt of the skeptic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • David Hume's theory of mind.Daniel E. Flage - 1990 - New York: Routledge.
    INTRODUCTION Anyone who reads David Hume's Treatise of Human Nature cannot but be struck by the diversity of philosophical issues Hume addresses, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Hume's Diffident Skepticism.Phillip D. Cummins - 1999 - Hume Studies 25 (1-2):43-65.
    One of the chief problems facing interpreters of Hume's philosophy is what I shall call the integration problem. It is a global problem inasmuch as it casts a shadow on every component of his philosophy, but does not directly affect how we interpret their details. The integration problem arises at the end of Book I of A Treatise of Human Nature, where Hume seemed to acknowledge that his account of human understanding, his logic, leads directly to total skepticism regarding both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume's Theory of the External World.Ralph W. Church - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52 (3):317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Hume’s Causal Reconstruction of the Perceptual Relativity Argument in Treatise 1.4.4.Annemarie Butler - 2009 - Dialogue 48 (1):77-101.
    RÉSUMÉ : Dans le Traité 1.4.4, Hume a présenté au nom des philosophes modernes un argument causal qui démontre que nos impressions des qualités secondaires ne ressemblent pas aux qualités des objets eux-mêmes. Les prédécesseurs de Hume n’ont pourtant pas employé d’argument causal, mais l’argument des qualités contraires. Je soutiens que la présentation qu’en a fait Hume n’est pas simplement à mettre au compte d’une différence stylistique «gratuite» mais est une correction importante dans la foulée de ses propres découvertes philosophiques.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations