Switch to: Citations

References in:

Narrow mental content

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Assertion revisited: On the interpretation of two-dimensional modal semantics.Robert C. Stalnaker - 2006 - In Garc (ed.), Philosophical Studies. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 293-309.
    This paper concerns the applications of two-dimensional modal semantics to the explanation of the contents of speech and thought. Different interpretations and applications of the apparatus are contrasted. First, it is argued that David Kaplan's two-dimensional semantics for indexical expressions is different from the use that I made of a formally similar framework to represent the role of contingent information in the determination of what is said. But the two applications are complementary rather than conflicting. Second, my interpretation of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Social content and psychological content.Brian Loar - 1988 - In Robert H. Grimm & Daniel Davy Merrill (eds.), Contents of Thought. Tucson.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Ignorance of meaning.Gabriel Segal - 2003 - In Alex Barber (ed.), Epistemology of language. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Content: Wide vs. narrow.Kent Bach - 1998 - In Edward Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Genealogy to Iqbal. Routledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • All the Difference in the World.Tim Crane - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162):1-25.
    The celebrated "Twin Earth" arguments of Hilary Putnam (1975) and Tyler Burge (1979) aim to establish that some intentional states logically depend on facts external to the subjects of those states. Ascriptions of states of these kinds to a thinker entail that the thinker's environment is a certain way. It is not possible that the thinker could be in those very intentional states unless the environment is that way...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • The extended mind.Andy Clark & David J. Chalmers - 1998 - Analysis 58 (1):7-19.
    Where does the mind stop and the rest of the world begin? The question invites two standard replies. Some accept the demarcations of skin and skull, and say that what is outside the body is outside the mind. Others are impressed by arguments suggesting that the meaning of our words "just ain't in the head", and hold that this externalism about meaning carries over into an externalism about mind. We propose to pursue a third position. We advocate a very different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1616 citations  
  • The nature of narrow content.David J. Chalmers - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):46-66.
    A content of a subject's mental state is narrow when it is determined by the subject's intrinsic properties: that is, when any possible intrinsic duplicate of the subject has a corresponding mental state with the same content. A content of a subject's mental state is..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Comment on Yli-Vakkuri and Hawthorne, Narrow Content.Alex Byrne - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (9):3017-3026.
    This comment mainly examines Yli-Vakkuri and Hawthorne’s preferred framework for examining whether narrow content is viable, arguing that their framework is not well-suited to the task; once a more traditional framework is adopted, Y&H’s case against internalism is strengthened.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Origins of Objectivity.Tyler Burge - 2010 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Tyler Burge presents an original study of the most primitive ways in which individuals represent the physical world. By reflecting on the science of perception and related psychological and biological sciences, he gives an account of constitutive conditions for perceiving the physical world, and thus aims to locate origins of representational mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   775 citations  
  • Individuation and causation in psychology.Tyler Burge - 1989 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (4):303-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Individualism and psychology.Tyler Burge - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (January):3-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   463 citations  
  • Direct and indirect belief.Curtis Brown - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (2):289-316.
    Belief states are only contingently connected with the objects of belief. Burge's examples show that the same belief state can be associated with different objects of belief. Kripke's puzzle shows that the same object of belief can be associated with different belief states. Nevertheless, belief states can best be characterized by a subset of the propositions one believes, namely those one directly or immediately believes. The rest of the things one believes are believed indirectly, by virtue of one's direct beliefs. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Belief states and narrow content.Curtis Brown - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (3):343-67.
    The first thesis is that beliefs play a role in explaining behavior. This is reasonably uncontroversial, though it has been controverted. Why did I raise my arm? Because I wanted to emphasize a point, and believed that I could do so by raising my arm. The belief that I could emphasize a point by raising my arm is central to the most natural explanation of my action.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Content and self-knowledge.Paul A. Boghossian - 1989 - Philosophical Topics 17 (1):5-26.
    This paper argues that, given a certain apparently inevitable thesis about content, we could not know our own minds. The thesis is that the content of a thought is determined by its relational properties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   250 citations  
  • Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap.Ned Block & Robert Stalnaker - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (1):1-46.
    The explanatory gap . Consciousness is a mystery. No one has ever given an account, even a highly speculative, hypothetical, and incomplete account of how a physical thing could have phenomenal states. Suppose that consciousness is identical to a property of the brain, say activity in the pyramidal cells of layer 5 of the cortex involving reverberatory circuits from cortical layer 6 to the thalamus and back to layers 4 and 6,as Crick and Koch have suggested for visual consciousness. .) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   310 citations  
  • Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.Ned Block - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):615-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   340 citations  
  • Horgan and Tienson on phenomenology and intentionality.Andrew Bailey & Bradley Richards - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 167 (2):313-326.
    Terence Horgan, George Graham and John Tienson argue that some intentional content is constitutively determined by phenomenology alone. We argue that this would require a certain kind of covariation of phenomenal states and intentional states that is not established by Horgan, Tienson and Graham’s arguments. We make the case that there is inadequate reason to think phenomenology determines perceptual belief, and that there is reason to doubt that phenomenology determines any species of non-perceptual intentionality. We also raise worries about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 2024 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    This book is a fiftieth anniversary republication of Thomas Nagel's "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?", a classic in the philosophy of mind. Through its argument for the irreducible subjectivity of consciousness, it played an essential role in making the study of consciousness a central part of philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience. It also spurred the now flourishing scientific attention to the consciousness of non-human creatures: mammals, birds, fish, mollusks, and insects. The book also includes a second essay offering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Narrow content meets fat syntax.Stephen P. Stich - 1991 - In Barry M. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • What narrow content is not.Ned Block - 1991 - In Barry M. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics.Barry M. Loewer (ed.) - 1991 - Cambridge: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Beyond belief.Daniel C. Dennett - 1982 - In Andrew Woodfield (ed.), Thought And Object: Essays On Intentionality. New York: Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Narrow content and narrow interpretation.Stephen L. White - 1991 - In The Unity of the Self. Cambridge: MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reply to Speaks.Juhani Yli-Vakkuri & John Hawthorne - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (9):3061-3065.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reply to Byrne.Juhani Yli-Vakkuri & John Hawthorne - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (9):3049-3054.
    In this reply to Alex Byrne’s comment on our book Narrow Content, we address Byrne’s claim that internalism is best framed as a thesis about properties of agents rather than properties of thoughts, arguing that a thought-based framework is better suited to standard internalist ambitions. We also discuss whether there is any prospect for a view in the internalist spirit that prescinds from multiplying indices beyond worlds, address Byrne’s ordinary language considerations against an ontology of thoughts, and briefly evaluate the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Social norms and narrow content.Meredith Williams - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):425-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind.Robert Andrew Wilson - 1995 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book offers the first sustained critique of individualism in psychology, a view that has been the subject of debate between philosophers such as Jerry Fodor and Tyler Burge for many years. The author approaches individualism as an issue in the philosophy of science and by discussing issues such as computationalism and the mind's modularity he opens the subject up for non-philosophers in psychology and computer science. Professor Wilson carefully examines the most influential arguments for individualism and identifies the main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Partial character and the language of thought.Stephen L. White - 1982 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63 (4):347-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • In Defense of a Different Taxonomy: A Reply to Owens.Valerie Walker - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (3):425 - 431.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Narrow content functionalism and the mind-body problem.Kenneth Taylor - 1989 - Noûs 23 (3):355-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Galacticism, thought-relativism, quasi-internalism.Jeff Speaks - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (9):3037-3047.
    In Narrow Content, Hawthorne & Yli-Vakkuri provide an admirably clear and precise framework for understanding the debate between internalist and externalist theories of mental content. They also present a series of arguments against internalism. They identify two views — which they call 'thought-relativism' and 'quasi-internalism' — which seem to avoid their main line of argument. I discuss Hawthorne & Yli-Vakkuri's arguments against these two views, and explore a few different ways in which they might be developed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reference and Description: The Case Against Two-Dimensionalism.Scott Soames - 2005 - Princeton: Princeton University Press. Edited by Frank Jackson & Michael Smith.
    In this book, Scott Soames defends the revolution in philosophy led by Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, and David Kaplan against attack from those wishing to revive ..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Seeing What is not There.Gabriel Segal - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (2):189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • A Slim Book About Narrow Content.Gabriel Segal - 2000 - MIT Press.
    The book, written in a clear, engaging style, contains four chapters.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • How Narrow is Narrow Content?François Recanati - 1994 - Dialectica 48 (3-4):209-229.
    SummaryIn this paper I discuss two influential views in the philosophy of mind: the two‐component picture draws a distinction between ‘narrow content’ and ‘broad content’, while radical externalism denies that there is such a thing as narrow content. I argue that ‘narrow content’ is ambiguous, and that the two views can be reconciled. Instead of considering that there is only one question and three possible answers corresponding to Cartesian internalism, the two‐component picture, and radical externalism respectively, I show that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Narrow Content.Juhani Yli-Vakkuri & John Hawthorne - 2018 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Edited by John Hawthorne.
    Can there be 'narrow' mental content, that is entirely determined by the goings-on inside the head of the thinker? This book argues not, and defends instead a thoroughgoing externalism: the entanglement of our minds with the external world runs so deep that no internal component of mentality can easily be cordoned off.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Charity, interpretation, and belief.Colin McGinn - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (9):521-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Narrow content.Michael McDermott - 1986 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (3):277-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Solipsistic semantics.Ernest Lepore & Barry Loewer - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):595-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Real narrow content.Uriah Kriegel - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (3):304–328.
    The purpose of the present paper is to develop and defend an account of narrow content that would neutralize the commonplace charge that narrow content.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Representation and narrow belief.Frank Jackson - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):99-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Narrow content and representation--or twin earth revisited.Frank Jackson - 2003 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 77 (2):55-70.
    Intentional states represent. Belief represents how we take things to be; desire represents how we would like things to be; and so on. To represent is to make a division among possibilities; it is to divide the possibilities into those that are consistent with how things are being represented to be and those that are not. I will call the possibilities consistent with how some intentional state represents things to be, its content. There is no suggestion that this is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Mental causation.Frank Jackson - 1996 - Mind 105 (419):377-413.
    I survey recent work on mental causation. The discussion is conducted under the twin presumptions that mental states, including especially what subjects believe and desire, causally explain what subjects do, and that the physical sciences can in principle give a complete explanation for each and every bodily movement. I start with sceptical discussions of various views that hold that, in some strong sense, the causal explanations offered by psychology are autonomous with respect to those offered by the physical sciences. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • In Defence of Narrow Content. [REVIEW]Anandi Hattiangadi - 2019 - Analysis 79 (3):539-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Against Content Normativity.Kathrin Glüer & Åsa Wikforss - 2009 - Mind 118 (469):31-70.
    As meaning's claim to normativity has grown increasingly suspect the normativity thesis has shifted to mental content. In this paper, we distinguish two versions of content normativism: 'CE normativism', according to which it is essential to content that certain 'oughts' can be derived from it, and 'CD normativism', according to which content is determined by norms in the first place. We argue that neither type of normativism withstands scrutiny. CE normativism appeals to the fact that there is an essential connection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Why broad content can’t influence behaviour.Cressida Gaukroger - 2017 - Synthese 194 (8):3005–3020.
    This article examines one argument in favour of the position that the relational properties of mental states do not have causal powers over behaviour. This argument states that we establish that the relational properties of mental states do not have causal powers by considering cases where intrinsic properties remain the same but relational properties vary to see whether, under such circumstances, behaviour would ever vary. The individualist argues that behaviour will not vary with relational properties alone, which means that they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1987 - MIT Press. Edited by Margaret A. Boden.
    Preface 1 Introduction: The Persistence of the Attitudes 2 Individualism and Supervenience 3 Meaning Holism 4 Meaning and the World Order Epilogue Creation Myth Appendix Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought Notes References Author Index.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1496 citations  
  • Replies.Jerry Fodor - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (1):50–57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A modal argument for narrow content.Jerry A. Fodor - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (1):5-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Must psychology be individualistic?Frances Egan - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (April):179-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations