Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Wittgenstein and Idealism.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 7:76-95.
    Tractatus, 5.62 famously says: ‘… what the solipsist means is quite correct; only it cannot be said but makes itself manifest. The world is my world: this is manifest in the fact that the limits of language mean the limits of my world.’ The later part of this repeats what was said in summary at 5.6: ‘the limits of my language mean the limits of my world’. And the key to the problem ‘how much truth there is in solipsism’ has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The normativity of meaning defended.Daniel Whiting - 2007 - Analysis 67 (2):133-140.
    Meaning, according to a significant number of philosophers, is an intrinsically normative notion.1 For this reason, it is suggested, meaning is not conducive to a naturalistic explanation. In this paper, I shall not address whether this is indeed so. Nor shall I present arguments in support of the normativity thesis (see Glock 2005; Kripke 1982). Instead, I shall examine and respond to two forceful objections recently (and independently) raised against it by Boghossian (2005), Hattiangadi (2006) and Miller (2006). Although I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • A lógica do 'Tractatus'.João Cuter - 2002 - Manuscrito 25 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Anything but argument?Cora Diamond - 1982 - Philosophical Investigations 5 (1):23-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Goethe and Wittgenstein.M. W. Rowe - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (257):283 - 303.
    The influence of Goethe on Wittgenstein is just beginning to be appreciated. Hacker and Baker, Westphal, Monk, and Haller have all drawn attention to significant affinities between the two men's work, and the number of explicit citations of Goethe in Wittgenstein's texts supports the idea that we are not dealing simply with a matter of deeplying similarities of aim and method, but of direct and major influence. These scholarly developments are encouraging because they help to place Wittgenstein's work within an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Modern Moral Philosophy.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1958 - Philosophy 33 (124):1 - 19.
    The author presents and defends three theses: (1) "the first is that it is not profitable for us at present to do moral philosophy; that should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology." (2) "the second is that the concepts of obligation, And duty... And of what is morally right and wrong, And of the moral sense of 'ought', Ought to be jettisoned if this is psychologically possible...." (3) "the third thesis is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   768 citations  
  • Exemplification and expression.Charles Altieri - 2007 - In Garry Hagberg & Walter Jost (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 491–506.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The “Grammaticalization of Experience” What is Exemplification? Exemplifying Feeling Poetry and the Resources of Grammar Example “Of ” and Example “As”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Wittgenstein and idealism.Bernard Williams - 1981 - In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 144-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • A reply to my critics.George Edward Moore - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • Reply : Rule-following and moral realism.Simon Blackburn - 1981 - In Steven H. Holtzman & Christopher M. Leich (eds.), Wittgenstein: To Follow A Rule. Boston: Routledge. pp. 163--87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Moore’s Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person.Mitchell S. Green & John N. Williams (eds.) - 2007 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    G. E. Moore observed that to assert, 'I went to the pictures last Tuesday but I don't believe that I did' would be 'absurd'. Over half a century later, such sayings continue to perplex philosophers. In the definitive treatment of the famous paradox, Green and Williams explain its history and relevance and present new essays by leading thinkers in the area.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Indexicals.David Braun - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    Indexicals are linguistic expressions whose reference shifts from context to context: some paradigm examples are ‘I’, ‘here’, ‘now’, ‘today’,‘he’, ‘she’, and ‘that’. Two speakers who utter a single sentence that contains an indexical may say different things. For instance, Fred and Wilma say different things when they utter the sentence ‘I am female’. Many philosophers (following David Kaplan 1989a) hold that indexicals have two sorts of meaning. The first sort of meaning is often called ‘character’ or ‘linguistic meaning’; the second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kripke on Wittgenstein and normativity.George M. Wilson - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):366-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Modern Moral Philosophy.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1997 - In Roger Crisp & Michael Slote (eds.), Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   246 citations  
  • Thoughts on demonstratives.David Kaplan - 1990 - In Palle Yourgrau (ed.), Demonstratives. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 34-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and literary language.Jon Cook & Rupert Read - 2007 - In Garry Hagberg & Walter Jost (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 465–490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wittgenstein, ethics and basic moral certainty.Nigel Pleasants - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (3):241 – 267.
    Alice Crary claims that “the standard view of the bearing of Wittgenstein's philosophy on ethics” is dominated by “inviolability interpretations”, which often underlie conservative readings of Wittgenstein. Crary says that such interpretations are “especially marked in connection with On Certainty”, where Wittgenstein is represented as holding that “our linguistic practices are immune to rational criticism, or inviolable”. Crary's own conception of the bearing of Wittgenstein's philosophy on ethics, which I call the “intrinsically-ethical reading”, derives from the influential New Wittgenstein school (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Meaning and normativity.Allan Gibbard - 1994 - Philosophical Issues 5:95-115.
    The concepts of meaning and mental content resist naturalistic analysis. This is because they are normative: they depend on ideas of how things ought to be.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and Shakespeare.Peter B. Lewis - 2005 - Philosophy and Literature 29 (2):241-255.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and ShakespearePeter B. LewisNear the middle of the first of his 1938 Lectures on Aesthetics, Wittgenstein talks about what he calls "the tremendous things in art"(LC, I 23 8, italics in original).1 Apart from a brief indication of the way in which our response to the tremendous differs from the non-tremendous, he does not refer again in this way to the tremendous things in art, though he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mind, meaning and practice.Barry G. Stroud - 1996 - In Hans D. Sluga & David G. Stern (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Some Paradoxes of Counterprivacy.André Gombay - 1988 - Philosophy 63 (244):191 - 210.
    For many years G. E. Moore asked himself what was wrong with sentences like ‘I went to the pictures last Tuesday, but I don't believe that I did’, or ‘I believe that he has gone out, but he has not’. He discussed the problem in 1912 in his Ethics , and was still discussing it in 1944 in a paper to the Moral Sciences Club at Cambridge—an event we know about from a letter of Wittgenstein that I shall quote in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The purpose of tractarian nonsense.Michael Kremer - 2001 - Noûs 35 (1):39–73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The Discovery of the Other: Cavell, Fichte, and Skepticism.Paul Franks - 1996 - Common Knowledge 5:72-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Modern Moral Philosophy.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1997 - In Thomas L. Carson & Paul K. Moser (eds.), Morality and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   359 citations  
  • (1 other version)I*—The Presidential Address: “Eine Einstellung zur Seele”.Peter Winch - 1981 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81 (1):1-16.
    Peter Winch; I*—The Presidential Address: “Eine Einstellung zur Seele”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 1–16, ht.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • More on Moore.Michael Welbourne - 1992 - Analysis 52 (4):237 - 241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)Demonstratives.David Kaplan - 1989 - In Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes From Kaplan. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 481--563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   321 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on Criteria and Other Minds.Jack Temkin - 1990 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):561-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Inferentialism and the Normativity of Meaning.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2012 - Philosophia 40 (1):75-97.
    There may be various reasons for claiming that meaning is normative, and additionally, very different senses attached to the claim. However, all such claims have faced fierce resistance from those philosophers who insist that meaning is not normative in any nontrivial sense of the word. In this paper I sketch one particular approach to meaning claiming its normativity and defend it against the anti-normativist critique: namely the approach of Brandomian inferentialism. However, my defense is not restricted to inferentialism in any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations