Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Scientific Image.William Demopoulos & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1762 citations  
  • Will, Belief and Knowledge.H. G. Classen - 1979 - Dialogue 18 (1):64-72.
    In her recent paper, “Belief, Values and the Will,” Trudy Govier raises several interesting and challenging points. Most interesting is her conclusion that it is at least logically possible for a person to believe something “simply in virtue of having taken that decision,” i.e., by fiat. In otherwords, it is possible to believe something by an act of will.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Descartes, Belief and the Will.Brian Grant - 1976 - Philosophy 51 (198):401 - 419.
    I want to discuss the puzzling, but, in some ways, persuasive view that I have a familiar and unproblematic kind of freedom with respect to my beliefs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge.Laurence Bonjour - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):53-73.
    One of the many problems that would have t o be solved by a satisfactory theory of empirical knowledge, perhaps the most central is a general structural problem which I shall call the epistemic regress problem: the problem of how to avoid an in- finite and presumably vicious regress of justification in ones account of the justifica- tion of empirical beliefs. Foundationalist theories of empirical knowledge, as we shall see further below, attempt t o avoid the regress by locating a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   294 citations  
  • Belief and the Will.Anthony O'Hear - 1972 - Philosophy 47 (180):95 - 112.
    In this article, we will consider how far we might be said to be active in forming our beliefs; in particular, we will ask to what extent we can be said to be free in believing what we want to believe. It is clear that we ought to believe only what is really so, at least in so far as it lies in our power to determine this, but reflection shows that, regrettably, we do not confine our beliefs to what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Internalist Conception of Justification.Alvin Goldman - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):27-51.
    One possible aim of epistemology is to advise cognizers on the proper choice of beliefs or other doxastic attitudes. This aim has often been part of scientific methodology: to tell scientists when they should accept a given hypothesis, or give it a certain degree of credence. This regulative function is naturally linked to the notion of epistemic justification. It may well be suggested that a cognizer is justified in believing something just in case the rules of proper epistemic procedure prescribe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • What is Justified Belief?Alvin I. Goldman - 1979 - In George Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology. Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 1-25.
    The aim of this paper is to sketch a theory of justified belief. What I have in mind is an explanatory theory, one that explains in a general way why certain beliefs are counted as justified and others as unjustified. Unlike some traditional approaches, I do not try to prescribe standards for justification that differ from, or improve upon, our ordinary standards. I merely try to explicate the ordinary standards, which are, I believe, quite different from those of many classical, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   890 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-40).David Hume - 1969 - Mineola, N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Edited by Ernest Campbell Mossner.
    A key to modern studies of 18th century Western philosophy, the Treatise considers numerous classic philosophical issues, including causation, existence, freedom and necessity and morality. This abridged edition has an introduction which explain's Hume's thought and places it in the context of its times.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   477 citations  
  • The Darwinian Revolution.Michael Ruse - 2019 - Cambridge University Press.
    What is the Darwinian revolution and why is it important for philosophers? These are the questions tackled in this Element. In four sections, the topics covered are the story of the revolution, the question of whether it really was a revolution, the nature of the revolution, and the implications for philosophy, both epistemology and ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The philosophical works of Descartes.René Descartes - 1967 - London,: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Elizabeth Sanderson Haldane & G. R. T. Ross.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • The Melanchthon Circle, Rheticus, and the Wittenberg Interpretation of the Copernican Theory.Robert S. Westman - 1975 - Isis 66 (2):165-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Belief and Will.H. H. Price - 1954 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 28 (1):1-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • The psychological turn.Hilary Kornblith - 1982 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (3):238 – 253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1727 citations  
  • Belief and Will Revisited.Robert Holyer - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (2):273-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Doxastic agency.John Heil - 1983 - Philosophical Studies 43 (3):355 - 364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Belief, Values, and the Will.Trudy Govier - 1976 - Dialogue 15 (4):642-663.
    In this paper I shall presuppose that: logic and epistemology are disciplines which supply us with normative statements pertaining to states of belief. as such, logic and epistemology have implications concerning what we ought and ought not to believe. as such, logic and epistemology presuppose that there is some sense in which a person controls what he believes — some sense in which ‘can’ has a place in contexts where one comes to believe things.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Contra Reliabilism.Carl Ginet - 1985 - The Monist 68 (2):175-187.
    The reliability of a belief-producing process is a matter of how likely it is that the process will produce beliefs that are true. The term reliabilism may be used to refer to any position that makes this idea of reliability central to the explication of some important epistemic concept. I know of three such positions that appeal to some epistemologists: a reliabilist account of what makes a belief justified, a reliabilist account of what makes a true belief knowledge, and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Conclusive reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   313 citations  
  • Problems of the Self.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press.
    A volume of philosophical studies, centred on problems of personal identity and extending to related topics in the philosophy of mind and moral philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   306 citations  
  • Deciding to believe.Bernard Williams - 1973 - In Problems of the Self. Cambridge University Press. pp. 136--51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   338 citations  
  • Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge.Laurence BonJour - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • Conclusive Reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Seeing is believing.John Heil - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (3):229-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Problems of the Self.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 37 (3):551-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   366 citations  
  • Reliability and Two Kinds of Epistemic Justification.Clarke Murray - 1987 - In Newton Garver Peter H. Hare (ed.), Naturalism and Rationality. Buffalo: Prometheus Press. pp. 159-170.
    In this paper, I argue that there are two kinds of epistemic justification: one is objective and the other, subjective. Internalists are interested in the subjective variety of justification. Externalists are interested in the objective notion of justification. A paper by Stewart Cohen fails to distinguish these two varieties of epistemic justification and, as a result, criticizes externalists for failing to address the internalist, subjective notion of epistemic justification. But, since that notion is not the one that externallists care about, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations