Switch to: Citations

References in:

Christian Wolff

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2019)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition.David O. Brink - 2019 - Philosophers' Imprint 19.
    Perfectionism is an underexplored tradition, perhaps because of doubts about the grounds, content, and implications of perfectionist ideals. Aristotle, J.S. Mill, and T.H. Green are normative perfectionists, grounding perfectionist ideals in a normative conception of human nature involving personality or agency. This essay explores the prospects of normative perfectionism by examining Kant’s criticisms of the perfectionist tradition. First, Kant claims that the perfectionist can generate only hypothetical, not categorical, imperatives. But insofar as the normative perfectionist appeals to the normative category (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant, Wolff and the Method of Philosophy.Gabriele Gava - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 8:271-303.
    Both in his pre-critical writings and in his critical works, Kant criticizes the Wolffian tradition for its use of the mathematical method in philosophy. The chapter argues that the apparent unambiguousness of this opposition between Kant and Wolff notwithstanding, the problem of ascertaining the relationship between Kant’s and Wolff’s methods in philosophy cannot be dismissed so quickly. Only a close consideration of Kant’s different remarks on Wolff’s approach and a comparison of the methods that Wolff and Kant actually used in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Before and Beyond Leibniz: Tschirnhaus and Wolff on Experience and Method.Corey W. Dyck - manuscript
    In this chapter, I consider the largely overlooked influence of E. W. von Tschirnhaus' treatise on method, the Medicina mentis, on Wolff's early philosophical project (in both its conception and execution). As I argue, part of Tschirnhaus' importance for Wolff lies in the use he makes of principles gained from experience as a foundation for the scientific enterprise in the context of his broader philosophical rationalism. I will show that this lesson from Tschirnhaus runs through Wolff's earliest philosophical discussions, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Women and Philosophy in Eighteenth-Century Germany.Corey W. Dyck (ed.) - 2021 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Women and Philosophy in 18th Century Germany gathers for the first time an exceptional group of scholars with the explicit aim of composing a comprehensive portrait of the complex and manifold contributions on the part of women in 18th century Germany. Amidst the re-evaluation of the place of women in the history of early Modern philosophy, this vital and distinctive intellectual context has thus far been missing. As this volume will show, women intellectuals contributed crucially (directly and indirectly) to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rationalism and Perfectionism [in 18-Century Moral Philosophy].Stefano Bacin - 2017 - In Sacha Golob & Jens Timmermann (eds.), The Cambridge History of Moral Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 379-393.
    The chapter provides a brief survey of the moral views of some of the main writers advocating rationalist conceptions in philosophical ethics in Eighteenth-Century Britain and Germany, prior to Reid and Kant: Samuel Clarke, William Wollaston, John Balguy, Richard Price, Christian Wolff (along with his adversary Christian August Crusius), Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality.Eric Watkins - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is a book about Kant's views on causality as understood in their proper historical context. Specifically, Eric Watkins argues that a grasp of Leibnizian and anti-Leibnizian thought in eighteenth-century Germany helps one to see how the critical Kant argued for causal principles that have both metaphysical and epistemological elements. On this reading Kant's model of causality does not consist of events, but rather of substances endowed with causal powers that are exercised according to their natures and circumstances. This innovative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • The Newtonian-Wolffian Controversy: 1740-1759.Ronald S. Calinger - 1969 - Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (3):319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Founding of Aesthetics in the German Enlightenment: The Art of Invention and the Invention of Art.Stefanie Buchenau - 2013 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    When, in 1735, Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten added a new discipline to the philosophical system, he not only founded modern aesthetics but also contributed to shaping the modern concept of art or 'fine art'. In The Founding of Aesthetics in the German Enlightenment, Stefanie Buchenau offers a rich analysis and reconstruction of the origins of this new discipline in its wider context of German Enlightenment philosophy. Present-day scholars commonly regard Baumgarten's views as an imperfect prefiguration of Kantian and post-Kantian aesthetics, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Christian Wolff and Leibnizian Monads.Martin Schönfeld - 2002 - The Leibniz Review 12:131-135.
    As the label “Leibnizian-Wolffian School Philosophy” suggests, Christian Wolff has traditionally been regarded as Leibniz’s disciple. Thanks to L. W. Beck, C. A. Corr, J. École, and others, we now know that Wolff was inspired by.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and Rational Psychology.Corey Dyck - 2014 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press UK.
    Corey W. Dyck presents a new account of Kant's criticism of the rational investigation of the soul in his monumental Critique of Pure Reason, in light of its eighteenth-century German context. When characterizing the rational psychology that is Kant's target in the Paralogisms of Pure Reason chapter of the Critique commentators typically only refer to an approach to, and an account of, the soul found principally in the thought of Descartes and Leibniz. But Dyck argues that to do so is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Kant and His German Contemporaries : Volume 1, Logic, Mind, Epistemology, Science and Ethics.Corey W. Dyck & Falk Wunderlich (eds.) - 2017 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    This collection of new essays, the first of its kind in English, considers the ways in which the philosophy of Immanuel Kant engages with the views of lesser-known eighteenth-century German thinkers. Each chapter casts new light on aspects of Kant's complex relationship with these figures, particularly with respect to key aspects of his logic, metaphysics, epistemology, theory of science, and ethics. The portrait of Kant that emerges is of a major thinker thoroughly engaged with his contemporaries - drawing on their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Christian Wolff's Doctrine of the Soul.Richard J. Blackwell - 1961 - Journal of the History of Ideas 22 (3):339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Transzendentale Wahrheit und Traum: Christian Wolffs Antwort auf die Herausforderung durch den cartesianischen Zweifel.Sonia Carboncini - 1991 - Frommann-Holzboog.
    Das Problem des Unterschiedes zwischen Wirklichkeit (bzw. Wahrheit) und Traum in seiner Entwicklung von Descartes bis Kant wurde zum Thema in der Lehre von der transzendentalen Wahrheit, dem Kernstuck der Wolffschen Ontologie und Kosmologie. Die Arbeit stellt die Wahrheits- und Traumlehre Wolffs aus einem dreifachen Gesichtspunkt dar: zunachst aus der Konfrontation mit der Scholastik, aber auch mit dem Cartesianismus; sodann im Hinblick auf die Ausarbeitung einer neuen Bedeutung des Terminus transzendental; und schliesslich in bezug auf die Lehre vom somnium objective (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 'What Does Heaven Say?': Christian Wolff and Western Interpretations of Confucian Ethics.Robert B. Louden - 2001 - In Bryan W. Van Norden (ed.), Confucius and the Analects: New Essays. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 73--93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Wolffian roots of Kant’s teleology.Hein van den Berg - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (4):724-734.
    Kant’s teleology as presented in the Critique of Judgment is commonly interpreted in relation to the late eighteenth-century biological research of Johann Friedrich Blumenbach. In the present paper, I show that this interpretative perspective is incomplete. Understanding Kant’s views on teleology and biology requires a consideration of the teleological and biological views of Christian Wolff and his rationalist successors. By reconstructing the Wolffian roots of Kant’s teleology, I identify several little known sources of Kant’s views on biology. I argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Wolff and Kant on Scientific Demonstration and Mechanical Explanation.Hein van den Berg - 2013 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 95 (2):178-205.
    This paper analyzes Immanuel Kant’s views on mechanical explanation on the basis of Christian Wolff’s idea of scientific demonstration. Kant takes mechanical explanations to explain properties of wholes in terms of their parts. I reconstruct the nature of such explanations by showing how part-whole conceptualizations in Wolff’s logic and metaphysics shape the ideal of a proper and explanatory scientific demonstration. This logico-philosophical background elucidates why Kant construes mechanical explanations as ideal explanations of nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Structure of Wolffian Philosophy.Richard J. Blackwell - 1961 - Modern Schoolman 38 (3):203-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Newton and Wolff: The Leibnizian reaction to the Principia, 1716-1763.Marius Stan - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):459-481.
    Newton rested his theory of mechanics on distinct metaphysical and epistemological foundations. After Leibniz's death in 1716, the Principia ran into sharp philosophical opposition from Christian Wolff and his disciples, who sought to subvert Newton's foundations or replace them with Leibnizian ideas. In what follows, I chronicle some of the Wolffians' reactions to Newton's notion of absolute space, his dynamical laws of motion, and his general theory of gravitation. I also touch on arguments advanced by Newton's Continental followers, such as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Christian Wolff's Philosophy of Contingent Reality.Cornelis Anthonie van Peursen - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (1):69-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The early modern subject: self-consciousness and personal identity from Descartes to Hume.Udo Thiel - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Explores the understanding of self-consciousness and personal identity - two fundamendtal features of human subjectivity - as it developed in early modern philosophy. Udo Thiel presents a critical evaluation of these features as they were conceived in the sevententh and eighteenth centuries. He explains the arguments of thinkers such as Descartes, Locke, Leibniz, Wolff, and Hume, as well as their early critics, followers, and other philosophical contemporaries, and situates them within their historical contexts. Interest in the issues of self-consciousness and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen.Thomas Sturm - 2009 - Mentis.
    This book explores Kant's philosophy of the human sciences, their status, their relations and prospects. Contrary to widespread belief, he is not dogmatic about the question of whether these disciplines are proper sciences. Instead, this depends on whether we can rationally adjust assumptions about the methods, goals, and subject matter of these disciplines - and this has to be done alongside of ongoing research. Kant applies these ideas especially in lectures on "pragmatic antropology" given from 1772-1796. In doing so, he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Christian Wolff on Individuation.Jorge J. E. Gracia - 1993 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 10 (2):147 - 164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Grounding the Principle of Sufficient Reason: Leibnizian Rationalism versus the Humean Challenge.Brandon C. Look - 2010 - In Carlos Fraenkel, Dario Perinetti & Justin E. H. Smith (eds.), The Rationalists: Between Tradition and Innovation. Springer. pp. 201--219.
    This essay examines arguments offered in support of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR) by Leibniz and his followers as well as Hume's critique of the PSR. It is shown that Leibniz has a defensible argument for the PSR, whereas the arguments of his self-proclaimed followers are weak. Thus, Hume's challenge is met by Leibniz, by Wolff and Baumgarten not so much.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Wolff in Kant’s Clothing: Christian Wolff’s Influence on Kant’s Accounts of Consciousness, Self-Consciousness, and Psychology.Corey W. Dyck - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (1):44-53.
    In attempts to come to grips with Kant’s thought, the influence of the philosophy of Christian Wolff (1679-1754) is often neglected. In this paper, I consider three topics in Kant’s philosophy of mind, broadly construed, where Wolff’s influence is particularly visible: consciousness, self-consciousness, and psychology. I argue that we can better understand Kant’s particular arguments and positions within this context, but also gain a more accurate sense of which aspects of Kant’s accounts derive from the antecedent traditions and which constitute (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Being and some philosophers.Etienne Gilson - 1952 - Toronto,: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.
    The study of being was one of the main preoccupations of Gilson's scholarly and intellectual life. Being and Some Philosophers is at once a testament to the persistence of these concerns and an important landmark in the history of the question of being. The book charts the ways in which being is translated across history, from unity in Plato and substance in Aristotle to essence in Avicenna and the act of existence in Aquinas. It examines the vicissitudes of essence and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors.Lewis White Beck - 1969 - Cambridge, Mass.,: St. Augustine's Press.
    This comprehensive history of German philosophy from its medieval beginnings to near the end of the eighteenth century explores the spirit of German intellectual life and its distinctiveness from that of other countries. Beck devotes whole chapters to four great philosophers -- Nicholas of Cusa, Leibniz, Lessing, and Kant -- and extensively examines many others, including Albertus Magnus, Meister Eckhart, Paracelsus, Kepler, Mendelssohn, Wolff, and Herder. Questioning explanations of philosophy by the racial or ethnic character of its exponents, Beck's conclusion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • (1 other version)The fate of reason: German philosophy from Kant to Fichte.Frederick C. Beiser - 1987 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    The Fate of Reason is the first general history devoted to the period between Kant and Fichte, one of the most revolutionary and fertile in modern philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Newtonianism in early Enlightenment Germany, c. 1720 to 1750: metaphysics and the critique of dogmatic philosophy.Thomas Ahnert - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (3):471-491.
    The acceptance of Newton’s ideas and Newtonianism in the early German Enlightenment is usually described as hesitant and slow. Two reasons help to explain this phenomenon. One is that those who might have adopted Newtonian arguments were critics of Wolffianism. These critics, however, drew on indigenous currents of thought, pre-dating the reception of Newton in Germany and independent of Newtonian science. The other reason is that the controversies between Wolffians and their critics focused on metaphysics. Newton’s reputation, however, was that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Christian Wolff's criticisms of Spinoza.James C. Morrison - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (3):405-420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Oxford Handbook of German Philosophy in the Eighteenth Century.Corey W. Dyck, Frederick Beiser & Brandon Look (eds.) - forthcoming - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (8 other versions)Critique of pure reason.Immanuel Kant - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Paul Guyer & Allen W. Wood.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Wolff and the First Fifty Years of German Metaphysics.Corey W. Dyck - 2024 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Wolff and the First Fifty Years of German Metaphysics offers a fresh account of philosophical developments in German philosophy in the first half of the 18th century. At the centre of this book is Wolff's seminal text on metaphysics, the Deutsche Metaphysik of 1719, a text that modernized and advanced German philosophy but also provoked a vigorous intellectual controversy which informed and animated German thought through the decades until Kant's later philosophical revolution. -/- Corey W. Dyck draws extensively on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • „Partes Metaphysicae sunt duae: Deus & Mentes.“ Anmerkungen zur Entstehung und Entwicklung der Psychologie als Metaphysica specialis zwischen Rudolph Goclenius und Christian Wolff.Gideon Stiening - 2004 - In Oliver-Pierre Rudolph & Jean-François Goubet (eds.), Die Psychologie Christian Wolffs: Systematische und historische Untersuchungen. De Gruyter. pp. 207-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant's Critique of Pure Reason and the Method of Metaphysics.Gabriele Gava - 2023 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    In two often neglected passages of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant submits that the Critique is a 'treatise' or a 'doctrine of method'. These passages are puzzling because the Critique is only cursorily concerned with identifying adequate procedures of argument for philosophy. In this book, Gabriele Gava argues that these passages point out that the Critique is the doctrine of method of metaphysics. Doctrines of method have the task of showing that a given science is indeed a science because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wolff on Substance, Power, and Force.Nabeel Hamid - 2024 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 62 (4):615-638.
    This paper argues that Wolff’s rejection of Leibnizian monads is rooted in a disagreement concerning the general notion of substance. Briefly, whereas Leibniz defines substance in terms of activity, Wolff retains a broadly scholastic and Cartesian conception of substance as that which per se subsists and sustains accidents. One consequence of this difference is that it leads Wolff to interpret Leibniz’s concept of a constantly striving force as denoting a feature of substance separate from its static powers, and not as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mereology and mathematics: Christian Wolff's foundational programme.Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (6):1151-1172.
    ABSTRACTHow did the traditional doctrine of parts and wholes evolve into contemporary formal mereology? This paper argues that a crucial missing link may lie in the early modern and especially Wolf...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Die Seele und ihre Vermögen: Kants Metaphysik des Mentalen in der Kritik der reinen Vernunft.Stefan Heßbrüggen-Walter - 2004 - Mentis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • John Locke in the German Enlightenment: an Interpretation.Klaus P. Fischer - 1975 - Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (3):431.
    A favorite assumption of anglo-American scholarship is that locke's influence "pervaded the eighteenth century with an almost scriptural authority." examining the philosophy of the german enlightenment, This essay disputes the exaggerated importance ascribed to locke in the eighteenth century. Locke's influence was always limited by native traditions inimical to his thought. His empiricism could not compete with the leibniz-Wolff system in which all german philosophers, Including the lockean sympathizers, Were educated. It is true that around mid-Century and beyond locke attracted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What Is a Maxim?Patricia Kitcher - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):215-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Philosophy, geometry, and logic in Leibniz, Wolff, and the early Kant.Daniel Sutherland - 2010 - In Michael Friedman, Mary Domski & Michael Dickson (eds.), Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science. Open Court.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Wolffian Paradigm and its Discontent: Kant’s Containment Definition of Analyticity in Historical Context.R. Lanier Anderson - 2005 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 87 (1):22-74.
    I defend Kant’s definition of analyticity in terms of concept “containment”, which has engendered widespread scepticism. Kant deployed a clear, technical notion of containment based on ideas standard within traditional logic, notably genus/species hierarchies formed via logical division. Kant’s analytic/synthetic distinction thereby undermines the logico-metaphysical system of Christian Wolff, showing that the Wolffian paradigm lacks the expressive power even to represent essential knowledge, including elementary mathematics, and so cannot provide an adequate system of philosophy. The results clarify the extent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The existence of God, natural theology and Christian Wolff.Charles A. Corr - 1973 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (2):105 - 118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Christian Wolff's German Ethics: New Essays.Sonja Schierbaum, Michael Walschots & John Walsh (eds.) - 2024 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This is a collection of sixteen essays by a diverse group of international scholars that offers a wide-ranging and contemporary perspective on the major aspects of Christian Wolff’s ethics. The volume focuses on Wolff’s German Ethics, arguably his most important and influential text on moral philosophy, but many of the chapters also consider the development of the basic tenets of Wolff’s moral theory in his later Latin writings. The contributions cover a range of topics, including the systematic structure of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)On the Necessity and Nature of Simples: Leibniz, Wolff, Baumgarten, and the Pre-Critical Kant.Eric Watkins - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3:261-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Die Psychologie Christian Wolffs: Systematische und historische Untersuchungen.Oliver-Pierre Rudolph & Jean-François Goubet (eds.) - 2004 - De Gruyter.
    Die Psychologie nimmt im Werk Christian Wolffs (1679-1754) eine zentrale Stellung ein. Sie begründet die Logik und die praktische Philosophie mit Naturrecht, Ethik, Politik und Ökonomik. Der vorliegende Band geht den vielfältigen Problemen nach, die sich mit Wolffs Konzeption einer rationalen und einer empirischen Psychologie einerseits, ihrer Grundlegungsfunktion innerhalb des Wolffschen Systems der Philosophie andererseits ergeben. Darüber hinaus stellt er die Psychologie Wolffs in den philosophie- und wissenschaftsgeschichtlichen Kontext von der Scholastik bis zur kritischen Philosophie Immanuel Kants.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Christian Wolff über motivierende Gründe und handlungsrelevante Irrtümer.Sonja Schierbaum - 2022 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 104 (1):131-163.
    In this paper, I discuss Christian Wolff’s conception of motivating and normative reasons. My aim is to show that in the discussion of error cases, Wolff pursues a strategy that is strikingly similar to the strategy of contemporary defenders of nicht-psychologist accounts of motivating reasons. According to many nicht-psychologist views, motivating reasons are facts. My aim is to show that Wolff’s motivation in pursuing this strategy is very different. The point is that due to his commitment to the Principle of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz’s Justification of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (Mainly) in the Correspondence with Clarke.Paul Lodge - 2018 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 21 (1):69-91.
    The aim of this paper is to shed light on Leibniz’s justification of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. It approaches this issue through a close textual analysis of the correspondence with Samuel Clarke and a more abstruse and lesser-known writing, ‘Leibniz’s Philosophical Dream’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Christian Wolff 1679-1754. Interpretationen zu seiner Philosophie und deren Wirkung.Werner Schneiders - 1985 - Studia Leibnitiana 17 (1):111-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cet esprit de profondeur: Christian Wolff, l'ontologie et la métaphysique.Jean-Paul Paccioni - 2006 - Vrin.
    L'eloge qu'adresse Kant au Geist der Grundlichkeit de Christian Wolff est reste celebre, mais comme une anecdote. Il engage pourtant l'approche de la metaphysique en tant que systeme traite de maniere scientifique. Le sens de la philosophie moderne s'y joue, tel qu'il sera repris et discute de l'idealisme allemand jusqu'a Husserl et Heidegger. En partant d'une analyse de cet eloge, et de son articulation au probleme general de la raison pure, cet ouvrage etudie comment la question du fondement est a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Between Wolff and Kant: Merian's theory of apperception.Udo Thiel - 1996 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (2):213-232.
    Between Wolff and Kant: Merian's Theory of Apperception UDO THIEL IT IS WELL KNOWN that the nodon of apperception or self-consciousness is central to Kant's theoretical philosophy. Kant introduces the notion in one of the crucial parts of the Critique of Pure Reason, the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories, and assigns it an important role in his critique of traditional metaphysics of the soul in the Transcendental Dialectic.' It is also well known that Kant did not invent the term "apperception." (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations