Switch to: Citations

References in:

Seeing White and Wrong: Reid on the Role of Sensations in Perception, with a Focus on Color Perception

In Thomas Reid on Mind, Knowledge, and Value (Mind Association Occasional Series). Oxford University Press. pp. 100-123 (2015)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. When warrant transmits.James Pryor - 2012 - In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Consider the argument: Circus-1 Men in clown suits are handing out tickets. So, probably: Circus-2 There’s a circus in town. So: Circus-3 There’s an entertainment venue in town. Presumably you’d be able to warrantedly believe Circus-2 on the basis of Circus-1. And we can suppose you’re reasonably certain that wherever there are circuses, there are entertainment venues. So you’d seem to be in a position to reasonably go on to infer Circus-3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • The Perils of Dogmatism.Crispin Wright - 2007 - In Susana Nuccetelli & Gary Seay (eds.), Themes From G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Fixing the Transmission: The New Mooreans.Ram Neta - 2007 - In Susana Nuccetelli & Gary Seay (eds.), Themes From G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free)?Crispin Wright - 2004 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78 (1):167–212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   483 citations  
  • Did Reid Hold Coherentist Views ?Daniel Schulthess - 1989 - In M. Dalgarno & Eva Matthews (eds.), The Philosophy of Thomas Reid. Reidel. pp. p.193-203..
    The article criticizes the interpretation of Thomas Reid’s philosophy as a form of coherentism put forward by Lehrer and Smith. In the author’s view Reid’s “first principles”, which govern the activities of our faculties, rely on a correspondence theory of truth. At the same time the rightness of our first principles in conjunction with the fact that the world is structured in such a way that true judgements about it do not lead to contradiction entails that our “doxastic system” (i.e. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 1. Taking Pragmatism Seriously.Hilary Putnam & Ruth Anna Putnam - 2017 - In Hilary Putnam & Ruth Anna Putnam (eds.), Pragmatism as a Way of Life: The Lasting Legacy of William James and John Dewey, D. Macarthur (ed.). Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. 13-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A coherence theory of truth and knowledge.Donald Davidson - 1986 - In Ernest LePore (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Cambridge: Blackwell. pp. 307-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   482 citations  
  • Reid on the real foundation of the primary-secondary quality distinction.James Van Cleve - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proof of an External World.G. E. Moore - 1939 - H. Milford.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Thomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention.Gideon Yaffe - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):165-194.
    It was common enough in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries to find philosophers holding the position that for something to be ‘in the mind’ and for that mind to be conscious of it are one and the same thing. The thought is that consciousness is a relation between a mind and a mental entity playing the same role as the relation of inherence found between a substance and qualities belonging to it. What it is, on this view, for something to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reid Versus Berkeley on the Inverted Retinal Image.James Van Cleve - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):425-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reid Versus Berkeley on the Inverted Retinal Image.James Van Cleve - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):425-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Foundationalism, epistemic principles, and the cartesian circle.James Van Cleve - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (1):55-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • When Transmission Fails.Chris Tucker - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (4):497-529.
    The Neo-Moorean Deduction (I have a hand, so I am not a brain-in-a-vat) and the Zebra Deduction (the creature is a zebra, so isn’t a cleverly disguised mule) are notorious. Crispin Wright, Martin Davies, Fred Dretske, and Brian McLaughlin, among others, argue that these deductions are instances of transmission failure. That is, they argue that these deductions cannot transmit justification to their conclusions. I contend, however, that the notoriety of these deductions is undeserved. My strategy is to clarify, attack, defend, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Thomas Reid on acquired perception.Rebecca Copenhaver - 2010 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (3):285-312.
    Thomas Reid's distinction between original and acquired perception is not merely metaphysical; it has psychological and phenomenological stories to tell. Psychologically, acquired perception provides increased sensitivity to features in the environment. Phenomenologically, Reid's theory resists the notion that original perception is exhaustive of perceptual experience. James Van Cleve has argued that most cases of acquired perception do not count as perception and so do not pose a threat to Reid's direct realism. I argue that acquired perception is genuine perception and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Thomas Reid and the theory of taste.Dabney Townsend - 2003 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61 (4):341–351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Virtue perspectivism: A response to Foley and Fumerton.Ernest Sosa - 1994 - Philosophical Issues 5:29-50.
    I am grateful to both Richards, Foley and Fumerton, for the time and attention that they have given to my work. I have certainly learned from their excellent comments, just as I expected. Given the constraints, however, I must be selective in my response. First of all, I will aim to present my view of human knowledge in a broader context. Against this background I will then respond to several of the points they have made.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aesthetics and the World at Large.James Shelley - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2):169-183.
    l Carroll, that there is no reason to think that an aesthetic theory of art cannot do justice to art in its relation to the extra-artistic world. My argument depends on a reinterpretation of the aesthetic theory of Francis Hutcheson, according to which Hutcheson does not hold aesthetic perception to be non-epistemic, as Peter Kivy has maintained.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reidian Evidence.Patrick Rysiew - 2005 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 3 (2):107-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reid and epistemic naturalism.Patrick Rysiew - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):437–456.
    Central to the contemporary dispute over 'naturalizing epistemology' is the question of the continuity of epistemology with science, i.e., how far purely descriptive, psychological matters can or should inform the traditional evaluative epistemological enterprise. Thus all parties tend to agree that the distinction between psychology and epistemology corresponds to a firm fact/value distinction. This is something Reid denies with respect to the first principles of common sense: while insisting on the continuity of epistemology with the rest of science, he does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description.Bertrand Russell - 1911 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 11:108--28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   378 citations  
  • Pragmatism, Relativism, and Irrationalism.Richard Rorty - 1980 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 53 (6):717 - 738.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The aesthetics of Thomas Reid.David O. Robbins - 1942 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 2 (5):30-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Justice And Resentment In Hume, Reid, And Smith.Michael S. Pritchard - 2008 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 6 (1):59-70.
    Adam Smith and Thomas Reid follow Joseph Butler's lead in discussing the moral significance of resentment in great detail. David Hume does not. For Smith and Reid, resentment reveals shortcomings in Hume's attempt to ground justice solely in terms of self-interest and public utility. This can be seen most clearly in Reid's critique of Hume's response to the sensible knave. Reid argues that Hume's appeal to our integrity can have force only if Hume concedes that there are elements of justice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A criterion for meaning change.Kathryn Pyne Parsons - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (6):367 - 396.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Symposiums papers: Sensation and perception in Reid.George S. Pappas - 1989 - Noûs 23 (2):155-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Causation and perception in Reid.George S. Pappas - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (4):763-766.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reid on fictional objects and the way of ideas.Ryan Nichols - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (209):582-601.
    I argue that Reid adopts a form of Meinongianism about fictional objects because of, not in spite of, his common sense philosophy. According to 'the way of ideas', thoughts take representational states as their immediate intentional objects. In contrast, Reid endorses a direct theory of conception and a heady thesis of first-person privileged access to the contents of our thoughts. He claims that thoughts about centaurs are thoughts of non-existent objects, not thoughts about mental intermediaries, adverbial states or general concepts. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Beauty and objectivity in Thomas Reid.James Manns - 1988 - British Journal of Aesthetics 28 (2):119-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Skeptic and The Madman: The Proto‐Pragmatism of Thomas Reid.Erik Lundestad - 2006 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 4 (2):125-137.
    Even though the philosophy of common sense is not justifi able as such, the assump- tion upon which it rests, namely that there are things which we are not in position to doubt is correct. The reason why Thomas Reid was unable to bring this assumption out in a justifi able manner is that his views, both on knowledge and nature, are to be considered dogmatic. American pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce and John Dewey on the other hand, may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Dispositional theories of color and the claims of common sense.Janet Levin - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 100 (2):151-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Reid on Primary and Secondary Qualities.Keith Lehrer - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):184-191.
    Reid defends the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. He does so in spite of accepting Berkeley’s critique of Locke on this issue and rejecting the Cartesian thesis that the distinction is based on reason. Reid contends that we have a clear, direct, and distinct conception of primary qualities but not of secondary qualities. We shall attempt to explain how Reid could defend the distinction while rejecting the resemblance theory of Locke and the rationalistic theory of Descartes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Reid on Testimony and Perception.Keith Lehrer - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 11:21-38.
    Reid defended common sense against scepticism by appeal to the claim that our faculties should be considered trustworthy until some argument proves them to be untrustworthy. He believed, of course, that no such argument would be forthcoming. In this paper, we shall investigate Reid's defense of the faculty of perception and the evidence of the senses by analogy with the faculty of language and the evidence of testimony. Reid argued that the evidence of testimony should be trusted unless there is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reid on Testimony and Perception.Keith Lehrer & John-Christian Smith - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (sup1):21-38.
    Reid defended common sense against scepticism by appeal to the claim that our faculties should be considered trustworthy until some argument proves them to be untrustworthy. He believed, of course, that no such argument would be forthcoming. In this paper, we shall investigate Reid's defense of the faculty of perception and the evidence of the senses by analogy with the faculty of language and the evidence of testimony. Reid argued that the evidence of testimony should be trusted unless there is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Thomas Reid and the Expression Theory of Art.Peter Kivy - 1978 - The Monist 61 (2):167-183.
    I mean by "the expression theory of art" the theory which holds that the expression of emotion is the essential property of art. I mean by "a theory of artistic expression" any theory which gives an account of how works of art express emotions. My argument is that thomas reid, In contrast to his contemporaries and immediate predecessors, Came very close to holding not merely a theory of artistic expression but the expression theory of art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • "Lectures on the Fine Arts": An Unpublished Manuscript of Thomas Reid's.Peter Kivy - 1970 - Journal of the History of Ideas 31 (1):17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Evidence: Fundamental concepts and the phenomenal conception.Thomas Kelly - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (5):933-955.
    The concept of evidence is among the central concerns of epistemology broadly construed. As such, it has long engaged the intellectual energies of both philosophers of science and epistemologists of a more traditional variety. Here I briefly survey some of the more important ideas to have emerged from this tradition of reflection. I then look somewhat more closely at an issue that has recently come to the fore, largely as a result of Williamson's Knowledge and Its Limits: that of whether (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • How to speak of the colors.Mark Johnston - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (3):221-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   539 citations  
  • Color Primitivism.David R. Hilbert & Alex Byrne - 2006 - Erkenntnis 66 (1-2):73 - 105.
    The typical kind of color realism is reductive: the color properties are identified with properties specified in other terms (as ways of altering light, for instance). If no reductive analysis is available — if the colors are primitive sui generis properties — this is often taken to be a convincing argument for eliminativism. That is, realist primitivism is usually thought to be untenable. The realist preference for reductive theories of color over the last few decades is particularly striking in light (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • A Spectral Reflectance Doth Not A Color Make.C. L. Hardin - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy 100 (4):191-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Reid and Condillac on Sensation and Perception.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2008 - Southwest Philosophy Review 24 (1):191-200.
    In order to illustrate the difference between sensation and perception, Reid imagines a blind man that by ‘some strange distemper’ has lost all his notions of external objects, but has retained the power of sensation and reasoning. Reid argues that since sensations do not resemble external objects, the blind man could not possibly infer from them any notion of primary qualities. Condillac proposed a similar thought experiment in the Treatise on Sensations. I argue that Condillac can reach a conclusion opposite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   221 citations  
  • Reid: Conception, Representation and Innate Ideas.Roger D. Gallie - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (2):315-336.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXIII, Number 2, November 1997, pp. 315-335 Reid: Conception, Representation and Innate Ideas ROGER D. GALLIE Section I of this paper begins with a presentation of Thomas Reid's doctrine of the signification of words, of what words signify or represent. That presentation serves to introduce a problem of interpretation, namely, what Reid thinks the connection is between conceiving something and grasping what a term for it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Observation reconsidered.Jerry Fodor - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (March):23-43.
    Several arguments are considered which purport to demonstrate the impossibility of theory-neutral observation. The most important of these infers the continuity of observation with theory from the presumed continuity of perception with cognition, a doctrine widely espoused in recent cognitive psychology. An alternative psychological account of the relation between cognition and perception is proposed and its epistemological consequences for the observation/theory distinction are then explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   288 citations  
  • Theory change and the indeterminacy of reference.Hartry Field - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (14):462-481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   223 citations  
  • Hume and Reid on the Perception of Hardness.Lorne Falkenstein - 2002 - Hume Studies 28 (1):27-48.
    This paper considers an objection to the Humean view that perception involves introspective acquaintance with representative images. The objection, originally raised by Thomas Reid and recently endorsed by Nicholas Wolterstorff, states that no representative image can be hard, and concludes that acquaintance with such images cannot therefore account for our perception of hardness. I argue in response that a case has not been made for denying that representative images can be hard. Hardness, as understood by Hume and Reid, is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Descartes, epistemic principles, epistemic circularity, and scientia.Keith DeRose - 1992 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73 (3):220-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Epistemic Entitlement, Warrant Transmission and Easy Knowledge.Martin Davies - 2004 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78 (1):213-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • II_— _Martin Davies: Epistemic Entitlement, Warrant Transmission and Easy Knowledge.Martin Davies - 2004 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 78 (1):213-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations