Switch to: Citations

References in:

The philosophy of computer science

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2013)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A novel defense of scientific realism.Jarrett Leplin - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Leplin attempts to reinstate the common sense idea that theoretical knowledge is achievable, indeed that its achievement is part of the means to progress in empirical knowledge. He sketches the genesis of the skeptical position, then introduces his argument for Minimalist Scientific Realism -- the requirement that novel predicitons be explained, and the claim that only realism about scientific theories can explain the importance of novel prediction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • Turing's golden: How well Turing's work stands today.Justin Leiber - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (1):13-46.
    A. M. Turing has bequeathed us a conceptulary including 'Turing, or Turing-Church, thesis', 'Turing machine', 'universal Turing machine', 'Turing test' and 'Turing structures', plus other unnamed achievements. These include a proof that any formal language adequate to express arithmetic contains undecidable formulas, as well as achievements in computer science, artificial intelligence, mathematics, biology, and cognitive science. Here it is argued that these achievements hang together and have prospered well in the 50 years since Turing's death.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reasoning and computation in leibniz.Leen Spruit & Guglielmo Tamburrini - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (1):1-14.
    Leibniz's overall view of the relationship between reasoning and computation is discussed on the basis of two broad claims that one finds in his writings, concerning respectively the nature of human reasoning and the possibility of replacing human thinking by a mechanical procedure. A joint examination of these claims enables one to appreciate the wide scope of Leibniz's interests for mechanical procedures, concerning a variety of philosophical themes further developed both in later logical investigations and in methodological contributions to cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Metaphors We Live by.Max Black - 1980 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (2):208-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   702 citations  
  • Conceptual metaphor in everyday language.George Lakoff & Mark Johnson - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (8):453-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.David Bohm - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):377-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1157 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • The dual nature of technical artefacts.Peter Kroes & Anthonie Meijers - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (1):1-4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on rules and private language: an elementary exposition.Saul A. Kripke - 1982 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In this book Saul Kripke brings his powerful philosophical intelligence to bear on Wittgenstein's analysis of the notion of following a rule.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   753 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.Paul Horwich - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (1):163-171.
    Discussion of Wittgenstein's philosophy has suffered from a scarcity of commentators who understand his work well enough to explain it in their own words. Apart from certain notable exceptions, all too many advocates and critics alike have tended merely to repeat slogans, with approval or ridicule as the case may be. The result has been an unusual degree of polarization and acrimony—some philosophers abandoning normal critical standards, falling under the spell and becoming fanatical supporters; and others taking an equally extreme (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   377 citations  
  • Vacuous names and fictional entities.Saul A. Kripke - 2011 - HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology 8 (2):676-706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory.Stephen M. Kosslyn - 1981 - Psychological Review 88 (1):46-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Foundations of AI: The big issues.David Kirsh - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 47 (1-3):3-30.
    The objective of research in the foundations of Al is to explore such basic questions as: What is a theory in Al? What are the most abstract assumptions underlying the competing visions of intelligence? What are the basic arguments for and against each assumption? In this essay I discuss five foundational issues: (1) Core Al is the study of conceptualization and should begin with knowledge level theories. (2) Cognition can be studied as a disembodied process without solving the symbol grounding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Programming Approach to Computability.A. J. Kfoury, Robert N. Moll & Michael A. Arbib - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):289-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Analysis of Matter.E. H. Kennard & Bertrand Russell - 1928 - Philosophical Review 37 (4):382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • A Philosopher Looks at Science. [REVIEW]Nicholas Rescher - 1959 - Journal of Philosophy 56 (24):970-973.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Thinking machines: Some fundamental confusions. [REVIEW]John T. Kearns - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (2):269-87.
    This paper explores Church's Thesis and related claims madeby Turing. Church's Thesis concerns computable numerical functions, whileTuring's claims concern both procedures for manipulating uninterpreted marksand machines that generate the results that these procedures would yield. Itis argued that Turing's claims are true, and that they support (the truth of)Church's Thesis. It is further argued that the truth of Turing's and Church'sTheses has no interesting consequences for human cognition or cognitiveabilities. The Theses don't even mean that computers can do as much (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mental Models in Cognitive Science.P. N. Johnson-Laird - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (1):71-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Mental models in cognitive science.P. N. Johnson-Laird - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (1):71-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Translation, interpretation and understanding.Richard C. Jennings - 1988 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 18 (3):343-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Counterpossibles in Science: The Case of Relative Computability.Matthias Jenny - 2018 - Noûs 52 (3):530-560.
    I develop a theory of counterfactuals about relative computability, i.e. counterfactuals such as 'If the validity problem were algorithmically decidable, then the halting problem would also be algorithmically decidable,' which is true, and 'If the validity problem were algorithmically decidable, then arithmetical truth would also be algorithmically decidable,' which is false. These counterfactuals are counterpossibles, i.e. they have metaphysically impossible antecedents. They thus pose a challenge to the orthodoxy about counterfactuals, which would treat them as uniformly true. What’s more, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • What is computer ethics?James H. Moor - 1985 - Metaphilosophy 16 (4):266-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • Can semantics be syntactic?Neal Jahren - 1990 - Synthese 82 (3):309-28.
    The author defends John R. Searle's Chinese Room argument against a particular objection made by William J. Rapaport called the Korean Room. Foundational issues such as the relationship of strong AI to human mentality and the adequacy of the Turing Test are discussed. Through undertaking a Gedankenexperiment similar to Searle's but which meets new specifications given by Rapaport for an AI system, the author argues that Rapaport's objection to Searle does not stand and that Rapaport's arguments seem convincing only because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The faculty of language: what's special about it?Ray Jackendoff & Steven Pinker - 2005 - Cognition 95 (2):201-236.
    We examine the question of which aspects of language are uniquely human and uniquely linguistic in light of recent suggestions by Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch that the only such aspect is syntactic recursion, the rest of language being either specific to humans but not to language (e.g. words and concepts) or not specific to humans (e.g. speech perception). We find the hypothesis problematic. It ignores the many aspects of grammar that are not recursive, such as phonology, morphology, case, agreement, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • How a cockpit remembers its speeds.Edwin Hutchins - 1995 - Cognitive Science 19 (3):265--288.
    Cognitive science normally takes the individual agent as its unit of analysis. In many human endeavors, however, the outcomes of interest are not determined entirely by the information processing properties of individuals. Nor can they be inferred from the properties of the individual agents, alone, no matter how detailed the knowledge of the properties of those individuals may be. In commercial aviation, for example, the successful completion of a flight is produced by a system that typically includes two or more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  • Chess As An Art Form.P. N. Humble - 1993 - British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (1):59-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ascribing Functions to Technical Artefacts: A Challenge to Etiological Accounts of Functions.Wybo Houkes & Pieter E. Vermaas - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2):261-289.
    The aim of this paper is to evaluate etiological accounts of functions for the domain of technical artefacts. Etiological theories ascribe functions to items on the basis of the causal histories of those items; they apply relatively straightforwardly to the biological domain, in which neo‐Darwinian evolutionary theory provides a well‐developed and generally accepted background for describing the causal histories of biological items. Yet there is no well‐developed and generally accepted theory for describing the causal history of artefacts, so the application (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Review of Douglas Richard Hofstadter: Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid[REVIEW]Russell Hardin - 1980 - Ethics 90 (2):310-311.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid.Douglas Richard Hofstadter - 1979 - Hassocks, England: Basic Books.
    A young scientist and mathematician explores the mystery and complexity of human thought processes from an interdisciplinary point of view.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   505 citations  
  • Alan Turing.Andrew Hodges - 2000 - Minds and Machines.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Existence assumptions in knowledge representation.Graeme Hirst - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 49 (1-3):199-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What an Algorithm Is.Robin K. Hill - 2016 - Philosophy and Technology 29 (1):35-59.
    The algorithm, a building block of computer science, is defined from an intuitive and pragmatic point of view, through a methodological lens of philosophy rather than that of formal computation. The treatment extracts properties of abstraction, control, structure, finiteness, effective mechanism, and imperativity, and intentional aspects of goal and preconditions. The focus on the algorithm as a robust conceptual object obviates issues of correctness and minimality. Neither the articulation of an algorithm nor the dynamic process constitute the algorithm itself. Analysis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Are Logic and Mathematics Identical?Leon Henkin - 1964 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 29 (3):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What Is a Computer?Patrick J. Hayes - 1997 - The Monist 80 (3):389-404.
    An e-mail discussion can be rendered into print in several ways. Rather than trying to imitate a genuine conversation, this is a personal essay containing comments and replies by the other contributors. Most of the substantial points made in the e-mail discussion are contained here, although not always in the order they happened.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • What Is a Computer?Patrick J. Hayes - 1997 - The Monist 80 (3):389-404.
    An e-mail discussion can be rendered into print in several ways. Rather than trying to imitate a genuine conversation, this is a personal essay containing comments and replies by the other contributors. Most of the substantial points made in the e-mail discussion are contained here, although not always in the order they happened.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Changing the Ideology and Culture of Philosophy: Not by Reason (Alone).Sally Haslanger - 2008 - Hypatia 23 (2):210-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Preface.Stevan Harnad - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (4):377-378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation; cognition isn't.Stevan Harnad - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (4):379-90.
    Computation is interpretable symbol manipulation. Symbols are objects that are manipulated on the basis of rules operating only on theirshapes, which are arbitrary in relation to what they can be interpreted as meaning. Even if one accepts the Church/Turing Thesis that computation is unique, universal and very near omnipotent, not everything is a computer, because not everything can be given a systematic interpretation; and certainly everything can''t be givenevery systematic interpretation. But even after computers and computation have been successfully distinguished (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Calculating Instruments and Machines.Douglas R. Hartree - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (4):347-347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Abstract objects.Bob Hale - 1988 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Quantum algorithms: Philosophical lessons.Amit Hagar - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):233-247.
    I discuss the philosophical implications that the rising new science of quantum computing may have on the philosophy of computer science. While quantum algorithms leave the notion of Turing-Computability intact, they may re-describe the abstract space of computational complexity theory hence militate against the autonomous character of some of the concepts and categories of computer science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique.Adolf Grünbaum - 1984 - Berkeley: University of California Press.
    This study is a philosophical critique of the foundations of Sigmund Freud's psychoanalysis. As such, it also takes cognizance of his claim that psychoanalysis has the credentials of a natural science. It shows that the reasoning on which Freud rested the major hypotheses of his edifice was fundamentally flawed, even if the probity of the clinical observations he adduced were not in question. Moreover, far from deserving to be taken at face value, clinical data from the psychoanalytic treatment setting are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • Problems for a Philosophy of Software Engineering.Stefan Gruner - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (2):275-299.
    On the basis of an earlier contribution to the philosophy of computer science by Amnon Eden, this essay discusses to what extent Eden’s ‘paradigms’ of computer science can be transferred or applied to software engineering. This discussion implies an analysis of how software engineering and computer science are related to each other. The essay concludes that software engineering can neither be fully subsumed by computer science, nor vice versa. Consequently, also the philosophies of computer science and software engineering—though related to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Meinong.Reinhardt Grossmann - 1974 - New York: Routledge.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Meinong.Peter Lamarque - 1975 - Philosophical Quarterly 25 (99):170-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Informatics and professional responsibility.Donald Gotterbarn - 2001 - Science and Engineering Ethics 7 (2):221-230.
    Many problems in software development can be traced to a narrow understanding of professional responsibility. The author examines ways in which software developers have tried to avoid accepting responsibility for their work. After cataloguing various types of responsibility avoidance, the author introduces an expanded concept of positive responsibility. It is argued that the adoption of this sense of positive responsibility will reduce many problems in software development.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Limiting recursion.E. Mark Gold - 1965 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 30 (1):28-48.
    A class of problems is called decidable if there is an algorithm which will give the answer to any problem of the class after a finite length of time. The purpose of this paper is to discuss the classes of problems that can be solved by infinitely long decision procedures in the following sense: An algorithm is given which, for any problem of the class, generates an infinitely long sequence of guesses. The problem will be said to be solved in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Mechanisms and the nature of causation.Stuart S. Glennan - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (1):49--71.
    In this paper I offer an analysis of causation based upon a theory of mechanisms-complex systems whose internal parts interact to produce a system's external behavior. I argue that all but the fundamental laws of physics can be explained by reference to mechanisms. Mechanisms provide an epistemologically unproblematic way to explain the necessity which is often taken to distinguish laws from other generalizations. This account of necessity leads to a theory of causation according to which events are causally related when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   432 citations  
  • How models are used to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):742-752.
    Most recent philosophical thought about the scientific representation of the world has focused on dyadic relationships between language-like entities and the world, particularly the semantic relationships of reference and truth. Drawing inspiration from diverse sources, I argue that we should focus on the pragmatic activity of representing, so that the basic representational relationship has the form: Scientists use models to represent aspects of the world for specific purposes. Leaving aside the terms "law" and "theory," I distinguish principles, specific conditions, models, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Edmund L. Gettier - 1963 - Analysis 23 (6):121-123.
    Russian translation of Gettier E. L. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? // Analysis, vol. 23, 1963. Translated by Lev Lamberov with kind permission of the author.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1005 citations