Switch to: References

Citations of:

Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity

[author unknown]
Studia Logica 54 (2):261-266 (1975)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Knowledge as Fact-Tracking True Belief.Fred Adams, John A. Barker & Murray Clarke - 2017 - Manuscrito 40 (4):1-30.
    ABSTRACT Drawing inspiration from Fred Dretske, L. S. Carrier, John A. Barker, and Robert Nozick, we develop a tracking analysis of knowing according to which a true belief constitutes knowledge if and only if it is based on reasons that are sensitive to the fact that makes it true, that is, reasons that wouldn’t obtain if the belief weren’t true. We show that our sensitivity analysis handles numerous Gettier-type cases and lottery problems, blocks pathways leading to skepticism, and validates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Grafted frames and S1 -completeness.Beihai Zhou - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):1324-1338.
    A grafted frame is a new kind of frame which combines a modal frame and some relevance frames. A grafted model consists of a grafted frame and a truth-value assignment. In this paper, the grafted frame and the grafted model are constructed and used to show the completeness of S1. The implications of S1-completeness are discussed. A grafted frame does not combine two kinds of frames simply by putting relations defined in the components together. That is, the resulting grafted frame (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On recent applications of paraconsistent logic: an exploratory literature review.A. Zamansky - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (4):382-391.
    This paper aims to empirically explore the state of practical applications of paraconsistent logics. To this end, we performed an exploratory literature review, analysing papers published between the years 2015 and 2018. Paraconsistent formalisms based on annotated logics are practically the sole type of approach we found to be applied in engineering applications. The engineering problems solved by paraconsistent approaches were mainly in the fields of signal and image processing and decision support. The results of our exploratory review indicate that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unphilosophical probability.Sandy L. Zabell - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):358-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Actuality and Essence.William G. Lycan & Stewart Shapiro - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11 (1):343-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Cohen on contraposition.N. E. Wetherick - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):358-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competence, performance, and ignorance.Robert W. Weisberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):356-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The importance of cognitive illusions.Peter Wason - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):356-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Independent forebrain and brainstem controls for arousal and sleep.Jaime R. Villablanca - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):494-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The defective conditional in mathematics.Mathieu Vidal - 2014 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24 (1-2):169-179.
    This article focuses on defective conditionals ? namely indicative conditionals whose antecedents are false and whose truth-values therefore cannot be determined. The problem is to decide which formal connective can adequately represent this usage. Classical logic renders defective conditionals true whereas traditional mathematics dismisses them as irrelevant. This difference in treatment entails that, at the propositional level, classical logic validates some sentences that are intuitively false in plane geometry. With two proofs, I show that the same flaw is shared by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • 2009 North American Annual Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Alasdair Urquhart - 2009 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 (4):441-464.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • L. J. Cohen, again: On the evaluation of inductive intuitions.Amos Tversky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):354-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The relevance of premises to conclusions of core proofs.Neil Tennant - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (4):743-784.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Logic, Mathematics, and the A Priori, Part II: Core Logic as Analytic, and as the Basis for Natural Logicism.Neil Tennant - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (3):321-344.
    We examine the sense in which logic is a priori, and explain how mathematical theories can be dichotomized non-trivially into analytic and synthetic portions. We argue that Core Logic contains exactly the a-priori-because-analytically-valid deductive principles. We introduce the reader to Core Logic by explaining its relationship to other logical systems, and stating its rules of inference. Important metatheorems about Core Logic are reported, and its important features noted. Core Logic can serve as the basis for a foundational program that could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Cut for classical core logic.Neil Tennant - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):236-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Defining LFIs and LFUs in extensions of infectious logics.Szmuc Damian Enrique - 2016 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 26 (4):286-314.
    The aim of this paper is to explore the peculiar case of infectious logics, a group of systems obtained generalizing the semantic behavior characteristic of the -fragment of the logics of nonsense, such as the ones due to Bochvar and Halldén, among others. Here, we extend these logics with classical negations, and we furthermore show that some of these extended systems can be properly regarded as logics of formal inconsistency and logics of formal undeterminedness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Inferential competence: right you are, if you think you are.Stephen P. Stich - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):353-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Some questions regarding the rationality of a demonstration of human rationality.Robert J. Sternberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):352-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle’s assertoric syllogistic and modern relevance logic.Philipp Steinkrüger - 2015 - Synthese 192 (5):1413-1444.
    This paper sets out to evaluate the claim that Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic is a relevance logic or shows significant similarities with it. I prepare the grounds for a meaningful comparison by extracting the notion of relevance employed in the most influential work on modern relevance logic, Anderson and Belnap’s Entailment. This notion is characterized by two conditions imposed on the concept of validity: first, that some meaning content is shared between the premises and the conclusion, and second, that the premises (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tracking reasons with extensions of relevant logics.Shawn Standefer - 2019 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 27 (4):543-569.
    In relevant logics, necessary truths need not imply each other. In justification logic, necessary truths need not all be justified by the same reason. There is an affinity to these two approaches that suggests their pairing will provide good logics for tracking reasons in a fine-grained way. In this paper, I will show how to extend relevant logics with some of the basic operators of justification logic in order to track justifications or reasons. I will define and study three kinds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Trees for E.Shawn Standefer - 2018 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 26 (3):300-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Translations Between Gentzen–Prawitz and Jaśkowski–Fitch Natural Deduction Proofs.Shawn Standefer - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (6):1103-1134.
    Two common forms of natural deduction proof systems are found in the Gentzen–Prawitz and Jaśkowski–Fitch systems. In this paper, I provide translations between proofs in these systems, pointing out the ways in which the translations highlight the structural rules implicit in the systems. These translations work for classical, intuitionistic, and minimal logic. I then provide translations for classical S4 proofs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Artifacts and Truth-Preservation.Shawn Standefer - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Logic 12 (3):135-158.
    In Saving Truth from Paradox, Hartry Field presents and defends a theory of truth with a new conditional. In this paper, I present two criticisms of this theory, one concerning its assessments of validity and one concerning its treatment of truth-preservation claims. One way of adjusting the theory adequately responds to the truth-preservation criticism, at the cost of making the validity criticism worse. I show that in a restricted setting, Field has a way to respond to the validity criticism. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Ranking‐Theoretic Approach to Conditionals.Wolfgang Spohn - 2013 - Cognitive Science 37 (6):1074-1106.
    Conditionals somehow express conditional beliefs. However, conditional belief is a bi-propositional attitude that is generally not truth-evaluable, in contrast to unconditional belief. Therefore, this article opts for an expressivistic semantics for conditionals, grounds this semantics in the arguably most adequate account of conditional belief, that is, ranking theory, and dismisses probability theory for that purpose, because probabilities cannot represent belief. Various expressive options are then explained in terms of ranking theory, with the intention to set out a general interpretive scheme (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Worlds, Models and Descriptions.John F. Sowa - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (2):323-360.
    Since the pioneering work by Kripke and Montague, the term possible world has appeared in most theories of formal semantics for modal logics, natural languages, and knowledge-based systems. Yet that term obscures many questions about the relationships between the real world, various models of the world, and descriptions of those models in either formal languages or natural languages. Each step in that progression is an abstraction from the overwhelming complexity of the world. At the end, nothing is left but a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parts and Moments. Studies in Logic and Formal Ontology.Barry Smith (ed.) - 1982 - Philosophia Verlag.
    A collection of material on Husserl's Logical Investigations, and specifically on Husserl's formal theory of parts, wholes and dependence and its influence in ontology, logic and psychology. Includes translations of classic works by Adolf Reinach and Eugenie Ginsberg, as well as original contributions by Wolfgang Künne, Kevin Mulligan, Gilbert Null, Barry Smith, Peter M. Simons, Roger A. Simons and Dallas Willard. Documents work on Husserl's ontology arising out of early meetings of the Seminar for Austro-German Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Logic and the consistency of the world.Joseph Wayne Smith - 1986 - Erkenntnis 24 (2):105 - 114.
    The claim that nature is self-consistent has recently been contested by a number of paraconsistent logicians. In this paper I will survey the arguments which paraconsistent logicians have presented for the thesis that nature is actually inconsistent. My conclusion is that these arguments all fail.The paraconsistency programme has to date been concerned primarily with outlining the philosophical inadequacy of classical logic, and detailed discussions of issues bearing upon the philosophical adequacy of the paraconsistency position itself are not to be found (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rationality is a necessary presupposition in psychology.Jan Smedslund - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):352-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 3088 varieties a solution to the Ackermann constant problem.John K. Slaney - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):487-501.
    It is shown that there are exactly six normal DeMorgan monoids generated by the identity element alone. The free DeMorgan monoid with no generators but the identity is characterised and shown to have exactly three thousand and eighty-eight elements. This result solves the "Ackerman constant problem" of describing the structure of sentential constants in the logic R.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Conditional probability, taxicabs, and martingales.Brian Skyrms - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):351-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Linguistic Complexity and Argumentative Unity: A Lvov-Warsaw School Supplement.Peter Simons - 2014 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 36 (1):101-119.
    It is argued that the source of complexity in language is twofold: repetition, and syntactic embedding. The former enables us to return again and again to the same subject across many sentences, and to maintain the coherence of an argument. The latter is governed by two forms of complexification: the functor-argument structure of all languages and the operator-bound-variable mechanism of familiar formal languages. The former is most transparently represented by categorial grammar, and an extension of this can adequately describe the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Fmla-Fmla Axiomatizations of the Exactly True and Non-falsity Logics and Some of Their Cousins.Yaroslav Shramko, Dmitry Zaitsev & Alexander Belikov - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (5):787-808.
    In this paper we present a solution of the axiomatization problem for the Fmla-Fmla versions of the Pietz and Rivieccio exactly true logic and the non-falsity logic dual to it. To prove the completeness of the corresponding binary consequence systems we introduce a specific proof-theoretic formalism, which allows us to deal simultaneously with two consequence relations within one logical system. These relations are hierarchically organized, so that one of them is treated as the basic for the resulting logic, and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • First-Degree Entailment and its Relatives.Yaroslav Shramko, Dmitry Zaitsev & Alexander Belikov - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (6):1291-1317.
    We consider a family of logical systems for representing entailment relations of various kinds. This family has its root in the logic of first-degree entailment formulated as a binary consequence system, i.e. a proof system dealing with the expressions of the form \, where both \ and \ are single formulas. We generalize this approach by constructing consequence systems that allow manipulating with sets of formulas, either to the right or left of the turnstile. In this way, it is possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Formal Logic for Informal Logicians.David Sherry - 2006 - Informal Logic 26 (2):199-220.
    Classical logic yields counterintuitive results for numerous propositional argument forms. The usual alternatives (modal logic, relevance logic, etc.) generate counterintuitive results of their own. The counterintuitive results create problems—especially pedagogical problems—for informal logicians who wish to use formal logic to analyze ordinary argumentation. This paper presents a system, PL– (propositional logic minus the funny business), based on the idea that paradigmatic valid argument forms arise from justificatory or explanatory discourse. PL– avoids the pedagogical difficulties without sacrificing insight into argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • ‘New continents’: The logical system of Josiah Royce.Scott L. Pratt - 2007 - History and Philosophy of Logic 28 (2):133-150.
    Josiah Royce (1855?1916) was, in addition to being the pre-eminent metaphysician at the turn of the 19th century in the USA, regarded as ?a logician of the first rank?. At the time of his death in 1916, he had begun a substantial and potentially revolutionary project in logic in which he sought to show the connection between logic and ethics, aesthetics, and metaphysics. His system was developed in light of the work of Bertrand Russell and A. B. Kempe and aimed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Implicational relevance logic is 2-exptime-complete.Sylvain Schmitz - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (2):641-661.
    We show that provability in the implicational fragment of relevance logic is complete for doubly exponential time, using reductions to and from coverability in branching vector addition systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Human rationality: Misleading linguistic analogies.Geoffrey Sampson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):350-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Normalized Natural Deduction Systems for Some Relevant Logics I: The Logic DW.Ross T. Brady - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):35 - 66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Class of All Natural Implicative Expansions of Kleene’s Strong Logic Functionally Equivalent to Łkasiewicz’s 3-Valued Logic Ł3.Gemma Robles & José M. Méndez - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (3):349-374.
    We consider the logics determined by the set of all natural implicative expansions of Kleene’s strong 3-valued matrix and select the class of all logics functionally equivalent to Łukasiewicz’s 3-valued logic Ł3. The concept of a “natural implicative matrix” is based upon the notion of a “natural conditional” defined in Tomova.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reduced Routley–Meyer semantics for the logics characterized by natural implicative expansions of Kleene’s strong 3-valued matrix.Gemma Robles - forthcoming - Logic Journal of the IGPL.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Partiality and its dual in natural implicative expansions of Kleene’s strong 3-valued matrix with only one designated value.Gemma Robles & José M. Méndez - 2019 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 27 (6):910-932.
    Equivalent overdetermined and underdetermined bivalent Belnap–Dunn type semantics for the logics determined by all natural implicative expansions of Kleene’s strong 3-valued matrix with only one designated value are provided.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Entities for Analyzing Legal Relations.Richard E. Robinson - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (4):621-630.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Belnap-Dunn semantics for natural implicative expansions of Kleene's strong three-valued matrix with two designated values.Gemma Robles & José M. Méndez - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (1):37-63.
    ABSTRACTA conditional is natural if it fulfils the three following conditions. It coincides with the classical conditional when restricted to the classical values T and F; it satisfies the Modus Ponens; and it is assigned a designated value whenever the value assigned to its antecedent is less than or equal to the value assigned to its consequent. The aim of this paper is to provide a ‘bivalent’ Belnap-Dunn semantics for all natural implicative expansions of Kleene's strong 3-valued matrix with two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Belnap-Dunn semantics for natural implicative expansions of Kleene's strong three-valued matrix II. Only one designated value.Gemma Robles, Francisco Salto & José M. Méndez - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (3):307-325.
    This paper is a sequel to ‘Belnap-Dunn semantics for natural implicative expansions of Kleene's strong three-valued matrix with two designated values’, where a ‘bivalent’ Belnap-Dunn semantics is provided for all the expansions referred to in its title. The aim of the present paper is to carry out a parallel investigation for all natural implicative expansions of Kleene's strong 3-valued matrix now with only one designated value.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Decision procedure of some relevant logics: a constructive perspective.Jacques Riche - 2005 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 15 (1):9-23.
    Some investigations into the algebraic constructive aspects of a decision procedure for various fragments of Relevant Logics are presented. Decidability of these fragments relies on S. Kripke's gentzenizations and on his combinatorial lemma known as Kripke's lemma that B. Meyer has shown equivalent to Dickson's lemma in number theory and to his own infinite divisor lemma, henceforth, Meyer's lemma or IDP. These investigations of the constructive aspects of the Kripke's-Meyer's decision procedure originate in the development of Paul Thistlewaite's “Kripke” theorem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truthmakers, entailment and necessity.Greg Restall - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (2):331 – 340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Grounding principles for (relevant) implication.Francesca Poggiolesi - 2020 - Synthese 198 (8):7351-7376.
    Most of the logics of grounding that have so far been proposed contain grounding axioms, or grounding rules, for the connectives of conjunction, disjunction and negation, but little attention has been dedicated to the implication connective. The present paper aims at repairing this situation by proposing adequate grounding principles for relevant implication. Because of the interaction between negation and implication, new grounding principles concerning negation will also arise.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Normative Argument Against Explosion.Mark Pinder - 2017 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 6 (1):61-70.
    One strategy for defending paraconsistent logics involves raising ‘normative arguments’ against the inference rule explosion. Florian Steinberger systematically criticises a wide variety of formulations of such arguments. I argue that, for one such formulation, Steinberger’s criticisms fail. I then sketch an argument, available to those who deny dialetheism, in defence of the formulation in question.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Generalized Correspondence Analysis for Three-Valued Logics.Yaroslav Petrukhin - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (3-4):423-460.
    Correspondence analysis is Kooi and Tamminga’s universal approach which generates in one go sound and complete natural deduction systems with independent inference rules for tabular extensions of many-valued functionally incomplete logics. Originally, this method was applied to Asenjo–Priest’s paraconsistent logic of paradox LP. As a result, one has natural deduction systems for all the logics obtainable from the basic three-valued connectives of LP -language) by the addition of unary and binary connectives. Tamminga has also applied this technique to the paracomplete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Automated correspondence analysis for the binary extensions of the logic of paradox.Yaroslav Petrukhin & Vasily Shangin - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):756-781.
    B. Kooi and A. Tamminga present a correspondence analysis for extensions of G. Priest’s logic of paradox. Each unary or binary extension is characterizable by a special operator and analyzable via a sound and complete natural deduction system. The present paper develops a sound and complete proof searching technique for the binary extensions of the logic of paradox.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations