Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Three Views of Theoretical Knowledge.William Demopoulos - 2011 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (1):177-205.
    Of the three views of theoretical knowledge which form the focus of this article, the first has its source in the work of Russell, the second in Ramsey, and the third in Carnap. Although very different, all three views subscribe to a principle I formulate as ‘the structuralist thesis’; they are also naturally expressed using the concept of a Ramsey sentence. I distinguish the framework of assumptions which give rise to the structuralist thesis from an unproblematic emphasis on the importance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Structure and Categoricity: Determinacy of Reference and Truth Value in the Philosophy of Mathematics.Tim Button & Sean Walsh - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (3):283-307.
    This article surveys recent literature by Parsons, McGee, Shapiro and others on the significance of categoricity arguments in the philosophy of mathematics. After discussing whether categoricity arguments are sufficient to secure reference to mathematical structures up to isomorphism, we assess what exactly is achieved by recent ‘internal’ renditions of the famous categoricity arguments for arithmetic and set theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On gödel's theorems on lengths of proofs I: Number of lines and speedup for arithmetics.Samuel R. Buss - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):737-756.
    This paper discusses lower bounds for proof length, especially as measured by number of steps (inferences). We give the first publicly known proof of Gödel's claim that there is superrecursive (in fact. unbounded) proof speedup of (i + 1)st-order arithmetic over ith-order arithmetic, where arithmetic is formalized in Hilbert-style calculi with + and · as function symbols or with the language of PRA. The same results are established for any weakly schematic formalization of higher-order logic: this allows all tautologies as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Computational Semantics.Patrick Blackburn & Johan Bos - 2010 - Theoria 18 (1):27-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indistinguishable elements and mathematical structuralism.José Bermúdez - 2007 - Analysis 67 (2):112-116.
    The existence of structures with non-trivial authomorphisms (such as the automorphism of the field of complex numbers onto itself that swaps the two roots of – 1) has been held by Burgess and others to pose a serious difficulty for mathematical structuralism. This paper proposes a model-theoretic solution to the problem. It suggests that mathematical structuralists identify the “position” of an n-tuple in a mathematical structure with the type of that n-tuple in the expansion of the structure that has a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The limits of phenomenology: From behaviorism to drug testing and engineering design.Yaneer Bar-Yam - 2016 - Complexity 21 (S1):181-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Formally Measuring and Eliminating Extraneous Notions in Proofs.Andrew Arana - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (2):189-207.
    Many mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics believe some proofs contain elements extraneous to what is being proved. In this paper I discuss extraneousness generally, and then consider a specific proposal for measuring extraneousness syntactically. This specific proposal uses Gentzen's cut-elimination theorem. I argue that the proposal fails, and that we should be skeptical about the usefulness of syntactic extraneousness measures.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Logic, Essence, and Modality — Review of Bob Hale's Necessary Beings. [REVIEW]Christopher Menzel - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (3):407-428.
    Bob Hale’s distinguished record of research places him among the most important and influential contemporary analytic metaphysicians. In his deep, wide ranging, yet highly readable book Necessary Beings, Hale draws upon, but substantially integrates and extends, a good deal his past research to produce a sustained and richly textured essay on — as promised in the subtitle — ontology, modality, and the relations between them. I’ve set myself two tasks in this review: first, to provide a reasonably thorough (if not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Carnap’s Early Semantics.Georg Schiemer - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (3):487-522.
    This paper concerns Carnap’s early contributions to formal semantics in his work on general axiomatics between 1928 and 1936. Its main focus is on whether he held a variable domain conception of models. I argue that interpreting Carnap’s account in terms of a fixed domain approach fails to describe his premodern understanding of formal models. By drawing attention to the second part of Carnap’s unpublished manuscript Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik, an alternative interpretation of the notions ‘model’, ‘model extension’ and ‘submodel’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A way out of the preface paradox?Hannes Leitgeb - 2014 - Analysis 74 (1):ant091.
    The thesis defended in this article is that by uttering or publishing a great many declarative sentences in assertoric mode, one does not actually assert that their conjunction is true – one rather asserts that the vast majority of these sentences are true. Accordingly, the belief that is expressed thereby is the belief that the vast majority of these sentences are true. In the article, we make this proposal precise, we explain the context-dependency of belief that corresponds to it, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Tarski T-Schema is a tautology.E. N. Zalta - 2014 - Analysis 74 (1):5-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Tarski T-Schema is a tautology (literally).Edward N. Zalta - 2013 - Analysis (1):ant099.
    The Tarski T-Schema has a propositional version. If we use ϕ as a metavariable for formulas and use terms of the form that-ϕ to denote propositions, then the propositional version of the T-Schema is: that-ϕ is true if and only if ϕ. For example, that Cameron is Prime Minister is true if and only if Cameron is Prime Minister. If that-ϕ is represented formally as [λ ϕ], then the T-Schema can be represented as the 0-place case of λ-Conversion. If we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Did Tarski commit “Tarski's fallacy”?G. Y. Sher - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):653-686.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • A proof of completeness for continuous first-order logic.Itaï Ben Yaacov & Arthur Paul Pedersen - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1):168-190.
    -/- Continuous first-order logic has found interest among model theorists who wish to extend the classical analysis of “algebraic” structures (such as fields, group, and graphs) to various natural classes of complete metric structures (such as probability algebras, Hilbert spaces, and Banach spaces). With research in continuous first-order logic preoccupied with studying the model theory of this framework, we find a natural question calls for attention. Is there an interesting set of axioms yielding a completeness result? -/- The primary purpose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the formalization of semantic conventions.James G. Williams - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):220-243.
    This paper discusses six formalization techniques, of varying strengths, for extending a formal system based on traditional mathematical logic. The purpose of these formalization techniques is to simulate the introduction of new syntactic constructs, along with associated semantics for them. We show that certain techniques (among the six) subsume others. To illustrate sharpness, we also consider a selection of constructs and show which techniques can and cannot be used to introduce them. The six studied techniques were selected on the basis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege, hilbert, and the conceptual structure of model theory.William Demopoulos - 1994 - History and Philosophy of Logic 15 (2):211-225.
    This paper attempts to confine the preconceptions that prevented Frege from appreciating Hilbert?s Grundlagen der Geometrie to two: (i) Frege?s reliance on what, following Wilfrid Hodges, I call a Frege?Peano language, and (ii) Frege?s view that the sense of an expression wholly determines its reference.I argue that these two preconceptions prevented Frege from achieving the conceptual structure of model theory, whereas Hilbert, at least in his practice, was quite close to the model?theoretic point of view.Moreover, the issues that divided Frege (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Relative categoricity and abstraction principles.Sean Walsh & Sean Ebels-Duggan - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):572-606.
    Many recent writers in the philosophy of mathematics have put great weight on the relative categoricity of the traditional axiomatizations of our foundational theories of arithmetic and set theory. Another great enterprise in contemporary philosophy of mathematics has been Wright's and Hale's project of founding mathematics on abstraction principles. In earlier work, it was noted that one traditional abstraction principle, namely Hume's Principle, had a certain relative categoricity property, which here we term natural relative categoricity. In this paper, we show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logicism, Interpretability, and Knowledge of Arithmetic.Sean Walsh - 2014 - Review of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):84-119.
    A crucial part of the contemporary interest in logicism in the philosophy of mathematics resides in its idea that arithmetical knowledge may be based on logical knowledge. Here an implementation of this idea is considered that holds that knowledge of arithmetical principles may be based on two things: (i) knowledge of logical principles and (ii) knowledge that the arithmetical principles are representable in the logical principles. The notions of representation considered here are related to theory-based and structure-based notions of representation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Modal Foundations for Predicate Logic.Johan van Benthem - 1997 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 5 (2):259-286.
    The complexity of any logical modeling reflects both the intrinsic structure of a topic described and the weight of the formal tools. Some of this weight seems inherent in even the most basic logical systems. Notably, standard predicate logic is undecidable. In this paper, we investigate ‘lighter’ versions of this general purpose tool, by modally ‘deconstructing’ the usual semantics, and locating implicit choice points in its set up. The first part sets out the interest of this program and the modal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Semantics for first-order superposition logic.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 2019 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 27 (4):570-595.
    We investigate how the sentence choice semantics for propositional superposition logic developed in Tzouvaras could be extended so as to successfully apply to first-order superposition logic. There are two options for such an extension. The apparently more natural one is the formula choice semantics based on choice functions for pairs of arbitrary formulas of the basis language. It is proved however that the universal instantiation scheme of first-order logic, $\varphi \rightarrow \varphi $, is false, as a scheme of tautologies, with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decidable fragments of field theories.Shih-Ping Tung - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1007-1018.
    We say φ is an ∀∃ sentence if and only if φ is logically equivalent to a sentence of the form ∀ x∃ y ψ(x,y), where ψ(x,y) is a quantifier-free formula containing no variables except x and y. In this paper we show that there are algorithms to decide whether or not a given ∀∃ sentence is true in (1) an algebraic number field K, (2) a purely transcendental extension of an algebraic number field K, (3) every field with characteristic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Decidability of mereological theories.Hsing-Chien Tsai - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (1):45-63.
    Mereological theories are theories based on a binary predicate ‘being a part of’. It is believed that such a predicate must at least define a partial ordering. A mereological theory can be obtained by adding on top of the basic axioms of partial orderings some of the other axioms posited based on pertinent philosophical insights. Though mereological theories have aroused quite a few philosophers’ interest recently, not much has been said about their meta-logical properties. In this paper, I will look (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ways of branching quantifers.Gila Sher - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4):393 - 422.
    Branching quantifiers were first introduced by L. Henkin in his 1959 paper ‘Some Remarks on Infmitely Long Formulas’. By ‘branching quantifiers’ Henkin meant a new, non-linearly structured quantiiier-prefix whose discovery was triggered by the problem of interpreting infinitistic formulas of a certain form} The branching (or partially-ordered) quantifier-prefix is, however, not essentially infinitistic, and the issues it raises have largely been discussed in the literature in the context of finitistic logic, as they will be here. Our discussion transcends, however, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Truth, Logical Structure, and Compositionality.Gila Sher - 2001 - Synthese 126 (1-2):195-219.
    In this paper I examine a cluster of concepts relevant to the methodology of truth theories: 'informative definition', 'recursive method', 'semantic structure', 'logical form', 'compositionality', etc. The interrelations between these concepts, I will try to show, are more intricate and multi-dimensional than commonly assumed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Partially-ordered (branching) generalized quantifiers: A general definition.Gila Sher - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1):1-43.
    Following Henkin's discovery of partially-ordered (branching) quantification (POQ) with standard quantifiers in 1959, philosophers of language have attempted to extend his definition to POQ with generalized quantifiers. In this paper I propose a general definition of POQ with 1-place generalized quantifiers of the simplest kind: namely, predicative, or "cardinality" quantifiers, e.g., "most", "few", "finitely many", "exactly α", where α is any cardinal, etc. The definition is obtained in a series of generalizations, extending the original, Henkin definition first to a general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the possibility of a substantive theory of truth.Gila Sher - 1998 - Synthese 117 (1):133-172.
    The paper offers a new analysis of the difficulties involved in the construction of a general and substantive correspondence theory of truth and delineates a solution to these difficulties in the form of a new methodology. The central argument is inspired by Kant, and the proposed methodology is explained and justified both in general philosophical terms and by reference to a particular variant of Tarski's theory. The paper begins with general considerations on truth and correspondence and concludes with a brief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Did Tarski commit "Tarski's fallacy"?Gila Sher - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):653-686.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • ¿Cuándo una demostración es más perspicua que otra?José Seoane - 2017 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 21 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the role of Ramsey quantifiers in first order arithmetic.James H. Schmerl & Stephen G. Simpson - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):423-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Institutionalising ontology-based semantic integration.Marco Schorlemmer & Yannis Kalfoglou - 2008 - Applied ontology 3 (3):131-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Remarques à propos d’une récente Introduction à la logique.François Rivenc - 1999 - Dialogue 38 (2):369-.
    Ce bel ouvrage, clair, aéré et spacieux, se caractérise à la fois par sa volonté de simplicité d’accès, et son ambition, puisqu’on y trouve notamment une démonstration de la complétude d’un certain système déductif S1 pour la logique classique des prédicats, ainsi qu’une version synoptique du théorème de Gödel, selon lequel toute théorie du premier ordre complète axiomatisable est décidable, d’où il s’ensuit que l’arithmétique, c’est-à-dire l’ensemble des énoncés du premier ordre vrais dans, n’est pas axiomatisable; ce qu’on exprime souvent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Answer to a problem raised by J. Robinson: The arithmetic of positive or negative integers is definable from successor and divisibility.Denis Richard - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):927-935.
    In this paper we give a positive answer to Julia Robinson's question whether the definability of + and · from S and ∣ that she proved in the case of positive integers is extendible to arbitrary integers (cf. [JR, p. 102]).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine's 'limits of decision'.William C. Purdy - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1439-1466.
    In a 1969 paper, Quine coined the term 'limits of decision'. This term evidently refers to limits on the logical vocabulary of a logic, beyond which satisfiability is no longer decidable. In the same paper. Quine showed that not only monadic formulas, but homogeneous k-adic formulas for arbitrary k lie on the decidable side of the limits of decision. But the precise location of the limits of decision has remained an open question. The present paper answers that question. It addresses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fluted formulas and the limits of decidability.William C. Purdy - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):608-620.
    In the predicate calculus, variables provide a flexible indexing service which selects the actual arguments to a predicate letter from among possible arguments that precede the predicate letter (in the parse of the formula). In the process of selection, the possible arguments can be permuted, repeated (used more than once), and skipped. If this service is withheld, so that arguments must be the immediately preceding ones, taken in the order in which they occur, the formula is said to be fluted. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the angular component map modulo P.Johan Pas - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1125-1129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Theories of reasoning and the computational explanation of everyday inference.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (2):121 – 152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Mathematics is not the only language in the book of nature.James Nguyen & Roman Frigg - 2017 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 24):1-22.
    How does mathematics apply to something non-mathematical? We distinguish between a general application problem and a special application problem. A critical examination of the answer that structural mapping accounts offer to the former problem leads us to identify a lacuna in these accounts: they have to presuppose that target systems are structured and yet leave this presupposition unexplained. We propose to fill this gap with an account that attributes structures to targets through structure generating descriptions. These descriptions are physical descriptions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On models of the elementary theory of (z + 1).Mark Nadel & Jonathan Stavi - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Gödel Sentences and What They Say.Peter Milne - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (2):193-226.
    Proofs of Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem are often accompanied by claims such as that the gödel sentence constructed in the course of the proof says of itself that it is unprovable and that it is true. The validity of such claims depends closely on how the sentence is constructed. Only by tightly constraining the means of construction can one obtain gödel sentences of which it is correct, without further ado, to say that they say of themselves that they are unprovable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Some elementary degree-theoretic reasons why structures need similarity types.T. G. McLaughlin - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):732-747.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models and the Semantic View.Martin Thomson-Jones - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):524-535.
    I begin by distinguishing two notions of model, the notion of a truth-making structure and the notion of a mathematical model (in one specific sense). I then argue that although the models of the semantic view have often been taken to be both truth-making structures and mathematical models, this is in part due to a failure to distinguish between two ways of truth-making; in fact, the talk of truth-making is best excised from the view altogether. The result is a version (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • III-Reference by Abstraction.ØYstein Linnebo - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (1pt1):45-71.
    Frege suggests that criteria of identity should play a central role in the explanation of reference, especially to abstract objects. This paper develops a precise model of how we can come to refer to a particular kind of abstract object, namely, abstract letter types. It is argued that the resulting abstract referents are ‘metaphysically lightweight’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Axiomatic truth, syntax and metatheoretic reasoning.Graham E. Leigh & Carlo Nicolai - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):613-636.
    Following recent developments in the literature on axiomatic theories of truth, we investigate an alternative to the widespread habit of formalizing the syntax of the object-language into the object-language itself. We first argue for the proposed revision, elaborating philosophical evidences in favor of it. Secondly, we present a general framework for axiomatic theories of truth with theories of syntax. Different choices of the object theory O will be considered. Moreover, some strengthenings of these theories will be introduced: we will consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • What Are Structural Properties?†.Johannes Korbmacher & Georg Schiemer - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):295-323.
    Informally, structural properties of mathematical objects are usually characterized in one of two ways: either as properties expressible purely in terms of the primitive relations of mathematical theories, or as the properties that hold of all structurally similar mathematical objects. We present two formal explications corresponding to these two informal characterizations of structural properties. Based on this, we discuss the relation between the two explications. As will be shown, the two characterizations do not determine the same class of mathematical properties. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Cardinality logics. Part II: Definability in languages based on `exactly'.Harold Hodes - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):765-784.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ω1-like recursively saturated models of Presburger's arithmetic.Victor Harnik - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):421-429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Presburger arithmetic with unary predicates is Π11 complete.Joseph Y. Halpern - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (2):637 - 642.
    We give a simple proof characterizing the complexity of Presburger arithmetic augmented with additional predicates. We show that Presburger arithmetic with additional predicates is Π 1 1 complete. Adding one unary predicate is enough to get Π 1 1 hardness, while adding more predicates (of any arity) does not make the complexity any worse.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Modular first-order ontologies via repositories.Michael Grüninger, Torsten Hahmann, Ali Hashemi, Darren Ong & Atalay Ozgovde - 2012 - Applied ontology 7 (2):169-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • First-Order Logic Formalisation of Impossibility Theorems in Preference Aggregation.Umberto Grandi & Ulle Endriss - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (4):595-618.
    In preference aggregation a set of individuals express preferences over a set of alternatives, and these preferences have to be aggregated into a collective preference. When preferences are represented as orders, aggregation procedures are called social welfare functions. Classical results in social choice theory state that it is impossible to aggregate the preferences of a set of individuals under different natural sets of axiomatic conditions. We define a first-order language for social welfare functions and we give a complete axiomatisation for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Rational Analysis of Rule-Based Concept Learning.Noah D. Goodman, Joshua B. Tenenbaum, Jacob Feldman & Thomas L. Griffiths - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (1):108-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations