Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Commentary on Schwed.Lawrence Powers - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The power of the hexagon.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (1-2):1-43.
    The hexagon of opposition is an improvement of the square of opposition due to Robert Blanché. After a short presentation of the square and its various interpretations, we discuss two important problems related with the square: the problem of the I-corner and the problem of the O-corner. The meaning of the notion described by the I-corner does not correspond to the name used for it. In the case of the O-corner, the problem is not a wrong-name problem but a no-name (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • On a Minimal System of Aristotle’s Syllogistic.Piotr Kulicki - 2011 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 40 (3/4):129-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arthur Prior and Medieval Logic.Sara L. Uckelman - 2012 - Synthese 188 (3):349-366.
    Though Arthur Prior is now best known for his founding of modern temporal logic and hybrid logic, much of his early philosophical career was devoted to history of logic and historical logic. This interest laid the foundations for both of his ground-breaking innovations in the 1950s and 1960s. Because of the important rôle played by Prior's research in ancient and medieval logic in his development of temporal and hybrid logic, any student of Prior, temporal logic, or hybrid logic should be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Greek and Vedic Geometry.Frits Staal - 1999 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 27 (1/2):105-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Completion, reduction and analysis: three proof-theoretic processes in aristotle’s prior analytics.George Boger - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (4):187-226.
    Three distinctly different interpretations of Aristotle’s notion of a sullogismos in Prior Analytics can be traced: (1) a valid or invalid premise-conclusion argument (2) a single, logically true conditional proposition and (3) a cogent argumentation or deduction. Remarkably the three interpretations hold similar notions about the logical relationships among the sullogismoi. This is most apparent in their conflating three processes that Aristotle especially distinguishes: completion (A4-6)reduction(A7) and analysis (A45). Interpretive problems result from not sufficiently recognizing Aristotle’s remarkable degree of metalogical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The concept of paksa in indian logic.J. F. Staal - 1972 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 2 (2):156-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Complementary Logics for Classical Propositional Languages.Achille C. Varzi - 1992 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 4 (1):20-24.
    In previous work, I introduced a complete axiomatization of classical non-tautologies based essentially on Łukasiewicz’s rejection method. The present paper provides a new, Hilbert-type axiomatization (along with related systems to axiomatize classical contradictions, non-contradictions, contingencies and non-contingencies respectively). This new system is mathematically less elegant, but the format of the inferential rules and the structure of the completeness proof possess some intrinsic interest and suggests instructive comparisons with the logic of tautologies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Rejection in Łukasiewicz's and Słupecki' Sense.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2018 - Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present.
    The idea of rejection originated by Aristotle. The notion of rejection was introduced into formal logic by Łukasiewicz [20]. He applied it to complete syntactic characterization of deductive systems using an axiomatic method of rejection of propositions [22, 23]. The paper gives not only genesis, but also development and generalization of the notion of rejection. It also emphasizes the methodological approach to biaspectual axiomatic method of characterization of deductive systems as acceptance (asserted) systems and rejection (refutation) systems, introduced by Łukasiewicz (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The theory of rejected propositions. II.Jerzy Słupecki, Grzegorz Bryll & Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 1972 - Studia Logica 30 (1):97 - 145.
    This paper is a continuation of Part I under the same title. Its Chapter III contains results given in the following publications: U. Wybraniec-Skardowska, Teoria zdań odrzuconych (Theory of Rejected Sentences), (doctoral dissertation under the supervision of Jerzy Słupecki, published as a monograph), Zeszyty Naukowe Wyższej Szkoły Pedagogicznej w Opolu, Studia i Monografie, Nr 22 (1969), 5-131. G. Bryll, Związki logiczne pomiędzy zdaniami nauk empirycznych (Logical relations between sentences of empirical sciences). Zeszyty Naukowe Wyższej Szkoły Pedagogicznej w Opolu, Studia i (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)On the interpretation of aristotelian syllogistic.J. C. Shepherdson - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (2):137-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Inferential intensionality.Grzegorz Malinowski - 2004 - Studia Logica 76 (1):3 - 16.
    The paper is a study of properties of quasi-consequence operation which is a key notion of the so-called inferential approach in the theory of sentential calculi established in [5]. The principal motivation behind the quasi-consequence, q-consequence for short, stems from the mathematical practice which treats some auxiliary assumptions as mere hypotheses rather than axioms and their further occurrence in place of conclusions may be justified or not. The main semantic feature of the q-consequence reflecting the idea is that its rules (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Logics of Transitive Verbs With and Without Intersective Adjectives.Selçuk Topal - 2018 - Studia Humana 7 (1):31-43.
    The purpose of this paper is to contribute to the natural logic program which invents logics in natural language. This study presents two logics: a logical system called d R containing transitive verbs and a more expressive logical system R containing both transitive verbs and intersective adjectives. The paper offers three different set-theoretic semantics which are equivalent for the logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)A simple semantics for Aristotelian apodeictic syllogistics.Sara L. Uckelman & Spencer Johnston - 2010 - Advances in Modal Logic 8:454-469.
    We give a simple definition of validity for syllogisms involving necessary and assertoric premises which validates all and only the Aristotelian apodeictic syllogisms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Falsification-Aware Calculi and Semantics for Normal Modal Logics Including S4 and S5.Norihiro Kamide - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):395-440.
    Falsification-aware (hyper)sequent calculi and Kripke semantics for normal modal logics including S4 and S5 are introduced and investigated in this study. These calculi and semantics are constructed based on the idea of a falsification-aware framework for Nelson’s constructive three-valued logic. The cut-elimination and completeness theorems for the proposed calculi and semantics are proved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Peirce and Łukasiewicz on modal and multi-valued logics.Jon Alan Schmidt - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-18.
    Charles Peirce incorporates modality into his Existential Graphs by introducing the broken cut for possible falsity. Although it can be adapted to various modern modal logics, Zeman demonstrates that making no other changes results in a version that he calls Gamma-MR, an implementation of Jan Łukasiewicz's four-valued Ł-modal system. It disallows the assertion of necessity, reflecting a denial of determinism, and has theorems involving possibility that seem counterintuitive at first glance. However, the latter is a misconception that arises from overlooking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Łukasiewicz’s concept of logic and anti-psychologism.Zuzana Rybaříková - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-14.
    In the nineteenth century, philosophy was at a crossroads. While the natural and technical sciences were developing in an unprecedented fashion, philosophy seemed to be stalled. Inspired by the progress of the natural sciences, many philosophers attempted to make such progress in philosophy and make philosophy a truly scientific discipline. This effort was also reflected in the philosophy of the Lvov-Warsaw school. While its founder, Kazimierz Twardowski, following his teacher Franz Brentano, promoted psychology as a method of scientific philosophy, one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural Deduction, Hybrid Systems and Modal Logics.Andrzej Indrzejczak - 2010 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book provides a detailed exposition of one of the most practical and popular methods of proving theorems in logic, called Natural Deduction. It is presented both historically and systematically. Also some combinations with other known proof methods are explored. The initial part of the book deals with Classical Logic, whereas the rest is concerned with systems for several forms of Modal Logics, one of the most important branches of modern logic, which has wide applicability.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Arthur N. Prior on ‘Unquestionably the Best Logical Symbolism for Most Purposes’.Jeremiah Joven B. Joaquin - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (2):158-174.
    In his Formal Logic, Arthur N. Prior declared that Jan Łukasiewicz's logical notation is ‘unquestionably the best logical symbolism for most purposes’. Whether he had a substantive, and...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The correctness and relevance of the modal ontological argument.Andrzej Biłat - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1):2727-2743.
    This paper deals with some metaphilosophical aspects of the modal ontological argument originating from Charles Hartshorne. One of the specific premises of the argument expresses the idea that the existence of God is not contingent. Several well-known versions of the argument have been formulated that appeal to different ways of clarifying the latter. A question arises: which of the formally correct and relevant versions is proper or basic? The paper points to some criteria of formal correctness, and distinguishes two types (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Mythical Foundation of Logic and Its Impact on Metaphysics of Exclusion.Mohamed Almisbkawy - 2020 - Philosophy Study 10 (10): 654-662..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Łukasiewicz and Quine on Empirical and A Priori Sciences.Zuzana Rybaříková - 2019 - Studia Semiotyczne 33 (2):241-253.
    Although Łukasiewicz and Quine do not share many common views, they agreed on one important point in the 1950s: they both denied the distinction between empirical and a priori sciences. This agreement might be surprising as this denial was rather controversial at that time. This paper focuses on Quine’s and Łukasiewicz’s denials of the distinction between empirical and a priori sciences, and proposes three possible answers to the question of why both formulated the same conclusion at a similar time. Firstly, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Is There Anything Logically Distinctive About Practical Syllogisms?Jean-Baptiste Gourinat - 2008 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 11 (1):133-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Critical Examination of the Historical Origins of Connexive Logic.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2019 - History and Philosophy of Logic 41 (1):16-35.
    It is often assumed that Aristotle, Boethius, Chrysippus, and other ancient logicians advocated a connexive conception of implication according to which no proposition entails, or is entailed by, its own negation. Thus Aristotle claimed that the proposition ‘if B is not great, B itself is great […] is impossible’. Similarly, Boethius maintained that two implications of the type ‘If p then r’ and ‘If p then not-r’ are incompatible. Furthermore, Chrysippus proclaimed a conditional to be ‘sound when the contradictory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant’s Dynamic Hylomorphism in Logic.Elena Dragalina-Chernaya - 2016 - Con-Textos Kantianos 4:127-137.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a dynamic interpretation of Kant’s logical hylomorphism. Firstly, various types of the logical hylomorphism will be illustrated. Secondly, I propose to reevaluate Kant’s constitutivity thesis about logic. Finally, I focus on the design of logical norms as specific kinds of artefacts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A 4-valued logic of strong conditional.Fabien Schang - 2018 - South American Journal of Logic 3 (1):59-86.
    How to say no less, no more about conditional than what is needed? From a logical analysis of necessary and sufficient conditions (Section 1), we argue that a stronger account of conditional can be obtained in two steps: firstly, by reminding its historical roots inside modal logic and set-theory (Section 2); secondly, by revising the meaning of logical values, thereby getting rid of the paradoxes of material implication whilst showing the bivalent roots of conditional as a speech-act based on affirmations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • N. A. Vasil’ev’s Logic and the Problem of Future Random Events.Dmitry Maximov - 2018 - Axiomathes 28 (2):201-217.
    The solution of the problem of the future random events truth is considered in Vasil’ev’s logic. N. A. Vasil’ev graded the logic according to two levels—the level of facts, i.e. time fixed events, and the level of notions or rules, governing these facts. The mathematical construction previously suggested for imaginary Vasil’ev’s logic, extends to the early variant of his logic—a logic of notions. In the paper, we investigate the meaning of problematic and uncertain assertions introduced by Vasil’ev. As a result, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Physarum Polycephalum Syllogistic L-Systems and Judaic Roots of Unconventional Computing.Andrew Schumann - 2016 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 44 (1):181-201.
    We show that in Kabbalah, the esoteric teaching of Judaism, there were developed ideas of unconventional automata in which operations over characters of the Hebrew alphabet can simulate all real processes producing appropriate strings in accordance with some algorithms. These ideas may be used now in a syllogistic extension of Lindenmayer systems, where we deal also with strings in the Kabbalistic-Leibnizean meaning. This extension is illustrated by the behavior of Physarum polycephalum plasmodia which can implement, first, the Aristotelian syllogistic and, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Interpretation of Łukasiewicz’s 4-Valued Modal Logic.José M. Méndez, Gemma Robles & Francisco Salto - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (1):73-87.
    A simple, bivalent semantics is defined for Łukasiewicz’s 4-valued modal logic Łm4. It is shown that according to this semantics, the essential presupposition underlying Łm4 is the following: A is a theorem iff A is true conforming to both the reductionist and possibilist theses defined as follows: rt: the value of modal formulas is equivalent to the value of their respective argument iff A is true, etc.); pt: everything is possible. This presupposition highlights and explains all oddities arising in Łm4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A meta-logic of inference rules: Syntax.Alex Citkin - 2015 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 24 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Defining topics in aristotle’s topics VI.Lucas Angioni - 2014 - Philósophos - Revista de Filosofia 19 (2):151-193.
    I argue that Topics VI does not contain any serious theory about definitions, but only a collection of advices for formulating definitions in a dialectical context, namely, definitions aiming to catch what the opponent means. Topics VI is full of inconsistencies that can be explained away by this approach: the inconsistencies reflect "acceptable opinions about definitions" that distinct groups of interlocutors accept. I also argue that the "topoi" need not be pieces of serious theory Aristotle is commited to. The "topoi" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Alexander of Aphrodisias and the Heterodox dictum de omni et de nullo.Luca Gili - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (2):114-128.
    Aristotle's explanation of what is said ‘of every’ and ‘of none’ has been interpreted either as involving individuals, or as regarding exclusively universal terms. I claim that Alexander of Aphrodisias endorsed this latter interpretation of the dictum de omni et de nullo. This interpretation affects our understanding of Alexander's syllogistic: as a matter of fact, Alexander maintained that the dictum de omni et de nullo is one of the core principles of syllogistic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A note on relationship between the consequence operations cn and dcn.Anna Gomolinska & Justyna K. Myslinska - 2000 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 29 (1/2):63-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Axiomatisation of a Pure Calculus of Names.Piotr Kulicki - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (5):921-946.
    A calculus of names is a logical theory describing relations between names. By a pure calculus of names we mean a quantifier-free formulation of such a theory, based on classical propositional calculus. An axiomatisation of a pure calculus of names is presented and its completeness is discussed. It is shown that the axiomatisation is complete in three different ways: with respect to a set theoretical model, with respect to Leśniewski's Ontology and in a sense defined with the use of axiomatic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Remarks about syllogistic with negative terms.Bogusław Iwanuś - 1969 - Studia Logica 24 (1):131 - 141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Are Ancient Logics Explosive?Marcin Tkaczyk - 2024 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (2):109-123.
    The twentieth-century logical mainstream, derived from works by Łukasiewicz and Scholz, pictures the history of logic for the most part as the prehistory of Boolean–Fregean mathematical logic. Particularly, with respect to classical propositional calculus, the Stoic logic has been pictured as an early stage of it and Aristotle's or the Peripatetics' logic as a theory that assumes it. Although it was not emphasised, it follows that the ancient logics contain the principle of explosion. In the endmost quarter of the twentieth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connexivity in Aristotle’s Logic.Fabian Ruge - 2023 - History and Philosophy of Logic 44 (4):353-372.
    At APr 2.4 57a36–13, Aristotle presents a notorious reductio argument in which he derives the claim ‘If B is not large, B is large’ and calls that result impossible. Aristotle is thus committed to some form of connexivity and this paper argues that his commitment is to a strong form of connexivity which excludes even cases in which ‘B is large’ is necessary. It is further argued that Aristotle’s view of connexivity is best understood as arising from his analysis of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alexander of aphrodisias and others on a controversial demonstration in aristotle’s modal syllogistic.S. J. Kevin L. Flannery - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2):201-214.
    Aristotle’s treatment of mixed, first-figure, problematic-assertoric syllogisms has generated a good deal of controversy among modern commentators.I argue that W.D.Ross’s criticism of A.Becker’s cr...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Characteristics of the Referential and Inferential Predication in Classical Logic.Nijaz Ibrulj - 2021 - The Logical Foresight 1 (1):1-27.
    In the article we consider the relationship of traditional provisions of basic logical concepts and confront them with new and modern approaches to the same concepts. Logic is characterized in different ways when it is associated with syllogistics (referential – semantical model of logic) or with symbolic logic (inferential – syntactical model of logic). This is not only a difference in the logical calculation of (1) concepts, (2) statements, and (3) predicates, but this difference also appears in the treatment of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Theory of Deduction and Paraconsistency.Evandro Luís Gomes & Itala M. Loffredo D'Ottaviano - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):71–97.
    In the Organon Aristotle describes some deductive schemata in which inconsistencies do not entail the trivialization of the logical theory involved. This thesis is corroborated by three different theoretical topics by him discussed, which are presented in this paper. We analyse inference schema used by Aristotle in the Protrepticus and the method of indirect demonstration for categorical syllogisms. Both methods exemplify as Aristotle employs classical reductio ad absurdum strategies. Following, we discuss valid syllogisms from opposite premises (contrary and contradictory) studied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • DLEAC: A Dialetheic Logic with Exclusive Assumptions and Conclusions.Massimiliano Carrara & Enrico Martino - 2019 - Topoi 38 (2):379-388.
    This paper proposes a new dialetheic logic, a Dialetheic Logic with Exclusive Assumptions and Conclusions ), including classical logic as a particular case. In \, exclusivity is expressed via the speech acts of assuming and concluding. In the paper we adopt the semantics of the logic of paradox extended with a generalized notion of model and we modify its proof theory by refining the notions of assumption and conclusion. The paper starts with an explanation of the adopted philosophical perspective, then (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Toulmin Model and Non-monotonic Reasoning.William Keith - unknown
    While the nature of warrants is unclear in both Toulmin’s Uses of Argument and in textbook pedagogy based on it, the theory of non-monotonic reasoning could clarify and enhance our understanding of warrants.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Proving unprovability in some normal modal logics.Valentin Goranko - 1991 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 20 (1):23-29.
    This note considers deductive systems for the operator a of unprovability in some particular propositional normal modal logics. We give thus complete syntactic characterization of these logics in the sense of Lukasiewicz: for every formula  either `  or a  (but not both) is derivable. In particular, purely syntactic decision procedure is provided for the logics under considerations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Diagrammatic Calculus of Syllogisms.Ruggero Pagnan - 2012 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 21 (3):347-364.
    A diagrammatic logical calculus for the syllogistic reasoning is introduced and discussed. We prove that a syllogism is valid if and only if it is provable in the calculus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Establishing Connections between Aristotle's Natural Deduction and First-Order Logic.Edgar José Andrade & Edward Samuel Becerra - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (4):309-325.
    This article studies the mathematical properties of two systems that model Aristotle's original syllogistic and the relationship obtaining between them. These systems are Corcoran's natural deduction syllogistic and ?ukasiewicz's axiomatization of the syllogistic. We show that by translating the former into a first-order theory, which we call T RD, we can establish a precise relationship between the two systems. We prove within the framework of first-order logic a number of logical properties about T RD that bear upon the same properties (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A reconstruction of Aristotle's modal syllogistic.Marko Malink - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (2):95-141.
    Ever since ?ukasiewicz, it has been opinio communis that Aristotle's modal syllogistic is incomprehensible due to its many faults and inconsistencies, and that there is no hope of finding a single consistent formal model for it. The aim of this paper is to disprove these claims by giving such a model. My main points shall be, first, that Aristotle's syllogistic is a pure term logic that does not recognize an extra syntactic category of individual symbols besides syllogistic terms and, second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Solving categorical syllogisms with singular premises.Hugo Mercier & Guy Politzer - 2008 - Thinking and Reasoning 14 (4):434-454.
    We elaborate on the approach to syllogistic reasoning based on “case identification” (Stenning & Oberlander, 1995; Stenning & Yule, 1997). It is shown that this can be viewed as the formalisation of a method of proof that dates back to Aristotle, namely proof by exposition ( ecthesis ), and that there are traces of this method in the strategies described by a number of psychologists, from St rring (1908) to the present day. We hypothesised that by rendering individual cases explicit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Hegel and Peircean abduction.Paul Redding - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):295–313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A łukasiewicz-style refutation system for the modal logic S.Tomasz Skura - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (6):573 - 582.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Procedimientos argumentativos en el fragmento 17 de Sobre la filosofía.Claudia Marisa Seggiaro - 2021 - Hybris, Revista de Filosofí­A 12 (1):83-111.
    La hipótesis que intentaremos defender en este trabajo es que en Sobre la filosofía Aristóteles hace una defensa dialéctica de su concepción de los principios, tomando como punto de partida algunas de las opiniones existentes al respecto. En ese sentido, el modo de proceder aristotélico en esta obra es consistente con el implementado con idénticos fines en las obras canónicas y contribuye a comprender el uso epistémico de la dialéctica en este pensador. Para demostrar esto, nos centraremos en el análisis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark