Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. About and Around Computing Over the Reals.Solomon Feferman - unknown
    1. One theory or many? In 2004 a very interesting and readable article by Lenore Blum, entitled “Computing over the reals: Where Turing meets Newton,” appeared in the Notices of the American Mathematical Society. It explained a basic model of computation over the reals due to Blum, Michael Shub and Steve Smale (1989), subsequently exposited at length in their influential book, Complexity and Real Computation (1997), coauthored with Felipe Cucker. The ‘Turing’ in the title of Blum’s article refers of course (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • logicism, intuitionism, and formalism - What has become of them?Sten Lindstr©œm, Erik Palmgren, Krister Segerberg & Viggo Stoltenberg-Hansen (eds.) - 2008 - Berlin, Germany: Springer.
    The period in the foundations of mathematics that started in 1879 with the publication of Frege's Begriffsschrift and ended in 1931 with Gödel's Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I can reasonably be called the classical period. It saw the development of three major foundational programmes: the logicism of Frege, Russell and Whitehead, the intuitionism of Brouwer, and Hilbert's formalist and proof-theoretic programme. In this period, there were also lively exchanges between the various schools culminating in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The development of mathematical logic from Russell to Tarski, 1900-1935.Paolo Mancosu, Richard Zach & Calixto Badesa - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The period from 1900 to 1935 was particularly fruitful and important for the development of logic and logical metatheory. This survey is organized along eight "itineraries" concentrating on historically and conceptually linked strands in this development. Itinerary I deals with the evolution of conceptions of axiomatics. Itinerary II centers on the logical work of Bertrand Russell. Itinerary III presents the development of set theory from Zermelo onward. Itinerary IV discusses the contributions of the algebra of logic tradition, in particular, Löwenheim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Second-order logic and foundations of mathematics.Jouko Väänänen - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (4):504-520.
    We discuss the differences between first-order set theory and second-order logic as a foundation for mathematics. We analyse these languages in terms of two levels of formalization. The analysis shows that if second-order logic is understood in its full semantics capable of characterizing categorically central mathematical concepts, it relies entirely on informal reasoning. On the other hand, if it is given a weak semantics, it loses its power in expressing concepts categorically. First-order set theory and second-order logic are not radically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • On predicates in algebraically closed fields.Abraham Robinson - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (2):103-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen.Akihiro Kanamori - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):1-71.
    Set theory is an autonomous and sophisticated field of mathematics, enormously successful not only at its continuing development of its historical heritage but also at analyzing mathematical propositions cast in set-theoretic terms and gauging their consistency strength. But set theory is also distinguished by having begun intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes, and these have even been regarded as crucial by some of its great developers. This has encouraged the exaggeration of crises in foundations and of metaphysical doctrines in general. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)On tarski’s assumptions.Jaakko Hintikka - 2005 - Synthese 142 (3):353 - 369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic in mathematics and computer science.Richard Zach - forthcoming - In Filippo Ferrari, Elke Brendel, Massimiliano Carrara, Ole Hjortland, Gil Sagi, Gila Sher & Florian Steinberger (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Logic has pride of place in mathematics and its 20th century offshoot, computer science. Modern symbolic logic was developed, in part, as a way to provide a formal framework for mathematics: Frege, Peano, Whitehead and Russell, as well as Hilbert developed systems of logic to formalize mathematics. These systems were meant to serve either as themselves foundational, or at least as formal analogs of mathematical reasoning amenable to mathematical study, e.g., in Hilbert’s consistency program. Similar efforts continue, but have been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nominalism and Immutability.Daniel Berntson - manuscript
    Can we do science without numbers? How much contingency is there? These seemingly unrelated questions--one in the philosophy of math and science and the other in metaphysics--share an unexpectedly close connection. For as it turns out, a radical answer to the second leads to a breakthrough on the first. The radical answer is new view about modality called compossible immutabilism. The breakthrough is a new strategy for doing science without numbers. One of the chief benefits of the new strategy is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Representations of Intended Structures in Foundational Theories.Neil Barton, Moritz Müller & Mihai Prunescu - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (2):283-296.
    Often philosophers, logicians, and mathematicians employ a notion of intended structure when talking about a branch of mathematics. In addition, we know that there are foundational mathematical theories that can find representatives for the objects of informal mathematics. In this paper, we examine how faithfully foundational theories can represent intended structures, and show that this question is closely linked to the decidability of the theory of the intended structure. We argue that this sheds light on the trade-off between expressive power (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Axiomatizing Changing Conceptions of the Geometric Continuum I: Euclid-Hilbert†.John T. Baldwin - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):346-374.
    We give a general account of the goals of axiomatization, introducing a variant on Detlefsen’s notion of ‘complete descriptive axiomatization’. We describe how distinctions between the Greek and modern view of number, magnitude, and proportion impact the interpretation of Hilbert’s axiomatization of geometry. We argue, as did Hilbert, that Euclid’s propositions concerning polygons, area, and similar triangles are derivable from Hilbert’s first-order axioms. We argue that Hilbert’s axioms including continuity show much more than the geometrical propositions of Euclid’s theorems and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Tarski.Benedict Eastaugh - 2017 - In Alex Malpass & Marianna Antonutti Marfori (eds.), The History of Philosophical and Formal Logic: From Aristotle to Tarski. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing. pp. 293-313.
    Alfred Tarski was one of the greatest logicians of the twentieth century. His influence comes not merely through his own work but from the legion of students who pursued his projects, both in Poland and Berkeley. This chapter focuses on three key areas of Tarski's research, beginning with his groundbreaking studies of the concept of truth. Tarski's work led to the creation of the area of mathematical logic known as model theory and prefigured semantic approaches in the philosophy of language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Carnap’s conventionalism in geometry.Stefan Lukits - 2013 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 88 (1):123-138.
    Against Thomas Mormann's argument that differential topology does not support Carnap's conventionalism in geometry we show their compatibility. However, Mormann's emphasis on the entanglement that characterizes topology and its associated metrics is not misplaced. It poses questions about limits of empirical inquiry. For Carnap, to pose a question is to give a statement with the task of deciding its truth. Mormann's point forces us to introduce more clarity to what it means to specify the task that decides between competing hypotheses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Interpretations With Parameters.L. W. Szczerba - 1980 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 26 (1‐6):35-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Twin Paradox and the Logical Foundation of Relativity Theory.Judit X. Madarász, István Németi & Gergely Székely - 2006 - Foundations of Physics 36 (5):681-714.
    We study the foundation of space-time theory in the framework of first-order logic (FOL). Since the foundation of mathematics has been successfully carried through (via set theory) in FOL, it is not entirely impossible to do the same for space-time theory (or relativity). First we recall a simple and streamlined FOL-axiomatization Specrel of special relativity from the literature. Specrel is complete with respect to questions about inertial motion. Then we ask ourselves whether we can prove the usual relativistic properties of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Lógica e Completude.Arno A. Viero - 2001 - Princípios 8 (10):07-24.
    Quine, em seu livro Philosophy of Logic, identifica lógica com lógica de primeira ordem e defende a concepçáo segundo a qual a completude é uma propriedade necessária dos sistemas lógicos. O objetivo deste trabalho é discutir a argumentaçáo de Quine e mostrar que suas idéias a respeito da natureza da lógica apresentam diversos problemas tanto conceituais, como técnicos.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic and philosophy of mathematics in the early Husserl.Stefania Centrone - 2010 - New York: Springer.
    This volume will be of particular interest to researchers working in the history, and in the philosophy, of logic and mathematics, and more generally, to ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Finitude simple et structures o-minimales (finiteness property implies o-minimality).Jean-Marie Lion - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1616-1622.
    We consider a family of differential algebras of real functions on real euclidean spaces, stable under right composition by affine maps. We prove that under a weak finiteness property, there is an o-minimal expansion of the ordered field of real numbers in which all these functions are definable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Groundwork for weak analysis.António M. Fernandes & Fernando Ferreira - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (2):557-578.
    This paper develops the very basic notions of analysis in a weak second-order theory of arithmetic BTFA whose provably total functions are the polynomial time computable functions. We formalize within BTFA the real number system and the notion of a continuous real function of a real variable. The theory BTFA is able to prove the intermediate value theorem, wherefore it follows that the system of real numbers is a real closed ordered field. In the last section of the paper, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Case for the Irreducibility of Geometry to Algebra†.Victor Pambuccian & Celia Schacht - 2022 - Philosophia Mathematica 30 (1):1-31.
    This paper provides a definitive answer, based on considerations derived from first-order logic, to the question regarding the status of elementary geometry, whether elementary geometry can be reduced to algebra. The answer we arrive at is negative, and is based on a series of structural questions that can be asked only inside the geometric formal theory, as well as the consideration of reverse geometry, which is the art of finding minimal axiom systems strong enough to prove certain geometrical theorems, given (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Von Neumann, Gödel and complexity theory.Alasdair Urquhart - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (4):516-530.
    Around 1989, a striking letter written in March 1956 from Kurt Gödel to John von Neumann came to light. It poses some problems about the complexity of algorithms; in particular, it asks a question that can be seen as the first formulation of the P=?NP question. This paper discusses some of the background to this letter, including von Neumann's own ideas on complexity theory. Von Neumann had already raised explicit questions about the complexity of Tarski's decision procedure for elementary algebra (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the equational theory of projection lattices of finite von Neumann factors.Christian Herrmann - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (3):1102-1110.
    For a finite von Neumann algebra factor M, the projections form a modular ortholattice L(M). We show that the equational theory of L(M) coincides with that of some resp. all L(ℂ n × n ) and is decidable. In contrast, the uniform word problem for the variety generated by all L(ℂ n × n ) is shown to be undecidable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)In the shadow of giants: The work of mario pieri in the foundations of mathematics.Elena Anne Marchisotto - 1995 - History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1):107-119.
    (1995). In the shadow of giants: The work of mario pieri in the foundations of mathematics. History and Philosophy of Logic: Vol. 16, No. 1, pp. 107-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Continuum, name and paradox.Vojtěch Kolman - 2010 - Synthese 175 (3):351 - 367.
    The article deals with Cantor's argument for the non-denumerability of reals somewhat in the spirit of Lakatos' logic of mathematical discovery. At the outset Cantor's proof is compared with some other famous proofs such as Dedekind's recursion theorem, showing that rather than usual proofs they are resolutions to do things differently. Based on this I argue that there are "ontologically" safer ways of developing the diagonal argument into a full-fledged theory of continuum, concluding eventually that famous semantic paradoxes based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)The Henkin Quantifier and Real Closed Fields.John R. Cowles - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (31-35):549-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Behavioural approximations for restricted linear differential hybrid automata.Manindra Agrawal, Frank Stephan, P. S. Thiagarajan & Shaofa Yang - 2006 - In O. Stock & M. Schaerf (eds.), Lecture Notes In Computer Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 4-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Completeness and Categoricity. Part I: Nineteenth-century Axiomatics to Twentieth-century Metalogic.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):1-30.
    This paper is the first in a two-part series in which we discuss several notions of completeness for systems of mathematical axioms, with special focus on their interrelations and historical origins in the development of the axiomatic method. We argue that, both from historical and logical points of view, higher-order logic is an appropriate framework for considering such notions, and we consider some open questions in higher-order axiomatics. In addition, we indicate how one can fruitfully extend the usual set-theoretic semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Probability logic in the twentieth century.Theodore Hailperin - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (1):71-110.
    This essay describes a variety of contributions which relate to the connection of probability with logic. Some are grand attempts at providing a logical foundation for probability and inductive inference. Others are concerned with probabilistic inference or, more generally, with the transmittance of probability through the structure (logical syntax) of language. In this latter context probability is considered as a semantic notion playing the same role as does truth value in conventional logic. At the conclusion of the essay two fully (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • First order common knowledge logics.Frank Wolter - 2000 - Studia Logica 65 (2):249-271.
    In this paper we investigate first order common knowledge logics; i.e., modal epistemic logics based on first order logic with common knowledge operators. It is shown that even rather weak fragments of first order common knowledge logics are not recursively axiomatizable. This applies, for example, to fragments which allow to reason about names only; that is to say, fragments the first order part of which is based on constant symbols and the equality symbol only. Then formal properties of "quantifying into" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Metamathematical problems.Abraham Robinson - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (3):500-516.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Decision and optimization problems in the unreliable-circuit logic.J. Rasga, C. Sernadas, P. Mateus & A. Sernadas - 2017 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 25 (3):283-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)In the shadow of giants: the work of Mario Pieri in the foundations of mathematics.Elena Anne Marchisotto - 1995 - History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1):107.
    A discussion is given of the research in the foundations of mathematics of Mario Pieri and how it compares with the works of Christian von Staudt, Giuseppe Peano...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A modal logic framework for reasoning about comparative distances and topology.Mikhail Sheremet, Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (4):534-559.
    We propose and investigate a uniform modal logic framework for reasoning about topology and relative distance in metric and more general distance spaces, thus enabling the comparison and combination of logics from distinct research traditions such as Tarski’s for topological closure and interior, conditional logics, and logics of comparative similarity. This framework is obtained by decomposing the underlying modal-like operators into first-order quantifier patterns. We then show that quite a powerful and natural fragment of the resulting first-order logic can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Jak pojmenovat reálné číslo?Vojtěch Kolman - 2011 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 18 (3):283-301.
    The article deals with Cantor’s diagonal argument and its alleged philosophical consequences such as that there are more reals than integers and, hence, that some of the reals must be independent of language because the totality of words and sentences is always count-able. My claim is that the main flaw of the argument for the existence of non-nameable objects or truths lies in a very superficial understanding of what a name or representation actually is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Elementary Theory of Interval Real Numbers.Stephen D. Comer - 1985 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 31 (1‐6):89-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Ordered fields with several exponential functions.B. I. Dahn & H. Wolter - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19‐24):341-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probabilization of Logics: Completeness and Decidability. [REVIEW]Pedro Baltazar - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (4):403-440.
    The probabilization of a logic system consists of enriching the language (the formulas) and the semantics (the models) with probabilistic features. Such an operation is said to be exogenous if the enrichment is done on top, without internal changes to the structure, and is called endogenous otherwise. These two different enrichments can be applied simultaneously to the language and semantics of a same logic. We address the problem of studying the transference of metaproperties, such as completeness and decidability, to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Model theory of analytic functions: some historical comments.Deirdre Haskell - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):368-381.
    Model theorists have been studying analytic functions since the late 1970s. Highlights include the seminal work of Denef and van den Dries on the theory of the p-adics with restricted analytic functions, Wilkie's proof of o-minimality of the theory of the reals with the exponential function, and the formulation of Zilber's conjecture for the complex exponential. My goal in this talk is to survey these main developments and to reflect on today's open problems, in particular for theories of valued fields.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical Generality, Letter-Labels, and All That.F. Acerbi - 2020 - Phronesis 65 (1):27-75.
    This article focusses on the generality of the entities involved in a geometric proof of the kind found in ancient Greek treatises: it shows that the standard modern translation of Greek mathematical propositions falsifies crucial syntactical elements, and employs an incorrect conception of the denotative letters in a Greek geometric proof; epigraphic evidence is adduced to show that these denotative letters are ‘letter-labels’. On this basis, the article explores the consequences of seeing that a Greek mathematical proposition is fully general, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Decidable algebraic fields.Moshe Jarden & Alexandra Shlapentokh - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (2):474-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jacques Herbrand: life, logic, and automated deduction.Claus-Peter Wirth, Jörg Siekmann, Christoph Benzmüller & Serge Autexier - 2009 - In Dov Gabbay (ed.), The Handbook of the History of Logic. Elsevier. pp. 195-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the concept of categoricity.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1962 - Studia Logica 13 (1):39 - 66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A decision procedure for probability calculus with applications.Branden Fitelson - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):111-125.
    (new version: 10/30/07). Click here to download the companion Mathematica 6 notebook that goes along with this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Existence of faster than light signals implies hypercomputation already in special relativity.Péter Németi & Gergely Székely - 2012 - In S. Barry Cooper (ed.), How the World Computes. pp. 528--538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hilbert's 17th Problem for Real Closed Rings.Larry Mathews - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):445-454.
    We recall the characterisation of positive definite polynomial functions over a real closed ring due to Dickmann, and give a new proof of this result, based upon ideas of Abraham Robinson. In addition we isolate the class of convexly ordered valuation rings for which this characterisation holds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Completeness and categoricty, part II: 20th century metalogic to 21st century semantics.Steve Awodey & Erich H. Reck - 2002 - History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (1):77-92.
    This paper is the second in a two-part series in which we discuss several notions of completeness for systems of mathematical axioms, with special focus on their interrelations and historical origins in the development of the axiomatic method. We argue that, both from historical and logical points of view, higher-order logic is an appropriate framework for considering such notions, and we consider some open questions in higher-order axiomatics. In addition, we indicate how one can fruitfully extend the usual set-theoretic semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The ordered field of real numbers and logics with Malitz quantifiers.Andreas Rapp - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):380-389.
    Let ℜ = (R, + R , ...) be the ordered field of real numbers. It will be shown that the L(Q n 1 ∣ n ≥ 1)-theory of ℜ is decidable, where Q n 1 denotes the Malitz quantifier of order n in the ℵ 1 -interpretation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Growing methods for constructing recursive deterministic perceptron neural networks and knowledge extraction.M. Tajine & D. Elizondo - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 102 (2):295-322.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computing strength of structures related to the field of real numbers.Gregory Igusa, Julia F. Knight & Noah David Schweber - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (1):137-150.
    In [8], the third author defined a reducibility$\le _w^{\rm{*}}$that lets us compare the computing power of structures of any cardinality. In [6], the first two authors showed that the ordered field of reals${\cal R}$lies strictly above certain related structures. In the present paper, we show that$\left \equiv _w^{\rm{*}}{\cal R}$. More generally, for the weak-looking structure${\cal R}$ℚconsisting of the real numbers with just the ordering and constants naming the rationals, allo-minimal expansions of${\cal R}$ℚare equivalent to${\cal R}$. Using this, we show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Interpretations With Parameters.L. W. Szczerba - 1980 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 26 (1-6):35-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations