Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Law is Necessarily Vague.Timothy Endicott - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (1):377--83.
    In fact, law is necessarily very vague. So if vagueness is a problem for legal theory, it is a serious problem. The problem has to do with the ideal of the rule of law and with the very idea of law: if vague standards provide no guidance in some cases, how can the life of a community be ruled by law? The problem has long concerned philosophers of law; the papers at this symposium address it afresh by asking what legal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Two Paradoxes of Satisfaction.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2015 - Mind 124 (493):85-119.
    There are two paradoxes of satisfaction, and they are of different kinds. The classic satisfaction paradox is a version of Grelling’s: does ‘does not satisfy itself’ satisfy itself? The Unsatisfied paradox finds a predicate, P, such that Px if and only if x does not satisfy that predicate: paradox results for any x. The two are intuitively different as their predicates have different paradoxical extensions. Analysis reduces each paradoxical argument to differing rule sets, wherein their respective pathologies lie. Having different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The pinocchio paradox.Peter Eldridge-Smith & Veronique Eldridge-Smith - 2010 - Analysis 70 (2):212-215.
    The Pinocchio paradox, devised by Veronique Eldridge-Smith in February 2001, is a counter-example to solutions to the Liar that restrict the use or definition of semantic predicates. Pinocchio’s nose grows if and only if what he is stating is false, and Pinocchio says ‘My nose is growing’. In this statement, ‘is growing’ has its normal meaning and is not a semantic predicate. If Pinocchio’s nose is growing it is because he is saying something false; otherwise, it is not growing. ‘Because’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Pinocchio against the dialetheists.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):306-308.
    Semantic dialetheists astutely dodge Explosion, the logical contagion of everything being true if a single contradiction is true. A dialetheia is contained in their semantics, and sustained by a paraconsistent logic. Graham Priest has shown that this is a solution to the Liar paradox. I use the Pinocchio paradox, devised by Veronique Eldridge-Smith, as a counter-example. The Pinocchio paradox turns on the truth of Pinocchio, whose nose grows if and only if what he is saying is not true, saying ‘My (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pinocchio beards the Barber.Peter Eldridge-Smith - 2012 - Analysis 72 (4):749-752.
    The Pinocchio paradox poses one dialetheia too many for semantic dialetheists (Eldridge-Smith 2011). However, Beall (2011) thinks that the Pinocchio scenario is merely an impossible story, like that of the village barber who shaves just those villagers who do not shave themselves. Meanwhile, Beall maintains that Liar paradoxes generate dialetheia. The Barber scenario is self-contradictory, yet the Pinocchio scenario requires a principle of truth for a contradiction. In this and other respects the Pinocchio paradox is a version of the Liar, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inconsistent Languages.Matti Eklund - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2):251-275.
    The main thesis of this paper is that we sometimes are disposed to accept false and even jointly inconsistent claims by virtue of our semantic competence, and that this comes to light in the sorites and liar paradoxes. Among the subsidiary theses are that this is an important source of indeterminacy in truth conditions, that we must revise basic assumptions about semantic competence, and that classical logic and bivalence can be upheld in the face of the sorites paradox.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • The octagon of opposition.Edward A. Hacker - 1975 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 (3):352-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The philosophical problem of vagueness.Dorothy Edgington - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (4):371-378.
    Think of the color spectrum, spread out before you. You can identify the different colors with ease. But if you are asked to indicate the point at which one color ends and the next begins, you are at a loss. "There is no such point", is a natural thought: one color just shades gradually into the next.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games.Phan Minh Dung - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 77 (2):321-357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   440 citations  
  • A Truth Value Semantics for Modal Logic.J. Michael Dunn - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):314-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A truth value semantics for modal logic.J. Michael Dunn - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):87--100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Early history of the association for symbolic logic.C. J. Ducasse & Haskell B. Curry - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):255-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Strength of Desires: A Logical Approach.Didier Dubois, Emiliano Lorini & Henri Prade - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (1):199-231.
    The aim of this paper is to propose a formal approach to reasoning about desires, understood as logical propositions which we would be pleased to make true, also acknowledging the fact that desire is a matter of degree. It is first shown that, at the static level, desires should satisfy certain principles that differ from those to which beliefs obey. In this sense, from a static perspective, the logic of desires is different from the logic of beliefs. While the accumulation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generalized possibilistic logic: Foundations and applications to qualitative reasoning about uncertainty.Didier Dubois, Henri Prade & Steven Schockaert - 2017 - Artificial Intelligence 252 (C):139-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The contingent a priori and rigid designators.Keith S. Donnellan - 1977 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1):12-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  • Reference and definite descriptions.Keith S. Donnellan - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (3):281-304.
    Definite descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible functions. 1] They are used to refer to what a speaker wishes to talk about, but they are also used quite differently. Moreover, a definite description occurring in one and the same sentence may, on different occasions of its use, function in either way. The failure to deal with this duality of function obscures the genuine referring use of definite descriptions. The best known theories of definite descriptions, those of Russell and Strawson, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   747 citations  
  • Reasons as Evidence.Stephen Kearns & Daniel Star - 2009 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4:215-42.
    In this paper, we argue for a particular informative and unified analysis of normative reasons. According to this analysis, a fact F is a reason to act in a certain way just in case it is evidence that one ought to act in that way. Similarly, F is a reason to believe a certain proposition just in case it is evidence for the truth of this proposition. Putting the relatively uncontroversial claim about reasons for belief to one side, we present (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • The Unreality of Time.J. E. Mctaggart - 1908 - Mind 17:457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Investigations into Logical Deduction.Gerhard Gentzen - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (4):288 - 306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • Habits and Rituals.Raffaela Giovagnoli - 2018 - Open Information Science 2 (1):1-10.
    The aim of my contribution is to investigate the ground of habits and rituals; they are based on the same processes even though they have different functions depending on the context (personal or social). My discussion will mostly centered on the nature and function of rituals, as necessary practices in human social life (but also in animal life). After a brief introduction of different perspectives on the notions of “habit” and “ritual”, I propose an interpretation of rituals as collective activity, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Vagueness. [REVIEW]Roy A. Sorensen - 1994 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (2):483-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Pewna wersja definicji klasycznego pojęcia prawdy.Ludwik Borkowski - 1980 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 28 (1):119-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle on Deduction and Inferential Necessity.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2013 - Review of Metaphysics 67 (1):29-54.
    Aristotle’s Prior Analytics identifies deductions simpliciter with inferential necessity, so that a deduced conclusion is necessarily inferred from some premises. Modern logical reconstructions claim that inferential necessity in Aristotle corresponds to logical validity. However, this logical reconstruction fails on two accounts. First, logical validity does not highlight Aristotle’s distinction between inferential necessity and predicative necessity, meaning that the inferential necessity of a deduction is not of the same kind as the predicative necessity of a non‑deductive argument. Second, logical validity does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Paraconsistent logic.Graham Priest - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • The Value of Vagueness.Timothy Endicott - 2011 - In Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Language in the Law. Oxford University Press, Usa.
    How can it be valuable to use vagueness in a normative text? The effect is to make a vague norm, and vagueness seems repugnant to the very idea of making a norm. It leaves conduct (to some extent) unregulated, when the very idea of making a norm is to regulate conduct. A vague norm leaves the persons for whom the norm is valid with no guide to their conduct in some cases - and the point of a norm is to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Questions.Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stokhof - 2011 - In Johan van Benthem & Alice ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language. Elsevier. pp. 1059–1131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Diagram-Based Geometric Practice.Kenneth Manders - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press. pp. 65--79.
    This chapter provides a survey of issues about diagrams in traditional geometrical reasoning. After briefly refuting several common philosophical objections, and giving a sketch of diagram-based reasoning practice in Euclidean plane geometry, discussion focuses first on problems of diagram sensitivity, and then on the relationship between uniform treatment and geometrical generality. Here, one finds a balance between representationally enforced unresponsiveness (to differences among diagrams) and the intellectual agent's contribution to such unresponsiveness that is somewhat different from what one has come (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Q-consequence operation.Grzegorz Malinowski - 1990 - Reports on Mathematical Logic 24 (1):49--59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Possible world semantics for first order lp.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    First we have individual variables, as usual in first-order logics. (We do not have individual constants, but this is a minor point.) The propositional logic LP has justification constants, but in FOLP these are generalized to allow individual variables as arguments. Thus we have as justification constants c, c(x), c(x, y), . . . . Similarly LP has justification variables, but in FOLP these can be parametrized with individual variables p, p(x), p(x, y), . . . . To keep terminology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Weakly O-Minimal Structures and Some of Their Properties.B. Kulpeshov - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1511-1528.
    The main result of this paper is Theorem 3.1 which is a criterion for weak o-minimality of a linearly ordered structure in terms of realizations of 1-types. Here we also prove some other properties of weakly o-minimal structures. In particular, we characterize all weakly o-minimal linear orderings in the signature $\{<, =\}$. Moreover, we present a criterion for density of isolated types of a weakly o-minimal theory. Lastly, at the end of the paper we present some remarks on the Exchange (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Admissible Rules of Intuitionistic Propositional Logic.Rosalie Iemhoff - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):281-294.
    We present a basis for the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic. Thereby a conjecture by de Jongh and Visser is proved. We also present a proof system for the admissible rules, and give semantic criteria for admissibility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Understanding a Primitive Society.Peter Winch - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (4):307 - 324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Gunk, Topology and Measure.Frank Arntzenius - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The Analytic and the Synthetic.Hilary Putnam - 1962 - Critica 1 (2):109-113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Replies and Systematic Expositions.Rudolf Carnap - 1963 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), ¸ Iteschilpp:Prc. Open Court. pp. 859--1013.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • Paraconsistent Sensitivity Analysis for Bayesian Significance Tests.Julio Michael Stern - 2004 - Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 3171:134-143.
    In this paper, the notion of degree of inconsistency is introduced as a tool to evaluate the sensitivity of the Full Bayesian Significance Test (FBST) value of evidence with respect to changes in the prior or reference density. For that, both the definition of the FBST, a possibilistic approach to hypothesis testing based on Bayesian probability procedures, and the use of bilattice structures, as introduced by Ginsberg and Fitting, in paraconsistent logics, are reviewed. The computational and theoretical advantages of using (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Dialectic and Dialetheic.Graham Priest - 1989 - Science and Society 53 (4):388 - 415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Pluralism in Scientific Problem Solving. Why Inconsistency is No Big Deal.Diderik Batens - 2017 - Humana Mente 10 (32):149-177.
    Pluralism has many meanings. An assessment of the need for logical pluralism with respect to scientific knowledge requires insights in its domain of application. So first a specific form of epistemic pluralism will be defended. Knowledge turns out a patchwork of knowledge chunks. These serve descriptive as well as evaluative functions, may have competitors within the knowledge system, interact with each other, and display a characteristic dynamics caused by new information as well as by mutual readjustment. Logics play a role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Pluralism, Consistency Preservation, and Inconsistency Toleration.Otávio Bueno - 2017 - Humana Mente 10 (32):229-245.
    Scientific pluralism is the view according to which there is a plurality of scientific domains and of scientific theories, and these theories are empirically adequate relative to their own respective domains. Scientific monism is the view according to which there is a single domain to which all scientific theories apply. How are these views impacted by the presence of inconsistent scientific theories? There are consistency-preservation strategies and inconsistency-toleration strategies. Among the former, two prominent strategies can be articulated: Compartmentalization and Information (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Nearly every normal modal logic is paranormal.Joao Marcos - 2005 - Logique Et Analyse 48 (189-192):279-300.
    An overcomplete logic is a logic that ‘ceases to make the difference’: According to such a logic, all inferences hold independently of the nature of the statements involved. A negation-inconsistent logic is a logic having at least one model that satisfies both some statement and its negation. A negation-incomplete logic has at least one model according to which neither some statement nor its negation are satisfied. Paraconsistent logics are negation-inconsistent yet non-overcomplete; paracomplete logics are negation-incomplete yet non-overcomplete. A paranormal logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Realism and Dialetheism.Fred Kroon - 2004 - In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction. Clarendon Press. pp. 245–263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Oh the Algebra of Logic.C. S. Peirce - 1880 - American Journal of Mathematics 3 (1):15-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Towards a Computational Account of Inferentialist Meaning.Paul Piwek - 2014
    Both in formal and computational natural language semantics, the classical correspondence view of meaning – and, more specifically, the view that the meaning of a declarative sentence coincides with its truth conditions – is widely held. Truth (in the world or a situation) plays the role of the given, and meaning is analysed in terms of it. Both language and the world feature in this perspective on meaning, but language users are conspicuously absent. In contrast, the inferentialist semantics that Robert (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is the Liar sentence both true and false?Hartry Field - 2005 - In J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), Deflationism and Paradox. Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Searching the Arcane Origins of Fuzzy Logic.Angel Garrido - 2011 - BRAIN. Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience 2.
    ABSTRACT It is well-known that Artificial Intelligence requires Logic. But its Classical version shows too many insufficiencies. So, it is very necessary to introduce more sophisticated tools, as may be Fuzzy Logic, Modal Logic, Non-Monotonic Logic, and so on. When you are searching the possible precedent of such new ideas, we may found that they are not totally new, because some ancient thinkers have suggested many centuries ago similar concepts, certainly without adequate mathematical formulation, but in the same line: against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Relevance, Acceptability, and Sufficiency Today.J. Blair - 2007 - Anthropology and Philosophy 8 (1-2):33-48.
    In Logical Self-Defense , Johnson and I introduced the criteria of acceptability, relevance and sufficiency as appropriate for the evaluation of arguments in the sense of reasons offered in support of a claim. These three criteria have been widely adopted, but each has been subjected to a number of criticisms; and also 30 years of research have intervened. How do these criteria stand up today? In this paper I argue that they still have a place in argument analysis and evaluation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A Genetic Interpretation of Neo-Pythagorean Arithmetic.Ioannis M. Vandoulakis - 2010 - Oriens - Occidens 7:113-154.
    The style of arithmetic in the treatises the Neo-Pythagorean authors is strikingly different from that of the "Elements". Namely, it is characterised by the absence of proof in the Euclidean sense and a specific genetic approach to the construction of arithmetic that we are going to describe in our paper. Lack of mathematical sophistication has led certain historians to consider this type of mathematics as a feature of decadence of mathematics in this period [Tannery 1887; Heath 1921]. The alleged absence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Semi-Boolean algebras and their applications to intuitionistic logic with dual operations.Cecylia Rauszer - 1974 - Fundamenta Mathematicae 83:219-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Remarks on projective unifiers.Wojciech Dzik - 2011 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 40 (1/2):37-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Oppositions in a line segment.Alexandre Costa-Leite - 2018 - South American Journal of Logic 4 (1):185-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations