Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Science Without Numbers: A Defence of Nominalism.Hartry H. Field - 1980 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    Science Without Numbers caused a stir in 1980, with its bold nominalist approach to the philosophy of mathematics and science. It has been unavailable for twenty years and is now reissued in a revised edition with a substantial new preface presenting the author's current views and responses to the issues raised in subsequent debate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   581 citations  
  • Realism, Mathematics & Modality.Hartry H. Field - 1989 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   465 citations  
  • The nature of mathematical knowledge.Philip Kitcher - 1983 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues against the view that mathematical knowledge is a priori,contending that mathematics is an empirical science and develops historically,just as ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • Explanation and scientific understanding.Michael Friedman - 1974 - Journal of Philosophy 71 (1):5-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   607 citations  
  • Explanatory unification.Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (4):507-531.
    The official model of explanation proposed by the logical empiricists, the covering law model, is subject to familiar objections. The goal of the present paper is to explore an unofficial view of explanation which logical empiricists have sometimes suggested, the view of explanation as unification. I try to show that this view can be developed so as to provide insight into major episodes in the history of science, and that it can overcome some of the most serious difficulties besetting the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   665 citations  
  • Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world.Philip Kitcher - 1962 - In Philip Kitcher & Wesley C. Salmon, Scientific Explanation. Univ of Minnesota Pr. pp. 410-505.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   518 citations  
  • Realism, Mathematics, and Modality.Hartry Field - 1988 - Philosophical Topics 16 (1):57-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   460 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Scientific Explanation.P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (1):85-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   247 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice.Paolo Mancosu (ed.) - 2008 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    There is an urgent need in philosophy of mathematics for new approaches which pay closer attention to mathematical practice. This book will blaze the trail: it offers philosophical analyses of important characteristics of contemporary mathematics and of many aspects of mathematical activity which escape purely formal logical treatment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Systems of predicative analysis.Solomon Feferman - 1964 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 29 (1):1-30.
    This paper is divided into two parts. Part I provides a resumé of the evolution of the notion of predicativity. Part II describes our own work on the subject.Part I§1. Conceptions of sets.Statements about sets lie at the heart of most modern attempts to systematize all (or, at least, all known) mathematics. Technical and philosophical discussions concerning such systematizations and the underlying conceptions have thus occupied a considerable portion of the literature on the foundations of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Explanation, conjunction, and unification.Philip Kitcher - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (8):207-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of the aforementioned areas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Unifying Scientific Theories.Margaret Morrison - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1097-1102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's Posterior Analytics.Jonathan Barnes - 1978 - Mind 87 (345):128-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's Posterior Analytics.Jonathan Barnes - 1977 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 31 (2):316-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Explanation in Mathematics.Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - In Ed Zalta, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The philosophical analysis of mathematical explanations concerns itself with two different, although connected, areas of investigation. The first area addresses the problem of whether mathematics can play an explanatory role in the natural and social sciences. The second deals with the problem of whether mathematical explanations occur within mathematics itself. Accordingly, this entry surveys the contributions to both areas, it shows their relevance to the history of philosophy and science, it articulates their connection, and points to the philosophical pay-offs to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Mathematical explanation: Why it matters.Paolo Mancosu - 2008 - In The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 134--149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Purity of Methods.Michael Detlefsen & Andrew Arana - 2011 - Philosophers' Imprint 11.
    Throughout history, mathematicians have expressed preference for solutions to problems that avoid introducing concepts that are in one sense or another “foreign” or “alien” to the problem under investigation. This preference for “purity” (which German writers commonly referred to as “methoden Reinheit”) has taken various forms. It has also been persistent. This notwithstanding, it has not been analyzed at even a basic philosophical level. In this paper we give a basic analysis of one conception of purity—what we call topical purity—and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Aristotle on Kind‐Crossing.Philipp Steinkrüger - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 54:107-158.
    This paper concerns Aristotle's kind‐crossing prohibition. My aim is twofold. I argue that the traditional accounts of the prohibition are subject to serious internal difficulties and should be questioned. According to these accounts, Aristotle's prohibition is based on the individuation of scientific disciplines and the general kind that a discipline is about, and it says that scientific demonstrations must not cross from one discipline, and corresponding kind, to another. I propose a very different account of the prohibition. The prohibition is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Mathematical explanation: Problems and prospects.Paolo Mancosu - 2001 - Topoi 20 (1):97-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • What does it take to prove fermat's last theorem? Grothendieck and the logic of number theory.Colin McLarty - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):359-377.
    This paper explores the set theoretic assumptions used in the current published proof of Fermat's Last Theorem, how these assumptions figure in the methods Wiles uses, and the currently known prospects for a proof using weaker assumptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Why do mathematicians re-prove theorems?John W. Dawson Jr - 2006 - Philosophia Mathematica 14 (3):269-286.
    From ancient times to the present, the discovery and presentation of new proofs of previously established theorems has been a salient feature of mathematical practice. Why? What purposes are served by such endeavors? And how do mathematicians judge whether two proofs of the same theorem are essentially different? Consideration of such questions illuminates the roles that proofs play in the validation and communication of mathematical knowledge and raises issues that have yet to be resolved by mathematical logicians. The Appendix, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Explanation in metaphysics and Bolzano’s theory of ground and consequence.Arianna Betti - 2010 - Logique Et Analyse 211:281-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • On Interpretations of Arithmetic and Set Theory.Richard Kaye & Tin Lok Wong - 2007 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 48 (4):497-510.
    This paper starts by investigating Ackermann's interpretation of finite set theory in the natural numbers. We give a formal version of this interpretation from Peano arithmetic (PA) to Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the infinity axiom negated (ZF−inf) and provide an inverse interpretation going the other way. In particular, we emphasize the precise axiomatization of our set theory that is required and point out the necessity of the axiom of transitive containment or (equivalently) the axiom scheme of ∈-induction. This clarifies the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • On the alleged simplicity of impure proof.Andrew Arana - 2017 - In Roman Kossak & Philip Ording, Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts. Springer. pp. 207-226.
    Roughly, a proof of a theorem, is “pure” if it draws only on what is “close” or “intrinsic” to that theorem. Mathematicians employ a variety of terms to identify pure proofs, saying that a pure proof is one that avoids what is “extrinsic,” “extraneous,” “distant,” “remote,” “alien,” or “foreign” to the problem or theorem under investigation. In the background of these attributions is the view that there is a distance measure (or a variety of such measures) between mathematical statements and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Bolzano's ideal of algebraic analysis.Philip Kitcher - 1975 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 6 (3):229-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Purity as an ideal of proof.Michael Detlefsen - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu, The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 179-197.
    Various ideals of purity are surveyed and discussed. These include the classical Aristotelian ideal, as well as certain neo-classical and contemporary ideals. The focus is on a type of purity ideal I call topical purity. This is purity which emphasizes a certain symmetry between the conceptual resources used to prove a theorem and those needed for the clarification of its content. The basic idea is that the resources of proof ought ideally to be restricted to those which determine its content.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Reflections on the purity of method in Hilbert's Grundlagen der Geometrie.Michael Hallett - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu, The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Number theory and elementary arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad - 2003 - Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3):257-284.
    is a fragment of first-order aritlimetic so weak that it cannot prove the totality of an iterated exponential fimction. Surprisingly, however, the theory is remarkably robust. I will discuss formal results that show that many theorems of number theory and combinatorics are derivable in elementary arithmetic, and try to place these results in a broader philosophical context.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Beyond unification.Johannes Hafner & Paolo Mancosu - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu, The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 151--178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On the Depth of Szemeredi's Theorem.Andrew Arana - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (2):163-176.
    Many mathematicians have cited depth as an important value in their research. However, there is no single widely accepted account of mathematical depth. This article is an attempt to bridge this gap. The strategy is to begin with a discussion of Szemerédi's theorem, which says that each subset of the natural numbers that is sufficiently dense contains an arithmetical progression of arbitrary length. This theorem has been judged deep by many mathematicians, and so makes for a good case on which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Bolzano and Cournot on mathematical explanation / Bolzano et Cournot à propos de l'explication mathématique.Paolo Mancosu - 1999 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 52 (3):429-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Abstract.[author unknown] - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (4):447-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • The metamathematics of ergodic theory.Jeremy Avigad - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):64-76.
    The metamathematical tradition, tracing back to Hilbert, employs syntactic modeling to study the methods of contemporary mathematics. A central goal has been, in particular, to explore the extent to which infinitary methods can be understood in computational or otherwise explicit terms. Ergodic theory provides rich opportunities for such analysis. Although the field has its origins in seventeenth century dynamics and nineteenth century statistical mechanics, it employs infinitary, nonconstructive, and structural methods that are characteristically modern. At the same time, computational concerns (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Arithmetical truth and hidden higher-order concepts.Daniel Isaacson - 1987 - In Logic Colloquium '85: Proceedings of the Colloquium held in Orsay, France July 1985 (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Vol. 122.). Amsterdam, New York, Oxford, Tokyo: North-Holland. pp. 147-169.
    The incompleteness of formal systems for arithmetic has been a recognized fact of mathematics. The term “incompleteness” suggests that the formal system in question fails to offer a deduction which it ought to. This chapter focuses on the status of a formal system, Peano Arithmetic, and explores a viewpoint on which Peano Arithmetic occupies an intrinsic, conceptually well-defined region of arithmetical truth. The idea is that it consists of those truths which can be perceived directly from the purely arithmetical content (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Metastability in the Furstenberg-Zimmer Tower.Jeremy Avigad & Henry Towsner - unknown
    According to the Furstenberg-Zimmer structure theorem, every measure-preserving system has a maximal distal factor, and is weak mixing relative to that factor. Furstenberg and Katznelson used this structural analysis of measure-preserving systems to provide a perspicuous proof of Szemer\'edi's theorem. Beleznay and Foreman showed that, in general, the transfinite construction of the maximal distal factor of a separable measure-preserving system can extend arbitrarily far into the countable ordinals. Here we show that the Furstenberg-Katznelson proof does not require the full strength (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Abstract.[author unknown] - 1999 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 9 (1):3-6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der Allgemeinen Mengenlehre.Wilhelm Ackerman - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):167-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations