Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The bayesians and the Raven paradox.Jerrold L. Aronson - 1989 - Noûs 23 (2):221-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The paradoxes of confirmation.H. G. Alexander - 1958 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 9 (35):227-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Laws and symmetry.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Metaphysicians speak of laws of nature in terms of necessity and universality; scientists, in terms of symmetry and invariance. In this book van Fraassen argues that no metaphysical account of laws can succeed. He analyzes and rejects the arguments that there are laws of nature, or that we must believe there are, and argues that we should disregard the idea of law as an adequate clue to science. After exploring what this means for general epistemology, the author develops the empiricist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   815 citations  
  • The Principles of Scientific Thinking.[author unknown] - 1972 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (1):69-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Belief and the Will.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (5):235-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   344 citations  
  • Belief and the will.Bas C. van Fraassen - 2010 - In Antony Eagle (ed.), Philosophy of Probability: Contemporary Readings. New York: Routledge. pp. 235-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance.David K. Lewis - 2010 - In Antony Eagle (ed.), Philosophy of Probability: Contemporary Readings. New York: Routledge. pp. 263-293.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   594 citations  
  • Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach.Peter Urbach & Colin Howson - 1993 - Chicago: Open Court. Edited by Peter Urbach.
    Scientific reasoning is—and ought to be—conducted in accordance with the axioms of probability. This Bayesian view—so called because of the central role it accords to a theorem first proved by Thomas Bayes in the late eighteenth ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   567 citations  
  • Fact, Fiction, and Forecast.Nelson Goodman - 1965 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    In his new foreword to this edition, Hilary Putnam forcefully rejects these nativist claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1129 citations  
  • The structure of scientific inference.Mary B. Hesse - 1974 - [London]: Macmillan.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Inference to the Best Explanation.Peter Lipton - 1991 - New York: Routledge.
    "How do we go about weighing evidence, testing hypotheses and making inferences? According to the model of 'inference to the Best explanation', we work out what to inter from the evidence by thinking about what would actually explain that evidence, and we take the ability of a hypothesis to explain the evidence as a sign that the hypothesis is correct. In inference to the Best Explanation, Peter Lipton gives this important and influential idea the development and assessment it deserves." "The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   330 citations  
  • Critical review: Horwich on the ravens, projectability and induction. [REVIEW]James Woodward - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 47 (3):409 - 428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the confirmation paradox.P. R. Wilson - 1964 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15 (59):196-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Consequences and confirmation.Frederick L. Will - 1966 - Philosophical Review 75 (1):34-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A new approach to the confirmation paradox.P. R. Wilson - 1964 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 42 (3):393 – 401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Paradoxes of Confirmation.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1965 - Theoria 31 (3):255-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Selective confirmation and the Ravens.R. H. Vincent - 1975 - Dialogue 14 (1):3-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the sirens.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 77 (1):7-37.
    This is surely a bit of Socrates' famous irony. He draws the analogy to explain how his friends should regard poetry as they regretfully banish it from the ideal state. But lovers were no more sensible then than they are now. The advice to banish poetry, undermined already by Plato's own delight and skill in drama, is perhaps undermined still further by this evocation of a 'sensible' lover who counts love so well lost. Yet Socrates' image is one of avowed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Dinnaga and the Raven paradox.Joerg Tuske - 1998 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 26 (5):387-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An Introduction to Confirmation Theory.Richard Swinburne - 1973 - Methuen.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Hempel's Paradox.D. Stove - 1966 - Dialogue 4 (4):444-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Confirmation, paradoxes, and possible worlds.Shelley Stillwell - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):19-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nomological necessity and the paradoxes of confirmation.Brian Skyrms - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (3):230-249.
    Some of the concerns which motivate attempts to provide a philosophical reduction of nomological necessity are briefly introduced in I. In II, Hempel's treatment of the paradoxes is contrasted with a position which holds that nomological necessity is a pragmatic dimension of laws of nature, and that this pragmatic dimension is of such a type that it prevents laws of nature from contraposing. Such a position is, however, untenable unless (i) the sense of 'pragmatics' at issue is specified, and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Anatomy of Inquiry: Philosophical Studies in the Theory of Science. [REVIEW]S. F. Barker - 1966 - Journal of Philosophy 63 (12):358-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Selective Confirmation and the Ravens: A Reply to Foster.Israel Scheffler & Nelson Goodman - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (3):78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Paradox and projection.Robert Schwartz - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (2):245-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Confirmation by observation and the paradox of the ravens.Judith Schoenberg - 1964 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15 (59):200-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paradoxes.R. M. Sainsbury - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2):455-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Inference, Method and Decision.Ronald N. Giere - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (3):491-493.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Does the philosophy of induction rest on a mistake?R. D. Rosenkrantz - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (2):78-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (C) instances, the relevance criterion, and the paradoxes of confirmation.Phillip J. Rody - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (2):289-302.
    The Relevance Criterion of confirmation gained prominence as the underlying principle of the class-size approach (CSA) to Hempel's paradoxes of confirmation. The CSA, however, yields counter-intuitive results for (c) instances, and this failing cast serious doubt on the acceptability of the Relevance Criterion. In this paper an attempt is made to rescue the Relevance Criterion from this embarrassment. This is done by incorporating that criterion into a new resolution of the paradoxes, a resolution based on a theory of selective confirmation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An Introduction to Confirmation Theory.Mark Pastin & Richard Swinburne - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (1):122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Foundations of Geometry and Induction.Jean Nicod - 1930 - Humana Mente 5 (19):455-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Mr. Wilson on the paradox of confirmation.G. Nerlich - 1964 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 42 (3):401 – 405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Laws and Symmetry.Adam Morton & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (3):408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Goodman on the ravens.Sidney Morgenbesser - 1962 - Journal of Philosophy 59 (18):493-495.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inference, Method and Decision.David Miller - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Inductive logic and the ravens paradox.Patrick Maher - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (1):50-70.
    Hempel's paradox of the ravens arises from the inconsistency of three prima facie plausible principles of confirmation. This paper uses Carnapian inductive logic to (a) identify which of the principles is false, (b) give insight into why this principle is false, and (c) identify a true principle that is sufficiently similar to the false one that failure to distinguish the two might explain why the false principle is prima facie plausible. This solution to the paradox is compared with a variety (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Fact, Fiction, and Forecast.The Philosophy of Nature.Edward H. Madden, Nelson Goodman & Andrew G. Van Melsen - 1955 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16 (2):271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   308 citations  
  • The paradox of confirmation.J. L. Mackie - 1962 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 13 (52):265-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The paradox of confirmation.J. L. Mackie - 1963 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 13 (52):265-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Précis of Inference to the Best Explanation, 2 nd Edition.Peter Lipton - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2):421-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   564 citations  
  • Inference to the Best Explanation.Peter Lipton - 1991 - London and New York: Routledge/Taylor and Francis Group.
    How do we go about weighing evidence, testing hypotheses, and making inferences? The model of " inference to the best explanation " -- that we infer the hypothesis that would, if correct, provide the best explanation of the available evidence--offers a compelling account of inferences both in science and in ordinary life. Widely cited by epistemologists and philosophers of science, IBE has nonetheless remained little more than a slogan. Now this influential work has been thoroughly revised and updated, and features (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   589 citations  
  • Humean Supervenience Debugged.David Lewis - 1994 - Mind 103 (412):473--490.
    Tn this paper I explore and to an extent defend HS. The main philosophical challenges to HS come from philosophical views that say that nomic concepts-laws, chance, and causation-denote features of the world that fail to supervene on non-nomic features. Lewis rejects these views and has labored mightily to construct HS accounts of nomic concepts. His account of laws is fundamental to his program, since his accounts of the other nomic notions rely on it. Recently, a number of philosophers have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   605 citations  
  • The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory.Isaac Levi & James M. Joyce - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (7):387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory.James M. Joyce - 1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book defends the view that any adequate account of rational decision making must take a decision maker's beliefs about causal relations into account. The early chapters of the book introduce the non-specialist to the rudiments of expected utility theory. The major technical advance offered by the book is a 'representation theorem' that shows that both causal decision theory and its main rival, Richard Jeffrey's logic of decision, are both instances of a more general conditional decision theory. The book solves (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • A brief guide to the work of Carl Gustav Hempel.Richard Jeffrey - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (1):3 - 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The resolution of the confirmation paradox.R. Jardine - 1965 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):359 – 368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The foundations of causal decision theory. [REVIEW]Mirek Janusz - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):296-300.
    This book makes a significant contribution to the standard decision theory, that is, the theory of choice built around the principle of maximizing expected utility, both to its causal version and to the more traditional noncausal approach. The author’s success in clarifying the foundations of the standard decision theory in general, and causal decision theory in particular, also makes the book uniquely suitable for a person whose research in philosophy has led her to want to learn about contemporary decision theory. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • The solution of Hempel's Raven paradox in Rudolf Carnap's system of inductive logic.Jürgen Humburg - 1986 - Erkenntnis 24 (1):57 - 72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations