Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Semi-honest subrecursive degrees and the collection rule in arithmetic.Andrés Cordón-Franco & F. Félix Lara-Martín - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (1):163-180.
    By a result of L.D. Beklemishev, the hierarchy of nested applications of the $$\Sigma _1$$ -collection rule over any $$\Pi _2$$ -axiomatizable base theory extending Elementary Arithmetic collapses to its first level. We prove that this result cannot in general be extended to base theories of arbitrary quantifier complexity. In fact, given any recursively enumerable set of true $$\Pi _2$$ -sentences, S, we construct a sound $$(\Sigma _2 \! \vee \! \Pi _2)$$ -axiomatized theory T extending S such that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflection algebras and conservation results for theories of iterated truth.Lev D. Beklemishev & Fedor N. Pakhomov - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (5):103093.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Cognitive Projects and the Trustworthiness of Positive Truth.Matteo Zicchetti - 2022 - Erkenntnis (8).
    The aim of this paper is twofold: first, I provide a cluster of theories of truth in classical logic that is (internally) consistent with global reflection principles: the theories of positive truth (and falsity). After that, I analyse the _epistemic value_ of such theories. I do so employing the framework of cognitive projects introduced by Wright (Proc Aristot Soc 78:167–245, 2004), and employed—in the context of theories of truth—by Fischer et al. (Noûs 2019. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12292 ). In particular, I will argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth is Simple.Leon Horsten & Graham E. Leigh - 2016 - Mind:fzv184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On the Optimality of Conservation Results for Local Reflection in Arithmetic.A. Cordón-Franco, A. Fernández-Margarit & F. F. Lara-Martín - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (4):1025-1035.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some results on cut-elimination, provable well-orderings, induction and reflection.Toshiyasu Arai - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 95 (1-3):93-184.
    We gather the following miscellaneous results in proof theory from the attic.1. 1. A provably well-founded elementary ordering admits an elementary order preserving map.2. 2. A simple proof of an elementary bound for cut elimination in propositional calculus and its applications to separation problem in relativized bounded arithmetic below S21.3. 3. Equivalents for Bar Induction, e.g., reflection schema for ω logic.4. 4. Direct computations in an equational calculus PRE and a decidability problem for provable inequations in PRE.5. 5. Intuitionistic fixed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Paris-Harrington principles, reflection principles and transfinite induction up to epsilon 0.Reijiro Kurata - 1986 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 31:237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Too naturalist and not naturalist enough: Reply to Horsten.Luca Incurvati - 2008 - Erkenntnis 69 (2):261 - 274.
    Leon Horsten has recently claimed that the class of mathematical truths coincides with the class of theorems of ZFC. I argue that the naturalistic character of Horsten’s proposal undermines his contention that this claim constitutes an analogue of a thesis that Daniel Isaacson has advanced for PA. I argue, moreover, that Horsten’s defence of his claim against an obvious objection makes use of a distinction which is not available to him given his naturalistic approach. I suggest a way out of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Axiomatic theories of truth.Volker Halbach - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Definitional and axiomatic theories of truth -- Objects of truth -- Tarski -- Truth and set theory -- Technical preliminaries -- Comparing axiomatic theories of truth -- Disquotation -- Classical compositional truth -- Hierarchies -- Typed and type-free theories of truth -- Reasons against typing -- Axioms and rules -- Axioms for type-free truth -- Classical symmetric truth -- Kripke-Feferman -- Axiomatizing Kripke's theory in partial logic -- Grounded truth -- Alternative evaluation schemata -- Disquotation -- Classical logic -- Deflationism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Algorithmic information theory and undecidability.Panu Raatikainen - 2000 - Synthese 123 (2):217-225.
    Chaitin’s incompleteness result related to random reals and the halting probability has been advertised as the ultimate and the strongest possible version of the incompleteness and undecidability theorems. It is argued that such claims are exaggerations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Algorithmic information theory.Michiel van Lambalgen - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1389-1400.
    We present a critical discussion of the claim (most forcefully propounded by Chaitin) that algorithmic information theory sheds new light on Godel's first incompleteness theorem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Iterated reflection principles and the ω-rule.Ulf R. Schmerl - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):721-733.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On interpreting Chaitin's incompleteness theorem.Panu Raatikainen - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (6):569-586.
    The aim of this paper is to comprehensively question the validity of the standard way of interpreting Chaitin's famous incompleteness theorem, which says that for every formalized theory of arithmetic there is a finite constant c such that the theory in question cannot prove any particular number to have Kolmogorov complexity larger than c. The received interpretation of theorem claims that the limiting constant is determined by the complexity of the theory itself, which is assumed to be good measure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A survey of proof theory.G. Kreisel - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (3):321-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • On the no-counterexample interpretation.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1491-1511.
    In [15], [16] G. Kreisel introduced the no-counterexample interpretation (n.c.i.) of Peano arithmetic. In particular he proved, using a complicated ε-substitution method (due to W. Ackermann), that for every theorem A (A prenex) of first-order Peano arithmetic PA one can find ordinal recursive functionals Φ A of order type 0 which realize the Herbrand normal form A H of A. Subsequently more perspicuous proofs of this fact via functional interpretation (combined with normalization) and cut-elimination were found. These proofs however do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The relation of a to prov ⌜a ⌝ in the lindenbaum sentence algebra.C. F. Kent - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):295-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Remarks on weak notions of saturation in models of peano arithmetic.Matt Kaufmann & James H. Schmerl - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):129-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Truth, reflection, and hierarchies.Michael Glanzberg - 2005 - Synthese 142 (3):289 - 315.
    A common objection to hierarchical approaches to truth is that they fragment the concept of truth. This paper defends hierarchical approaches in general against the objection of fragmentation. It argues that the fragmentation required is familiar and unprob-lematic, via a comparison with mathematical proof. Furthermore, it offers an explanation of the source and nature of the fragmentation of truth. Fragmentation arises because the concept exhibits a kind of failure of closure under reflection. This paper offers a more precise characterization of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Provability: The emergence of a mathematical modality.George Boolos & Giovanni Sambin - 1991 - Studia Logica 50 (1):1 - 23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Bimodal logics for extensions of arithmetical theories.Lev D. Beklemishev - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1):91-124.
    We characterize the bimodal provability logics for certain natural (classes of) pairs of recursively enumerable theories, mostly related to fragments of arithmetic. For example, we shall give axiomatizations, decision procedures, and introduce natural Kripke semantics for the provability logics of (IΔ 0 + EXP, PRA); (PRA, IΣ 1 ); (IΣ m , IΣ n ) for $1 \leq m etc. For the case of finitely axiomatized extensions of theories these results are extended to modal logics with propositional constants.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Informal provability and dialetheism.Pawel Pawlowski & Rafal Urbaniak - 2023 - Theoria 89 (2):204-215.
    According to the dialetheist argument from the inconsistency of informal mathematics, the informal version of the Gödelian argument leads us to a true contradiction. On one hand, the dialetheist argues, we can prove that there is a mathematical claim that is neither provable nor refutable in informal mathematics. On the other, the proof of its unprovability is given in informal mathematics and proves that very sentence. We argue that the argument fails, because it relies on the unjustified and unlikely assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Local reflection, definable elements and 1-provability.Evgeny Kolmakov - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (7-8):979-996.
    In this note we study several topics related to the schema of local reflection \\) and its partial and relativized variants. Firstly, we introduce the principle of uniform reflection with \-definable parameters, establish its relationship with relativized local reflection principles and corresponding versions of induction with definable parameters. Using this schema we give a new model-theoretic proof of the \-conservativity of uniform \-reflection over relativized local \-reflection. We also study the proof-theoretic strength of Feferman’s theorem, i.e., the assertion of 1-provability (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Generalizations of gödel’s incompleteness theorems for ∑ N-definable theories of arithmetic.Makoto Kikuchi & Taishi Kurahashi - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):603-616.
    It is well known that Gödel’s incompleteness theorems hold for ∑1-definable theories containing Peano arithmetic. We generalize Gödel’s incompleteness theorems for arithmetically definable theories. First, we prove that every ∑n+1-definable ∑n-sound theory is incomplete. Secondly, we generalize and improve Jeroslow and Hájek’s results. That is, we prove that every consistent theory having ∏n+1set of theorems has a true but unprovable ∏nsentence. Lastly, we prove that no ∑n+1-definable ∑n-sound theory can prove its own ∑n-soundness. These three results are generalizations of Rosser’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Slow reflection.Anton Freund - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (12):2103-2128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Notes on local reflection principles.Lev Beklemishev - 1997 - Theoria 63 (3):139-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Characterizations of ordinal analysis.James Walsh - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (4):103230.
    Ordinal analysis is a research program wherein recursive ordinals are assigned to axiomatic theories. According to conventional wisdom, ordinal analysis measures the strength of theories. Yet what is the attendant notion of strength? In this paper we present abstract characterizations of ordinal analysis that address this question. -/- First, we characterize ordinal analysis as a partition of $\Sigma^1_1$-definable and $\Pi^1_1$-sound theories, namely, the partition whereby two theories are equivalent if they have the same proof-theoretic ordinal. We show that no equivalence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reducing omega-model reflection to iterated syntactic reflection.Fedor Pakhomov & James Walsh - 2021 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (2).
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Volume 23, Issue 02, August 2023. In mathematical logic there are two seemingly distinct kinds of principles called “reflection principles.” Semantic reflection principles assert that if a formula holds in the whole universe, then it holds in a set-sized model. Syntactic reflection principles assert that every provable sentence from some complexity class is true. In this paper, we study connections between these two kinds of reflection principles in the setting of second-order arithmetic. We prove that, for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflection ranks and ordinal analysis.Fedor Pakhomov & James Walsh - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (4):1350-1384.
    It is well-known that natural axiomatic theories are well-ordered by consistency strength. However, it is possible to construct descending chains of artificial theories with respect to consistency strength. We provide an explanation of this well-orderedness phenomenon by studying a coarsening of the consistency strength order, namely, the$\Pi ^1_1$reflection strength order. We prove that there are no descending sequences of$\Pi ^1_1$sound extensions of$\mathsf {ACA}_0$in this ordering. Accordingly, we can attach a rank in this order, which we call reflection rank, to any$\Pi (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Arithmetical Reflection and the Provability of Soundness.Walter Dean - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1):31-64.
    Proof-theoretic reflection principles are schemas which attempt to express the soundness of arithmetical theories within their own language, e.g., ${\mathtt{{Prov}_{\mathsf {PA}} \rightarrow \varphi }}$ can be understood to assert that any statement provable in Peano arithmetic is true. It has been repeatedly suggested that justification for such principles follows directly from acceptance of an arithmetical theory $\mathsf {T}$ or indirectly in virtue of their derivability in certain truth-theoretic extensions thereof. This paper challenges this consensus by exploring relationships between reflection principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Iterated local reflection versus iterated consistency.Lev Beklemishev - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 75 (1-2):25-48.
    For “natural enough” systems of ordinal notation we show that α times iterated local reflection schema over a sufficiently strong arithmetic T proves the same Π 1 0 -sentences as ω α times iterated consistency. A corollary is that the two hierarchies catch up modulo relative interpretability exactly at ε-numbers. We also derive the following more general “mixed” formulas estimating the consistency strength of iterated local reflection: for all ordinals α ⩾ 1 and all β, β ≡ Π 1 0 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Induction rules, reflection principles, and provably recursive functions.Lev D. Beklemishev - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (3):193-242.
    A well-known result states that, over basic Kalmar elementary arithmetic EA, the induction schema for ∑n formulas is equivalent to the uniform reflection principle for ∑n + 1 formulas . We show that fragments of arithmetic axiomatized by various forms of induction rules admit a precise axiomatization in terms of reflection principles as well. Thus, the closure of EA under the induction rule for ∑n formulas is equivalent to ω times iterated ∑n reflection principle. Moreover, for k < ω, k (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • My route to arithmetization.Solomon Feferman - 1997 - Theoria 63 (3):168-181.
    I had the pleasure of renewing my acquaintance with Per Lindström at the meeting of the Seventh Scandinavian Logic Symposium, held in Uppsala in August 1996. There at lunch one day, Per said he had long been curious about the development of some of the ideas in my paper [1960] on the arithmetization of metamathematics. In particular, I had used the construction of a non-standard definition !* of the set of axioms of P (Peano Arithmetic) to show that P + (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A note on fragments of uniform reflection in second order arithmetic.Emanuele Frittaion - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (3):451-465.
    We consider fragments of uniform reflection for formulas in the analytic hierarchy over theories of second order arithmetic. The main result is that for any second order arithmetic theory $T_0$ extending $\mathsf {RCA}_0$ and axiomatizable by a $\Pi ^1_{k+2}$ sentence, and for any $n\geq k+1$, $$\begin{align*}T_0+ \mathrm{RFN}_{\varPi^1_{n+2}} \ = \ T_0 + \mathrm{TI}_{\varPi^1_n}, \end{align*}$$ $$\begin{align*}T_0+ \mathrm{RFN}_{\varSigma^1_{n+1}} \ = \ T_0+ \mathrm{TI}_{\varPi^1_n}^{-}, \end{align*}$$ where T is $T_0$ augmented with full induction, and $\mathrm {TI}_{\varPi ^1_n}^{-}$ denotes the schema of transfinite induction up (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic of informal provability with truth values.Pawel Pawlowski & Rafal Urbaniak - 2023 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 31 (1):172-193.
    Classical logic of formal provability includes Löb’s theorem, but not reflection. In contrast, intuitions about the inferential behavior of informal provability (in informal mathematics) seem to invalidate Löb’s theorem and validate reflection (after all, the intuition is, whatever mathematicians prove holds!). We employ a non-deterministic many-valued semantics and develop a modal logic T-BAT of an informal provability operator, which indeed does validate reflection and invalidates Löb’s theorem. We study its properties and its relation to known provability-related paradoxical arguments. We also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Disquotation and Infinite Conjunctions.Thomas Schindler & Lavinia Picollo - 2017 - Erkenntnis 83 (5):899-928.
    One of the main logical functions of the truth predicate is to enable us to express so-called ‘infinite conjunctions’. Several authors claim that the truth predicate can serve this function only if it is fully disquotational, which leads to triviality in classical logic. As a consequence, many have concluded that classical logic should be rejected. The purpose of this paper is threefold. First, we consider two accounts available in the literature of what it means to express infinite conjunctions with a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On axiom schemes for T-provably $${\Delta_{1}}$$ Δ 1 formulas.A. Cordón-Franco, A. Fernández-Margarit & F. F. Lara-Martín - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (3):327-349.
    This paper investigates the status of the fragments of Peano Arithmetic obtained by restricting induction, collection and least number axiom schemes to formulas which are $${\Delta_1}$$ provably in an arithmetic theory T. In particular, we determine the provably total computable functions of this kind of theories. As an application, we obtain a reduction of the problem whether $${I\Delta_0 + \neg \mathit{exp}}$$ implies $${B\Sigma_1}$$ to a purely recursion-theoretic question.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Subsystems of true arithmetic and hierarchies of functions.Z. Ratajczyk - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 64 (2):95-152.
    Ratajczyk, Z., Subsystems of true arithmetic and hierarchies of functions, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 64 95–152. The combinatorial method coming from the study of combinatorial sentences independent of PA is developed. Basing on this method we present the detailed analysis of provably recursive functions associated with higher levels of transfinite induction, I, and analyze combinatorial sentences independent of I. Our treatment of combinatorial sentences differs from the one given by McAloon [18] and gives more natural sentences. The same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A note on applicability of the incompleteness theorem to human mind.Pavel Pudlák - 1999 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 96 (1-3):335-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Remarks on Herbrand normal forms and Herbrand realizations.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 1992 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (5):305-317.
    LetA H be the Herbrand normal form ofA andA H,D a Herbrand realization ofA H. We showThere is an example of an (open) theory ℐ+ with function parameters such that for someA not containing function parameters Similar for first order theories ℐ+ if the index functions used in definingA H are permitted to occur in instances of non-logical axiom schemata of ℐ, i.e. for suitable ℐ,A In fact, in (1) we can take for ℐ+ the fragment (Σ 1 0 -IA)+ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Axiomatization of provable n-provability.Evgeny Kolmakov & Lev Beklemishev - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (2):849-869.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Paradox of the Knower revisited.Walter Dean & Hidenori Kurokawa - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (1):199-224.
    The Paradox of the Knower was originally presented by Kaplan and Montague [26] as a puzzle about the everyday notion of knowledge in the face of self-reference. The paradox shows that any theory extending Robinson arithmetic with a predicate K satisfying the factivity axiom K → A as well as a few other epistemically plausible principles is inconsistent. After surveying the background of the paradox, we will focus on a recent debate about the role of epistemic closure principles in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Predicativity through transfinite reflection.Andrés Cordón-Franco, David Fernández-Duque, Joost J. Joosten & Francisco Félix Lara-martín - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (3):787-808.
    Let T be a second-order arithmetical theory, Λ a well-order, λ < Λ and X ⊆ ℕ. We use $[\lambda |X]_T^{\rm{\Lambda }}\varphi$ as a formalization of “φ is provable from T and an oracle for the set X, using ω-rules of nesting depth at most λ”.For a set of formulas Γ, define predicative oracle reflection for T over Γ ) to be the schema that asserts that, if X ⊆ ℕ, Λ is a well-order and φ ∈ Γ, then$$\forall \,\lambda (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unifying the model theory of first-order and second-order arithmetic via WKL 0 ⁎.Ali Enayat & Tin Lok Wong - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (6):1247-1283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Henkin sentences and local reflection principles for Rosser provability.Taishi Kurahashi - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (2):73-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Herbrand-analysen zweier beweise Des satzes Von Roth: Polynomiale anzahlschranken.H. Luckhardt - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):234-263.
    A previously unexplored method, combining logical and mathematical elements, is shown to yield substantial numerical improvements in the area of Diophantine approximations. Kreisel illustrated the method abstractly by noting that effective bounds on the number of elements are ensured if Herbrand terms from ineffective proofs of Σ 2 -finiteness theorems satisfy certain simple growth conditions. Here several efficient growth conditions for the same purpose are presented that are actually satisfied in practice, in particular, by the proofs of Roth's theorem due (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Gödel's Second incompleteness theorem for Q.A. Bezboruah & J. C. Shepherdson - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (2):503-512.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A Mathematical Commitment Without Computational Strength.Anton Freund - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (4):880-906.
    We present a new manifestation of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem and discuss its foundational significance, in particular with respect to Hilbert’s program. Specifically, we consider a proper extension of Peano arithmetic ( $\mathbf {PA}$ ) by a mathematically meaningful axiom scheme that consists of $\Sigma ^0_2$ -sentences. These sentences assert that each computably enumerable ( $\Sigma ^0_1$ -definable without parameters) property of finite binary trees has a finite basis. Since this fact entails the existence of polynomial time algorithms, it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kripke models and the intuitionistic theory of species.D. H. J. de Jongh - 1976 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Self-Reference in Arithmetic II.Volker Halbach & Albert Visser - 2014 - Review of Symbolic Logic 7 (4):692-712.
    In this sequel toSelf-reference in arithmetic Iwe continue our discussion of the question: What does it mean for a sentence of arithmetic to ascribe to itself a property? We investigate how the properties of the supposedly self-referential sentences depend on the chosen coding, the formulae expressing the properties and the way a fixed point for the expressing formulae are obtained. In this second part we look at some further examples. In particular, we study sentences apparently expressing their Rosser-provability, their own${\rm{\Sigma (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On the No-Counterexample Interpretation.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1491-1511.
    In [15], [16] G. Kreisel introduced the no-counterexample interpretation (n.c.i.) of Peano arithmetic. In particular he proved, using a complicated ε-substitution method (due to W. Ackermann), that for every theoremA(Aprenex) of first-order Peano arithmeticPAone can find ordinal recursive functionalsof order type < ε0which realize the Herbrand normal formAHofA.Subsequently more perspicuous proofs of this fact via functional interpretation (combined with normalization) and cut-elimination were found. These proofs however do not carry out the no-counterexample interpretation as alocalproof interpretation and don't respect the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations